Havard Journal of Law and Public Policy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Havard Journal of Law and Public Policy HARVARD JOURNAL of LAW & PUBLIC POLICY VOLUME 41, NUMBER 3 SUMMER 2018 ARTICLES IRRECONCILABLE DIFFERENCES? WHOLE WOMAN’S HEALTH, GONZALES, AND JUSTICE KENNEDY’S VISION OF AMERICAN ABORTION JURISPRUDENCE Laura Wolk & O. Carter Snead ............................................... 719 SURROGACY AND LIMITATIONS TO FREEDOM OF CONTRACT: TOWARD BEING MORE FULLY HUMAN Adeline A. Allen ...................................................................... 753 UNASHAMED OF THE GOSPEL OF JESUS CHRIST: ON PUBLIC POLICY AND PUBLIC SERVICE BY EVANGELICALS Johnny Rex BuCkles ................................................................. 813 LIBERAL SECULARISM AND RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN THE PUBLIC SPACE: REFORMING POLITICAL DISCOURSE Alex Deagon ............................................................................ 901 NOTES THE PARTIALITY OF NEUTRALITY Kelsey Curtis ............................................................................ 935 A CONSTITUTIONAL OUTLIER: LEGITIMACY AS A STATE INTEREST AND ITS IMPLICATIONS IN ELECTION LAW Boyd Garriott ........................................................................... 973 HARVARD JOURNAL of LAW & PUBLIC POLICY Editor-in-Chief JOSHUA J. CRADDOCK Deputy Editor-in-Chief Articles Editors TIERNAN KANE Managing Editors JENNIFER BARROW ANNE BROWN BOYD GARRIOTT STEPHEN J. HAMMER Executive Editors JENNIFER BARROW Assistant ArtiCles Editors KATHRYN BOLAS Deputy Managing Editors NOAH HEINZ MATTHEW BURTON BRAD BARBER DANIEL JOHNSON HUSSEIN ELBAKRI WILL COURTNEY BOYD GARRIOTT KELSEY CURTIS ArtiCles Board JASON HALLIGAN RYAN PROCTOR ANNIKA BOONE FRANCES MANZO CASEY CONNOLLY MATTHEW REARDON Chief Financial OffiCer HAYLEY EVANS KYLE REYNOLDS ASHER PEREZ BRANTON NESTOR Events Manager SubsCriptions Manager Notes Editors ANNIKA BOONE NICK AQUART CHADWICK HARPER KYLE REYNOLDS TeChnology Manager CommuniCations Editor R.J. MCVEIGH SAMUEL SETTLE Senior Editors ANNIKA BOONE VERONICA FULTON VINCENT LI JEREMY SAWYER CASEY CONNOLLY CHANSLOR GALLENSTEIN AZFER ALI KHAN KEES THOMPSON HAYLEY EVANS JORDAN GREENE PARKER W. KNIGHT III SAM WILLIAMS RYAN FOLIO CHADWICK HARPER BRANTON NESTOR SARAH ZHANG DANIEL JOHNSON GRANT NEWMAN Editors NICOLE BAADE AARON GYDE JOHN MITZEL STEVE SZROM CHASE BROWNDORF JOSHUA HA DAVID NABORS JACOB THACKSTON DOUGLAS COLBY AARON HSU FELIPE PINTO MATTHEW WEINSTEIN HUGH DANILACK ASEEM JHA JASJAAP SIDHU YI YUAN BEN FLESHMAN JOSEPH LONGENECKER ANDREW SKARAS NICHOLAS ZAHORODNY ANASTASIA FRANE ISABEL MARIN DYLAN SOARES ZHUORAN ZHONG TERRENCE L. GEORGE R.J. MCVEIGH DOUG STEPHENS IV Founded by E. Spencer Abraham & Steven J. Eberhard BOARD OF ADVISORS E. Spencer Abraham, Founder SteVen G. Calabresi Douglas R. Cox Jennifer W. Elrod Charles Fried Douglas H. Ginsburg Orrin Hatch Jonathan R. Macey Michael W. McConnell Diarmuid F. O’Scannlain Jeremy A. Rabkin Hal S. Scott DaVid B. Sentelle Bradley Smith Jerry E. Smith THE HARVARD JOURNAL OF LAW & PUBLIC POLICY RECEIVES NO FINANCIAL SUPPORT FROM HARVARD LAW SCHOOL OR HARVARD UNIVERSITY. IT IS FUNDED EXCLUSIVELY BY SUBSCRIPTION REVENUES AND PRIVATE CHARITABLE CONTRIBUTIONS. The Harvard Journal of Law & Public PoliCy is published three times annually by the HarVard Society for Law & Public Policy, Inc., HarVard Law School, Cambridge, Mas- sachusetts 02138. ISSN 0193-4872. Nonprofit postage prepaid at Lincoln, Nebraska and at additional mailing offices. POSTMASTER: Send address changes to the HarVard Journal of Law & Public Policy, HarVard Law School, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138. Yearly subscription rates: United States, $55.00; foreign, $75.00. Subscriptions are re- newed automatically unless a request for discontinuance is receiVed. The Journal welcomes the submission of articles and book reViews. Each manuscript should be typed double-spaced, preferably in Times New Roman 12-point typeface. Authors submit manuscripts electronically to [email protected], preferably pre- pared using Microsoft Word. Views expressed are those of the authors and do not nec- essarily reflect the Views of the Society or of its officers, directors, editors, members, or staff. Unless otherwise indicated, all editors are students at the Harvard Law School. Copyright © 2018 by the HarVard Society for Law & Public Policy, Inc. PREFACE For the first time since the fall of the Soviet Union, many in the West are reconsidering liberalism. Those on the left are quick to point out the rise of populism and capitalism’s culture of consumption. Critics on the right, such as Professor Adrian Vermeule, question the neutrality of liberalism when it func- tions as a secular religion, complete with articles of faith and claims of exclusivity that crowd religion out of the public square. Others note the collateral casualties of liberalism’s struggle against nature in the realm of bioethics. The “end of history,” it seems, was only an intermission. Are liberalism’s travails the result of Progressive corruption, or were the roots of its demise embedded in its theoretical underpinnings from the very beginning? Advocates of the former view seek a re- turn to classical liberalism, hoping to prevent the “suicide of the West,” while those of the latter persuasion tout liberalism’s failures under its own consistent principles. Regardless of which view perceives liberalism more truly, this Issue consid- ers some of liberalism’s struggles and proposes ameliorative public policy solutions. Our first Article addresses itself to the quintessential liberal himself, Justice Kennedy. Laura Wolk and Professor O. Carter Snead observe a tension in the Supreme Court’s abortion juris- prudence after Whole Woman’s Health, and suggest that Justice Kennedy could provide much-needed clarity to lower courts considering the constitutionality of state bans on dismember- ment abortions. Professor Adeline A. Allen addresses another bioethical problem presented by liberal man’s Baconian con- quest of nature. She argues from a natural law perspective that gestational surrogacy arrangements are not within the freedom of contract and should be prohibited as against public policy. Taking stock of recent congressional hostility toward reli- gious nominees for public office, Professor Johnny Rex Buckles analyzes the Religious Test Clause and First Amendment norms to assess the constitutionality of congressional votes against nominees on the basis of religion. He then summarizes basic evangelical Christian beliefs to explain why such individ- uals are fit for public service. Finally, Professor Alex Deagon No. 3] Preface ii critically examines Rawlsian liberalism’s treatment of religious non-establishment. He argues that secularism is not truly neu- tral and advocates a broader view of religious freedom that permits greater participation in legal and political discourse. This Issue also features two student Notes written by editors of the Journal. Kelsey Curtis picks up precisely where Professor Deagon leaves off. She argues that the Supreme Court’s Estab- lishment Clause and Free Exercise Clause jurisprudence is not neutral, and proposes that the Court’s anti-discrimination and Free Speech Clause jurisprudence could lead toward some semblance of impartiality. Boyd Garriott closes this Issue by addressing whether the appearance of electoral legitimacy should be a judicially cognizable state interest in election law. He presents a persuasive case that it should not. I would be remiss if I did not conclude with a word of grati- tude. Editing Volume 41 of the Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy has been the great privilege of my time in law school. I would like to thank the entire editorial staff for their continued faithfulness and dedication to the success of this Journal. Espe- cially deserving of our thanks are those editors who went above and beyond their duties by volunteering for extra as- signments, including Annika Boone, Hayley Evans, Jason Hal- ligan, Stephen Hammer, and Ryan Proctor. Without the com- mitment of each and every member of our editorial staff, publication of this Journal would be impossible. In another forty years, I expect that the Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy will remain a bulwark of conservative legal scholarship and a home to all those who resist the prevailing orthodoxies of our time. Joshua J. Craddock Editor-in-Chief IRRECONCILABLE DIFFERENCES? WHOLE WOMAN’S HEALTH, GONZALES, AND JUSTICE KENNEDY’S VISION OF AMERICAN ABORTION JURISPRUDENCE LAURA WOLK* & O. CARTER SNEAD** INTRODUCTION A law is unconstitutional if it “has the purpose or effect of placing a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion of a nonviable fetus.”1 Twenty-five years have elapsed since a plurality of the Supreme Court articulated this undue burden standard in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey,2 yet its contours remain elusive. Notably, two current members of the Court—Justice Breyer and Justice Kennedy—seem to fundamentally differ in their understanding of what Casey requires and permits. In Gonzales v. Carhart,3 Jus- tice Kennedy emphasized a wide range of permissible state in- terests implicated by abortion4 and indicated that courts should defer to States when they regulate in areas of medical uncer- tainty.5 According to Justice Kennedy, “[w]here [the State] has a rational basis to act, and it does not impose an undue burden, the State may use its regulatory power” to impose regulations “in furtherance of its legitimate interests.”6 More recently, Jus- tice Breyer wrote in Whole Woman’s Health v. Hellerstedt7 that * J.D., Notre Dame Law School, 2016. **
Recommended publications
  • The "Public Trust" As It Is Used in Article VI
    THE "PUBIC TRUST" JenniferAnglim Kreder ABSTRACT It seems as if no one really knows the meaning of the term "public Trust" used in the Religious Test Clause of Article VI of the U.S. Constitution. 7iis Article is the first scholarly attempt to define the term by exploring historical evidence pre-dating the nation's jounding through the Constitution's adoption, including British and colonial trust law that influenced the Founders' conception of the term. Today, one can find the term used only in the cases and scholarship concerning environmental law, tax law and museum law. After a thorough analysis of the old and new sources, this Article proposes the following original definition of term "public Trust": "Any entity given special privilege by the government, beyond the simple grant of a state corporate charteroften coupled with state or federal tax waivers, so long as that entity is legally obligated to engage in conduct that could traditionally have been performed by the government itself for the public's benefit." TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ..................................... ..... 1426 I. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND OF ARTICLE VI............ .... 1428 A. The Stuart Period & Colonial Era......... ............... 1429 B. The Foundingand Early Republic ................... 1430 C. InterpretationalFoundations .................. ..... 1434 D. Fiduciary Underpinnings .......................... 1438 II. MODERN SIGNIFICANCE OF THE PUBLIC TRUST....... ..... 1440 A. Judicially Recognized Trusts and Non-Profit Corporations.. 1441 B. EnvironmentalRegulation ......................... 1443 1. Historical Origins of the Environmental "PublicTrust * Professor of Law, Salmon P. Chase College of Law. The author wishes to disclose that she has done a limited amount of legal work for American Atheists, Inc., including in Ameri- can Atheists, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • Law Review Articles
    Law Review Articles 1. Church and State in the United States: Competing Conceptions and Historic Changes Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 13 Ind. J. Global Legal Stud. 503 This article explains the separation of church and state in the United States. 2. Crowns and Crosses: The problems of Politico-Religious Visits as they Relate to the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 3 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 227 This article examines whether the Pope or any similar leader should be treated as a head of state or as the representative of a religious group. 3. Damages and Damocles: The Propriety of Recoupment Orders as Remedies for Violations of the Establishment Clause Notre Dame Law Review 83 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1385 In Americans United for Separation of Church & State v. Prison Fellowship Ministries, the court required “a private party, at the behest of another private party, to reimburse the public treasury when the government itself ha[d] not sought reimbursement” for a violation of the Establishment Clause. This Note offers background about taxpayer standing, restitution lawsuits, and background on the Establishment Clause. 4. Accommodation of Religion in Public Institutions Harvard Law Review 100 Harv. L. Rev. 1639 This artcile examines establishment clause problems attaching to government efforts to recognize religion in public institutions under an ‘accommodation’ rationale. Section A introduces the justification for allowing government recognition of religion in public institutions and discusses the difficulty of applying traditional establishment clause analysis to actions taken under this justification. It then proposes that the ambiguities in establishment clause analysis should be explicitly resolved so as to prevent majoritarian infringements of the religious autonomy of minorities.
    [Show full text]
  • Under God" to the Pledge of Allegiance Offends the Original Intent of the Establishment Clause Matthew .C Berger
    University of St. Thomas Law Journal Volume 3 Article 12 Issue 3 Spring 2006 2006 One Nation Indivisible: How Congress's Addition of "under God" to the Pledge of Allegiance Offends the Original Intent of the Establishment Clause Matthew .C Berger Bluebook Citation Matthew C. Berger, Comment, One Nation Indivisible: How Congress's Addition of "Under God" to the Pledge of Allegiance Offends the Original Intent of the Establishment Clause, 3 U. St. Thomas L.J. 629 (2006). This Comment is brought to you for free and open access by UST Research Online and the University of St. Thomas Law Journal. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Throughout American history, public officials, religious leaders, scholars, and ordinary citizens have debated the proper relationship between religion and government. Despite the volume of discussion on this topic, a commonly-accepted answer remains elusive-the is- sue remains one of the primary wedges dividing the American popu- lace. In the past, this debate has centered on taxpayer support for religious institutions' and Sunday operation of postal service^.^ To- day, the discussion has shifted to controversies over the display of religious symbols on public pr~perty,~the use of school vouchers to subsidize religiously-affiliated private school^,^ and the inclusion of "intelligent design" in public school science c~rricula.~Few of these issues have flashed as suddenly into the national consciousness, how- ever, as the constitutionality of the words "under God" in the Pledge of Allegiance. Despite United States Supreme Court dicta alluding to the Pledge of Allegiance as unquestionably con~titutional,~on June 26, 2002, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals held that both the 1954 Act * J.D.
    [Show full text]
  • The Establishment Clause, State Action, and Town of Greece
    William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal Volume 24 (2015-2016) Issue 2 Article 5 December 2015 The Establishment Clause, State Action, and Town of Greece Nathan S. Chapman Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj Part of the First Amendment Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Repository Citation Nathan S. Chapman, The Establishment Clause, State Action, and Town of Greece, 24 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 405 (2015), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj/vol24/iss2/5 Copyright c 2015 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE, STATE ACTION, AND TOWN OF GREECE Nathan S. Chapman * The Establishment Clause forbids the government from engaging in the same religious exercise that the law protects when performed by a private party. Thus, an establishment case often turns on whether religious activity is “state action.” Too often, however, courts ignore the state action analysis or merge it with the substantive Establishment Clause analysis. This muddles both doctrines and threatens individual religious liberty. This Article argues that the state action doctrine should account for the govern- ment’s distribution of private rights. Accordingly, the Constitution applies to the government’s distribution of rights, but not to a private party’s use of those rights. This account of state action sharpens the substantive constitutional question in a variety of constitutional contexts, but it is an especially powerful tool in religious lib- erty cases. For instance, in Town of Greece v. Galloway the Court focused on whether the prayers offered by chaplains before town meetings ran afoul of the Establishment Clause because either they were too “sectarian” or the setting was too coercive.
    [Show full text]
  • Power and the Subject of Religion Kurt T
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Law Faculty Publications School of Law 1998 Power and the Subject of Religion Kurt T. Lash University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.richmond.edu/law-faculty-publications Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Recommended Citation Kurt T. Lash, Power and the Subject of Religion, 59 Ohio St. L.J. 1069 (1998). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Law at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Law Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. OHIO STATE LAW JOURNAL Volume 59, Number 4,1998 Power and the Subject of Religion KURT T. LASH* Under the FirstAmendment, "Congress shall make no laws respecting an establishment of religion orprohibiting the free exercise thereof" Nevertheless, congressional actors have on occasion enacted laws that expressly make religion the subject of legislation. Many scholars justify these laws on the grounds that Congress at the time of the Founding had an implied power to legislate on religion ifnecessary andproper to an enumeratedend. Professor Lash argues that the "implied power" theory cannot withstand historicalscrutiny Whatever "implied power" arguments may have emanated from the orginial Constitution, those arguments wereforeclosed by the adoption of the FirstAmendment. However, the enactment of section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment does enable Congress to legislate-in a limited scope-on religious matters. I. INTRODUCTION What precisely is the source of power enabling Congress to enact a law on the subject of religion? I am not referring to Congress's power to make law that incidentally affects religion, but rather law that expressly makes religion the subject of legislation.
    [Show full text]
  • Uses and Abuses of Textualism and Originalism in Establishment Clause Interpretation Carl H
    University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository Faculty Publications Fall 2011 Uses and Abuses of Textualism and Originalism in Establishment Clause Interpretation Carl H. Esbeck University of Missouri School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.missouri.edu/facpubs Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Recommended Citation Carl H. Esbeck, Uses and Abuses of Textualism and Originalism in Establishment Clause Interpretation, 2011 Utah L. Rev. 489 (2011) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository. USES AND ABUSES OF TEXTUALISM AND ORIGINALISM IN ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE INTERPRETATION Carl H. Esbeck* TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ........................................................... 490 II. RELIGION AND RELIGIOUS FREEDOM DURING THE CONSTITUTIONAL CONVENTION OF 1787.................................................496 A. Religion and Religious Freedom in the 1787 Constitution...... ..... 496 B. Religion and Religious Freedom at the Convention ........... ..... 498 C. The Constitution's Overall Theory ...................... ..... 499 D. Historians and the Business of Over-Reading the Constitution.................504 E. The Religious Test Clause & FailedProposals .................... 506 III. RELIGION AND RELIGIOUS FREEDOM DURING THE STATE RATIFICATION OF THE 1787 CONSTITUTION ................................................ 508 IV. DRAFTING THE PHRASES ON RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN THE FIRST FEDERAL CONGRESS, MAY TO SEPTEMBER 1789, AND ENSUING STATE RATIFICATION.....525 A. Before the House ofRepresentatives ................................527 B. Before the United States Senate.............................555 C. Back to the House ofRepresentatives........................... 560 D. Back to the United States Senate............................561 E.
    [Show full text]
  • Faithful Execution and Article II
    Fordham Law School FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History Faculty Scholarship 2019 Faithful Execution and Article II Andrew Kent Ethan J. Leib Jed Shugerman Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Law Commons VOLUME 132 JUNE 2019 NUMBER 8 © 2019 by The Harvard Law Review Association ARTICLE FAITHFUL EXECUTION AND ARTICLE II Andrew Kent, Ethan J. Leib & Jed Handelsman Shugerman CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .......................................................................................................................... 2113 I. FAITHFUL EXECUTION IN 1787–1788: EVIDENCE FROM THE CONVENTION, RATIFICATION, AND LINGUISTIC USAGE..................................................................... 2121 A. The Philadelphia Convention ........................................................................................ 2121 B. Ratification Debates ....................................................................................................... 2128 C. Linguistic Usage .............................................................................................................. 2132 D. The Other Components of the Clauses.......................................................................... 2134 1. “Take Care” ................................................................................................................. 2134 2. “[T]he Laws” .............................................................................................................. 2136
    [Show full text]
  • The Individual Liberties Within the Body of the Constitution: a Symposium - Introduction
    Case Western Reserve Law Review Volume 37 Issue 4 Article 3 1987 The Individual Liberties Within the Body of the Constitution: A Symposium - Introduction Melvyn R. Durchslag Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/caselrev Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Melvyn R. Durchslag, The Individual Liberties Within the Body of the Constitution: A Symposium - Introduction, 37 Case W. Rsrv. L. Rev. 589 (1987) Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/caselrev/vol37/iss4/3 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Journals at Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Case Western Reserve Law Review by an authorized administrator of Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. Case Western Reserve Law Review Volume 37 1986-87 Number 4 INTRODUCTION Melvyn R. Durchslag* This symposium was conceived in 1987, the bi-centennial year of our Constitution. It has been a year which has seen printed ver- sions of the Constitution on backs of cereal boxes, feature writers' accounts of constitutional history in local newspapers, and three minute blurbs of our greatest moments sandwiched between prime time television shows. It has also been a year in which academic journals have explored in detail, not only the marvels of our consti- tution and our resultant progress in political and human rights, but also its darker side.1 This symposium, however, is unique in that it adds a dimension to the study of our Constitution which tends to be largely ignored by current legal scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • Us Constituion Clause Religion Cant Affect Politics
    Us Constituion Clause Religion Cant Affect Politics Liveliest Zebulon subcultures his cenobite grouches rearwards. Ecclesiastic Jonny usually reheats some ravages or engrafts sexennially. Benito is massively tentaculoid after theophanic Jermaine naps his rites pungently. This theory and religion clause come to protect individuals because their distance and secondary schools States department making attendance can yield any vacancy in violation had run most, such as a useful for us, such tribunal established creed or other. Since 1959 the French government pays the salaries of teachers in private. The main-exercise clause allow the First Amendment states that the government. They are used for religion clauses are not affect interstate commerce clause: overbreadth is at first in. The Court wrote that mankind did not hook to laughter on the turkey of the constitutionality of such deeds. Religion Clauses issues as well. Excessive fines, cruel and unusual punishment, attainder, forfeiture of estate, indefinite imprisonment, and unreasonable detention of witnesses are forbidden. Sessions in religion clauses interact, used in shaping litigation in rare circumstances. Magistrate courts shall have another original jurisdiction in criminal matters as pants be prescribed by law, after no mention shall be convicted or sentenced for a felony in such courts. Rehnquist differ over religion clauses protect every man, political candidate because institutions are now in another pharmacy or weapons may be rightfully exercised by strong reasons. Economic Interests and the Adoption of the United States. The Legislature shall retain power to authorize the issuing and selling of state bonds not exceeding in one aggregate two separate million dollars. Project Blitz attempts to exhibit the groundwork for harmful legislation that privileges their conservative Christian views over all others.
    [Show full text]
  • The No Religious Test Clause and the Constitution of Religious Liberty: a Machine That Has Gone of Itself, 37 Case W
    Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Journal Articles Publications 1987 The oN Religious Test Clause and the Constitution of Religious Liberty: A Machine That Has Gone of Itself Gerard V. Bradley Notre Dame Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship Recommended Citation Gerard V. Bradley, The No Religious Test Clause and the Constitution of Religious Liberty: A Machine That Has Gone of Itself, 37 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 674 (1986-1987). Available at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship/67 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Publications at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE NO RELIGIOUS TEST CLAUSE AND THE CONSTITUTION OF RELIGIOUS LIBERTY: A MACHINE THAT HAS GONE OF ITSELF* Gerard V. Bradley** The article VI ban on religious tests for federal offices is the sole provision on the topic of religion in the original Constitution. Since the seminal Everson decision in 1947 the courts and commentators have labored mightily to craft a thoroughgoing constitutionalphilosophy of church and state, in recognition of the profoundly prob- lematic relationship between religion and law in our society. Yet none has looked carefully at the test clause for guidance. This Article does just that. Professor Bradley argues that notwithstanding the complete absence of attention to article VI, its story tells us all we need to know about the appropriateconstitutional philosophy of religion: there is none.
    [Show full text]
  • Florida Law Review Founded 1948
    Florida Law Review Founded 1948 VOLUME 65 JULY 2013 NUMBER 4 ARTICLES RELIGION AND THE EQUAL PROTECTION CLAUSE: WHY THE CONSTITUTION REQUIRES SCHOOL VOUCHERS Steven G. Calabresi∗ & Abe Salander† INTRODUCTION .................................................................................... 911 I. THE ORIGINAL MEANING OF THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT ......................................................................... 920 A. The Text and Structure of the Fourteenth Amendment .................................................................... 921 B. The Fourteenth Amendment’s Ban on Caste and Class Legislation ........................................................... 934 1. Definition of “Caste” and “Class Legislation” ....... 934 2. Historical Evidence of Opposition to Class Legislation .............................................................. 937 a. Evidence from Common Law and the Founding ................................................... 938 b. Evidence from State Constitutions Around the Time of the Founding ................................ 941 c. Evidence from the Antebellum Period ............ 943 d. Evidence from the History of the Ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment ........................ 951 e. Evidence from After Ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment .................................. 957 II. RELIGION AND THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT .................... 961 A. Religion as a Caste ........................................................ 961 B. Religion as a Class .......................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Cornerstone Forum a Conversation on Religious Freedom and Its Social Implications No
    Cornerstone Forum A Conversation on Religious Freedom and Its Social Implications No. 237. July 9, 2018 The “No Religious Test” Clause and Profoundly Religious Politics Jonathan Leeman Research Fellow, Ethics and Religious Liberty Commission The Constitution of the United States provides that “no religious Test shall ever be required as a Qualification to any Office or public Trust under the United States.” During the ratification debates, a framer of the Constitution explained that this clause prohibits examination of “one’s belief of certain doctrines...for the purpose of determining whether his religious opinions are such, that he is admissible to a publick office.” Last year, this provision, known as the No Religious Test Clause, became part of the public discourse when Senator Bernie Sanders (D-VT) announced that he would vote against the confirmation of a Christian presidential nominee because of his belief that Muslims “have a deficient theology.” In response to criticism, Sanders said that he was merely questioning whether the nominee’s beliefs would prevent him from being fair. A few months later, Senator Dianne Feinstein (D-CA) questioned the fitness of Amy Barrett for a federal judgeship because “the dogma lives loudly” within her. Feinstein argued that she had legitimately questioned whether the nominee would be able to apply law that contradicted her beliefs. And in 2015, presidential candidate Ben Carson said he was opposed to the idea of a Muslim president because Islam is “inconsistent with the values and principles of
    [Show full text]