Objectivity in Legal Judgment

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Objectivity in Legal Judgment Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 1994 Objectivity in Legal Judgment Heidi Li Feldman Georgetown University Law Center, [email protected] This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/1715 92 Mich. L. Rev. 1187 This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Legal Profession Commons OBJECTIVITY IN LEGAL JUDGMENT Heidi Li Feldman* INTRODUCTION We are experiencing a crisis of confidence in the idea of objectivity. In scholarly circles, many are ready to discontinue talk of objectivity altogether, on the grounds that it has been nothing more than a mask for the oppressive practices of politically and economically privileged groups, promising neutrality where in fact there are only power rela- tions. Some feminist legal scholars, some critical race scholars, and some critical legal studies scholars, along with some contemporary philosophers, argue that objectivity is inevitably a problematic, dan- gerous idea or ideal. Critics of objectivity sometimes argue that it can never be genuinely had, only claimed under false pretenses and then used oppressively.' On the strongest reading of their ideas, critics of objectivity insist that we entirely eliminate the idea of objectivity from our conceptual vocabulary. Different commentators base their insistence on different grounds. Feminist critics reject objectivity because, in their view, it is inextricably connected to male power and female subordination; purg- ing objectivity from our conceptual vocabulary is prerequisite to the elimination of these evils.2 Some philosophers claim that objectivity is, at best, chimerical, and that, at worst, it limits our capacity to im- agine and create new and better moral and political lives for ourselves. According to these critics, abandoning objectivity would save us from * Assistant Professor of Law, University of Michigan. B.A. 1986, Brown; J.D. 1990, Ph.D. (Philosophy) 1993, Michigan.-Ed. I would like to express my warmest, deepest thanks to the many colleagues in the University of Michigan Law School and Department of Philosophy who read drafts of this work for their generosity in commenting upon and discussing it throughout the stages of its development. 1. Commentators critical of objectivity include the feminist legal scholar Catharine Mac- Kinnon, the critical race scholar Richard Delgado, and the philosopher Richard Rorty. See CATHARINE A. MACKINNON, TOWARD A FEMINIST THEORY OF THE STATE 120-24 (1989); RICHARD RORTY, Solidarity or Objectivity, in OBJECTIVITY, RELATIVISM, AND TRUTH 21 (1991); Richard Delgado, The Inward Turn in OutsiderJurisprudence, 34 WM. & MARY L. REV. 741, 762-68 (1993). For a composite overview of feminist objections to objectivity, see SANDRA HARDING, WHOSE SCIENCE? WHOSE KNOWLEDGE?: THINKING FROM WOMEN'S LIVES 157- 59 (1991). Objectivity is controversial in fields other than law and philosophy. For a discussion of critics of objectivity as a journalistic ideal and a rebuttal of these criticisms, see Judith Lichten- berg, In Defense of Objectivity, in MASS MEDIA AND SOCIETY 216 (James Curran & Michael Gurevitch eds., 1991). 2. See, e.g., MACKINNON, supra note 1, at 120-25. 1187 1188 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 92:1187 both epistemological and ethical error.3 Other critics of objectivity condemn it less strenuously. They re- gard the idea of objectivity as dispensable, if not dangerous. Accord- ing to some such critics, talk of objectivity tends to inhibit our thinking, curtailing arguments that ought to continue.4 According to others, talk of objectivity makes us feel more constrained than we re- ally are.5 In either case, the idea of objectivity offers little in the way of positive power, according to these critics, and so relinquishing it imposes little cost. Skepticism and cynicism about objectivity, especially objectivity in law, is not restricted to scholars. We find it among the general public, surfacing in reaction to controversial trial judgments, such as those reached in the Rodney King and Reginald Denny beatings trials, and in response to Supreme Court judgments on sensitive matters, such as abortion and voting rights. Contentious legal judgments invite doubt about the law's capacity for objectivity. I take seriously concerns about the potential dangers of the idea or the ideal of objectivity and worries about whether objectivity is illu- sory. But objectivity is a very powerful idea, one that we could, per- haps, put to good use in criticizing what merits criticism and praising what merits praise. Before we abandon the idea or ideal of objectivity altogether, we should see whether we can elucidate it in a way that answers to that which seems worthwhile in the concept without in- cluding that which seems pernicious. This elucidation will enable us to gain a clear picture of the costs and benefits of retaining the idea and the ideal. Then, but only then, we will be ready to consider when, if ever, objectivity is*a concept worth keeping in currency. Popular understanding of science has given us one very simple conception of objectivity. According to this rather vague, prereflective conception, objectivity is a matter of correspondence to the world as it "really" is, independent of our practices, goals, values, and beliefs. Objective judgments track this human-independent world. For those seeking objectivity in legal judgment, a problem emerges immediately upon consideration of this simple conception. The phenomena identi- fied by legal concepts such as negligence, fraud, and rape are not like the phenomena identified by natural scientific concepts like proton or 3. See, e.g., RORTY, supra note 1, at 27-28, 33-34. 4. See, e.g., RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 80-83 (1986) [hereinafter DWORKIN, EM- PIRE]; RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 171-74 (1985) [hereinafter DWORKIN, PRINCIPLE]. 5. See, e.g., Duncan Kennedy, Freedom and Constraintin Adjudication: A CriticalPhenome. nology, 36 J. LEGAL EDUC. 518, 520-21 (1986). March 1994] Objectivity 1189 gravity. Negligence, fraud, and rape are not human-independent phe- nomena; they are constituted by our practices, goals, values, and be- liefs. Legal judgments that apply concepts like negligence, fraud, and rape are not purely descriptive. 6 These legal judgments do not aspire to correspond to a human-independent world, free from our practices, goals, values, and beliefs. If we have only the simple correspondence conception of objectivity available to us, it would seem that we have to surrender the possibility of objectivity in legal judgment. Many legal judgments do not fit into this conception of objectivity at all. 7 Nor would most legal judgments fit into a conception of objectivity suitable for wholly evaluative or purely normative judgments, judg- ments that apply concepts with little or no descriptive content. An example of a more purely evaluative concept is good; an example of a more purely normative concept is ought. These concepts apply appro- priately under an extremely wide variety of factual circumstance, serv- ing as all-purpose evaluative or prescriptive devices. Even though fraud and negligence have a negative evaluative flavor or component, it would be extremely odd to call torture fraud or negligence, whereas it would not be odd to call it bad. This is true because it will practi- cally always be inappropriate, due to the descriptive dimensions of fraud and negligence, to apply these concepts to torture, even though it is practically always appropriate to evaluate torture negatively. Moreover, fraud and negligence do not negatively evaluate torture in an apt way. Due to the intricate interweaving of the descriptive and the evaluative dimensions of these concepts, they evaluate in distinc- tive and particular ways.8 Bad, on the other hand, aptly negatively evaluates circumstances ranging from torture to spitting on a public bus. That is because its evaluative dimension is more general and less nuanced than the evaluative dimensions of negligence or fraud. We do not have a straightforward prereflective conception of ob- jectivity for more purely evaluative and more purely normative judg- ments, as we do in the case of more purely descriptive judgments. But, because more purely evaluative and more purely normative judgments are less closely world-guided than the kinds of legal judgments I have been noting, it is prima facie unlikely that a conception of objectivity suitable for more purely evaluative or normative judgments would be 6. Throughout this essay, I speak of "applying" concepts. Note that both the use and the nonuse of a concept count as "applications" - that is, a decision not to use a concept is as much an instance of applying it as is a decision to use it. 7. Whether even scientific judgments fit into this conception is a separate question, which I pursue briefly in Part II of this essay. See infra text accompanying notes 49-53. S. I clarify and pursue the nature of the connection between the descriptive and evaluative in concepts like fraud and negligence in Part I. See infra text accompanying notes 14-41. 1190 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 92:1187 suitable for more closely world-guided judgments, including the legal judgments mentioned so far.9 The situation confronting the defender of the idea or ideal of objec- tivity in legal judgment worsens. If neither the correspondence con- ception of objectivity
Recommended publications
  • A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont Scripps Senior Theses Scripps Student Scholarship 2019 A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry Karina Bucciarelli Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses Part of the Epistemology Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Bucciarelli, Karina, "A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry" (2019). Scripps Senior Theses. 1365. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1365 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Scripps Student Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scripps Senior Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGICAL FRAMEWORK: PREVENTING KNOWLEDGE DISTORTIONS IN SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY by KARINA MARTINS BUCCIARELLI SUBMITTED TO SCRIPPS COLLEGE IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE DEGREE OF BACHELOR OF ARTS PROFESSOR SUSAN CASTAGNETTO PROFESSOR RIMA BASU APRIL 26, 2019 Bucciarelli 2 Acknowledgements First off, I would like to thank my wonderful family for supporting me every step of the way. Mamãe e Papai, obrigada pelo amor e carinho, mil telefonemas, conversas e risadas. Obrigada por não só proporcionar essa educação incrível, mas também me dar um exemplo de como viver. Rafa, thanks for the jokes, the editing help and the spontaneous phone calls. Bela, thank you for the endless time you give to me, for your patience and for your support (even through WhatsApp audios). To my dear friends, thank you for the late study nights, the wild dance parties, the laughs and the endless support.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity in the Feminist Philosophy of Science
    OBJECTIVITY IN THE FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requisites for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Karen Cordrick Haely, M.A. ***** The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Louise M. Antony, Adviser Professor Donald C. Hubin _______________________ Professor George Pappas Adviser Philosophy Graduate Program ABSTRACT According to a familiar though naïve conception, science is a rigorously neutral enterprise, free from social and cultural influence, but more sophisticated philosophical views about science have revealed that cultural and personal interests and values are ubiquitous in scientific practice, and thus ought not be ignored when attempting to understand, describe and prescribe proper behavior for the practice of science. Indeed, many theorists have argued that cultural and personal interests and values must be present in science (and knowledge gathering in general) in order to make sense of the world. The concept of objectivity has been utilized in the philosophy of science (as well as in epistemology) as a way to discuss and explore the various types of social and cultural influence that operate in science. The concept has also served as the focus of debates about just how much neutrality we can or should expect in science. This thesis examines feminist ideas regarding how to revise and enrich the concept of objectivity, and how these suggestions help achieve both feminist and scientific goals. Feminists offer us warnings about “idealized” concepts of objectivity, and suggest that power can play a crucial role in determining which research programs get labeled “objective”.
    [Show full text]
  • Easychair Preprint the Indeterminist Objectivity of Quantum Mechanics
    EasyChair Preprint № 3891 The Indeterminist Objectivity of Quantum Mechanics Versus the Determinist Subjectivity of Classical Physics Vasil Penchev EasyChair preprints are intended for rapid dissemination of research results and are integrated with the rest of EasyChair. July 16, 2020 The indeterminist objectivity of quantum mechanics versus the determinist subjectivity of classical physics Vasil Penchev, [email protected] Bulgarian Academy of Sciences: Institute of Philosophy and Sociology: Dept. of Logic and Philosophy of Science Abstract. Indeterminism of quantum mechanics is considered as an immediate corollary from the theorems about absence of hidden variables in it, and first of all, the Kochen – Specker theorem. The base postulate of quantum mechanics formulated by Niels Bohr that it studies the system of an investigated microscopic quantum entity and the macroscopic apparatus described by the smooth equations of classical mechanics by the readings of the latter implies as a necessary condition of quantum mechanics the absence of hidden variables, and thus, quantum indeterminism. Consequently, the objectivity of quantum mechanics and even its possibility and ability to study its objects as they are by themselves imply quantum indeterminism. The so-called free-will theorems in quantum mechanics elucidate that the “valuable commodity” of free will is not a privilege of the experimenters and human beings, but it is shared by anything in the physical universe once the experimenter is granted to possess free will. The analogical idea, that e.g. an electron might possess free will to “decide” what to do, scandalized Einstein forced him to exclaim (in a letter to Max Born in 2016) that he would be а shoemaker or croupier rather than a physicist if this was true.
    [Show full text]
  • Madness, Reason, and Truth: an Examination of Two Philosophical Debates
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 7-2012 Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates Catherine Leigh Robey College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Robey, Catherine Leigh, "Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates" (2012). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 534. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/534 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates A thesis in partial fulfillment of the requirement for an award of honors in the department of Religious Studies from The College of William and Mary by Catherine Leigh Robey Williamsburg, VA May 3, 2012 Table of Contents I. INTRODUCTION 5 II. HEGEL, PLATO, AND KIERKEGAARD: AN ANALYSIS OF THE SUBJECTIVITY OF AN OBJECTIVE PHENOMENON 8 INTRODUCTION 8 HEGEL – THREE MAIN FORMS OF MADNESS 9 “IDIOCY” 9 “MADNESS PROPER” 11 “MANIA OR FRENZY” 12 HEGEL – REASON, UNIVERSALITY, OBJECTIVITY, AND THE DOCTRINE OF MEDIATION 13 PLATO AND “DIVINE MADNESS” 16 “MADNESS OF PROPHECY” 17 “MADNESS OF THE MYSTIC” 18 “MADNESS
    [Show full text]
  • Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science Stephen G
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 1980 "Cool Reflexion" and the Criticism of Values: Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science Stephen G. Salkever Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Political Science Commons Custom Citation Salkever, Stephen G. "'Cool Reflexion' and the Criticism of Values: Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science." American Political Science Review 74 (1980): 70-77. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/17 For more information, please contact [email protected]. "Cool Reflexion"and the Criticismof Values: Is, Ought,and Objectivityin Hume's SocialScience STEPHENG. SALKEVER Bryn MawrCollege Is the fact/value distinction incompatiblewith the possibility of a social science which is both objectiveand evaluative(or normative)?Does support of the latterrequire rejection of the former and vice versa? This article presents an indirect argument against the incompatibilityof the fact/value distinction and an objectively evaluativesocial science. My procedureis to show that David Hume, whose is/ought distinction is the locus classicusof the fact/value distinction, is committed both to the view that valuescannot be derivedfrom facts and to the view that social science is not (and should not be) value-neutral.Furthermore, Hume's position is free from any logical flaws. My conclusion is that it is false to say that the fact/value distinction entails a value-neutralsocial science, and that it is thereforeutterly unnecessaryfor criticsof such a science to waste their time attemptingto "bridgethe gap" betweenfacts and values.
    [Show full text]
  • Let's Not Talk About Objectivity
    Chapter 2 Let’s Not Talk About Objectivity Ian Hacking The first landmark event in twenty-first-century thinking about objectivity was, as is well known, Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison’s Objectivity (2007). It is a magisterial historical study of an epistemological concept, namely “objectivity”. Hence I call it a contribution to what I call (if it wants a name) meta-epistemology, although other prefer the less apt but better sounding historical epistemology. You will find more food for thought, not to mention headaches, in their book, than in any other body of work about objectivity. It will seem that Objectivity rejects the injunction stated in my title, for what is the book about, but objectivity? The authors are talking about objectivity if anyone is! Analytic philosopherslike myself make what others regard as too many distinctions, and I shall illustrate that here. Objectivity is about the concept of objectivity, its past uses, and the practices associated with it. For me, a concept is a word in its sites (Hacking 1984). In this context, that means the sites in which words cognate with “objective” were used over the past three centuries, the practices within which they were deployed, who had authority when using them, the actual modes of inscription, which in this case is closely associated with the use of pictures and other types of images. For me, as for a builder, a site is a rich field of activity to be described from many points of view, almost innumerable perspectives. Objectivity is a triumph of that type of analysis; it is not talking about objectivity but about the concept of objectivity (a distinction we most clearly owe to Gottlob Frege writing about number).
    [Show full text]
  • Realism and the Epistemic Objectivity of Science
    Realism and the Epistemic Objectivity of Science Howard Sankey Abstract The paper presents a realist account of the epistemic objectivity of science. Epistemic objectivity is distinguished from ontological objectivity and the objectivity of truth. As background, T.S. Kuhn's idea that scientific theory-choice is based on shared sci- entific values with a role for both objective and subjective factors is discussed. Kuhn's values are epistemologically ungrounded, hence provide a minimal sense of objectivity. A robust account of epistemic objectivity on which methodological norms are reliable means of arriving at the truth is presented. The problem remains that deliberative judgement is required to determine the relevance and relative significance of a range of methodological norms. A role is sketched for cognitive virtues which may be exercised in the course of the deliberative judgement. Keywords: scientific realism, objectivity, theory-choice, values, method 1 Introduction In this paper, I propose a realist account of the epistemic objectivity of science. Baldly stated, epistemic objectivity arises from the adoption of norms which promote truth about the objective world. Epistemic objec- tivity is explained in reliabilist terms as compliance with truth-conducive epistemic norms. To the extent that the scientist must deliberate on the application of competing epistemic norms, the account draws on the re- sources of virtue epistemology. The aim of the paper is not to defend a realist account of objectivity against anti-realist accounts of objectivity. The aim of the paper is to develop an account of epistemic objectivity that is suited to a realist conception of scientific inquiry. It is not my intention to argue for scientific realism here.
    [Show full text]
  • FAITH and OBJECTIVITY FAITH and OBJECTIVITY FRITZ Burl and the HERMENEUTICAL FOUNDATIONS of a RADICAL THEOLOGY
    FAITH AND OBJECTIVITY FAITH AND OBJECTIVITY FRITZ BURl AND THE HERMENEUTICAL FOUNDATIONS OF A RADICAL THEOLOGY by CHARLEY D. HARDWICK PREFACE by VAN A. HARVEY MARTINUS NIJHOFF I THE HAGUE I 1972 © 1972 by Martinus Nijhoff. The Hague, Netherlands Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1972 All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13: 978-90-247-1201-4 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-2760-1 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-010-2760-1 FOR ALLIE AND KEVIN AND CARY VII TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS USED XI PREFACE BY VAN A. HARVEY XIII FOREWORD XVI INTRODUCTION XIX I. THE PROBLEM OF OBJECTMTY IN THE GENESIS OF BURl'S THEOL- OOY 1 A. Consistent Eschatology and Philosophy of Religion: Burl's Early Position 2 B. Objectivity and Self-Understanding: The Transition to Burl's Mature Position 7 PART I THE PROBLEM OF OBJECTIVITY IN THE FOUNDATIONS OF A THEOLOGICAL HERMENEUTIC II. THE THEOLOGICAL PROBLEM OF OBJECTIVITY AND NON-OBJEC- TIVITY 23 A. Objectivity and Non-Objectivity in the Contemporary Dis- cussion 24 B. Knowledge and the Meanings of Objectivity 1. The Conditions of Objectivity in General 39 2. The Conditions of Scientific Objectivity 42 C. The Problem of Objectivity and Theological Language 45 D. The Limits of Objectivity 51 1. The Transparency of the Subject-Object Structure 53 2. The Limits of Scientific Objectivity 56 VIII TABLE OF CONTENTS E. BUrl's Clarification of the Problem of Objectivity 69 III. THE NON-OBmCTlVlTY OF FAITH AND REVELATION 72 A.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It Ronald Dworkin Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol
    Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe it Ronald Dworkin Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 25, No. 2. (Spring, 1996), pp. 87-139. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0048-3915%28199621%2925%3A2%3C87%3AOATYBB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-X Philosophy and Public Affairs is currently published by Princeton University Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/pup.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Sat
    [Show full text]
  • Defining Objectivity Within Journalism an Overview
    10.1515/nor-2017-0255 Defining Objectivity within Journalism An Overview CHARLOTTE WIEN Abstract The article seeks the roots of the journalistic concept of objectivity in various theoreti- cal schools. It argues that the concept of objectivity in journalism originates in the positivistic tradition and, furthermore, that it is strongly related to tan earlier theoretical school within historiography. Journalism has made several attempts have been made by journalism to break free of the positivistic objectivity paradigm, none of them very suc- cessful, however. The paper discusses each of these attempts. Finally, using the concept of objectivity as a prism, the paper sketches out what might be termed a landscape of jour- nalism theory. Key Words: objectivity, positivism, journalism, history Introduction Journalism derives a great deal of its legitimacy from the postulate that it is able to present true pictures of reality. No one would have use for journalism if the journalists themselves asserted that the dissemination of news consisted of false pictures of unre- ality. Concepts such as ‘truth’ and ‘reality’ cannot be separated from the concept of objectivity. Hence, if one can speak of a paradigm within journalism, we might see such a paradigm in the requirement for objectivity in disseminating news. But it is one thing to operate with objectivity as a beacon, and something else to operationalise objectiv- ity in the everyday task of journalism. Within journalism, there exist several schools which have attempted to operationalise the concept of objectivity: e.g. Mainstream Journalism, Scientific Journalism, New Journalism and Precision Journalism (including Computer-Assisted Reporting). To operationalise concepts demands either that one thinks for oneself or that one borrows the ideas of others.
    [Show full text]
  • Naturalism and Subjectivity Berk, K
    VU Research Portal Naturalism and Subjectivity Berk, K. 2010 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Berk, K. (2010). Naturalism and Subjectivity: A Philosophical Analysis. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 29. Sep. 2021 © K. Berk Typeset by Zink Typografie (www.zinktypografie.nl). e text is set in Garamond Pro /, a typeface designed by Robert Slimbach as a revival of the sixteenth-century typefaces created by Claude Garamond (romans) and Robert Granjon (italics). Printed in the Netherlands by Ridderprint Offsetdrukkerij , Ridderkerk. Naturalism and Subjectivity A Philosophical Analysis ter verkrijging van de graad Doctor aan de Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, op gezag van de rector magnificus prof.dr. L.M. Bouter, in het openbaar te verdedigen ten overstaan van de promotiecommissie van de faculteit der Wijsbegeerte op dinsdag december om .
    [Show full text]
  • Sensation and Intentionality in Kant's Theory of Empirical Cognition
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO Sensation and Intentionality in Kant’s Theory of Empirical Cognition A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Timothy P. Jankowiak Committee in Charge: Professor Eric Watkins, Chair Professor Rick Grush Professor Don MacLeod Professor William O’Brien Professor Clinton Tolley 2012 Copyright 2012 Timothy P. Jankowiak All rights reserved The Dissertation of Timothy P. Jankowiak is approved, and it is accept- able in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: Chair University of California, San Diego 2012 iii DEDICATION To my mother, Annabelle, for showing the unwavering and single-mindedly optimistic confidence in me that only a mother can show with sincerity; to the memory of my father, Paul, for always encouraging me to do with my life whatever I would find most satisfying; and to my wife, Joy, for keeping me happy and sane over the last seven years. iv EPIGRAPH Is our soul in itself so empty that unless it borrows images from outside it is nothing? (Leibniz, New Essays) For how else should the cognitive faculty be awakened into exercise if not through objects that stimulate our senses and in part themselves produce representations, in part bring the activity of our under- standing into motion to compare these, to connect or separate them, and thus to work up the raw material of sensible impressions into a cognition of objects that is called ex- perience? (Kant, Critique of Pure Reason) Shall I project a world? If not project then at least flash some arrow on the dome to skitter among constellations and trace out your Dragon, Whale, Southern Cross.
    [Show full text]