Naturalism and Subjectivity Berk, K

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Naturalism and Subjectivity Berk, K VU Research Portal Naturalism and Subjectivity Berk, K. 2010 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Berk, K. (2010). Naturalism and Subjectivity: A Philosophical Analysis. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 29. Sep. 2021 © K. Berk Typeset by Zink Typografie (www.zinktypografie.nl). e text is set in Garamond Pro /, a typeface designed by Robert Slimbach as a revival of the sixteenth-century typefaces created by Claude Garamond (romans) and Robert Granjon (italics). Printed in the Netherlands by Ridderprint Offsetdrukkerij , Ridderkerk. Naturalism and Subjectivity A Philosophical Analysis ter verkrijging van de graad Doctor aan de Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, op gezag van de rector magnificus prof.dr. L.M. Bouter, in het openbaar te verdedigen ten overstaan van de promotiecommissie van de faculteit der Wijsbegeerte op dinsdag december om . uur in het auditorium van de universiteit, De Boelelaan door Kiki Berk geboren te Amsterdam promotor: prof.dr. R. van Woudenberg copromotor: prof.dr. L. Stubenberg Acknowledgments ix Introduction xi e Subjectivity of Experience . Nagel’s Account of Subjectivity .. Nagel on the Subjectivity of Experience .. Point of View and Knowing What It Is Like . Other Accounts of Subjectivity .. More Definitions of Subjectivity .. Mapping onto De Sousa .. How Other Accounts Fit (S)-(S) . Subjective-Making Properties .. Does Experience Have ese Subjective-Making Properties? .. Do Other Mental Phenomena Have ese Subjective-Making Properties? . Conclusion Do Experiences Exist? . What Are Experiences? .. e Term ‘Experience’ .. Kinds of Experiences .. Structure of Experiences vi • . Contra: Arguments against the Existence of Experience .. Argument from Awkwardness .. Byrne’s Argument against Experience . Pro: An Argument for the Existence of Experience . First Reply: Behaviorism . Second Reply: Eliminativism . Conclusion Metaphysical Naturalism . Definitions of Materialism, Physicalism and Naturalism . Mapping onto the Literature . Varieties of Naturalism . Distinctions within Metaphysical Naturalism . Four Kinds of Metaphysical Naturalism .. Classical Materialism .. Spatio-Temporal Materialism .. Causal Materialism .. Anti-Supernaturalism . Conclusion Methodological Naturalism . Definitions of Methodological Naturalism . Methodological Naturalism: View, Stance or Research Program? . Hempel’s Dilemma . Two Other Problems . Does Methodological Naturalism Entail Metaphysical Naturalism? . e Objectivity of Science . Conclusion Are Subjectivity and Naturalism Compatible? . (S): Phenomenal Character of Experience . (S): A Single Point of View .. Argument from Perspective .. e Knowledge Argument .. Nagel’s Argument . (S): Argument from Privacy . (S): Knowledge of Experience . (S): Dualist Argument: Persons • vii . Objections & Replies .. Objection I: Lycan .. Objection II: Identity eory of Mind . Alternative Approaches .. Chrisley: Objectivity as Intersubjectivity .. Velmans: Objectivity as Intersubjectivity .. Howell: Subjective Physicalism . Conclusion Summary Bibliography Samenvatting – Summary in Dutch e first (two page) philosophy paper I ever wrote was for René van Wouden- berg’s class ‘Introduction to Metaphysics’, which I took my first semester of college. I wrote on dualism and physicalism; in particular, I tried to come up with arguments against physicalism, which I thought was an underdeveloped topic in the book we read for the class, Peter van Inwagen’s Metaphysics. Little did I know that four years later I would be taking a class with Van Inwagen himself and, soon afterwards, starting a four-year research project about the problems of physicalism (which I now prefer to call ‘naturalism’). It has been ten years since I wrote my first philosophy paper and four years since I started working on this dissertation, and I am happy to report that I am still fascinated by the same topic. Over the past four years I have learned a great deal about naturalism and subjectivity, how to do (and not to do) research, how to write more clearly, and how to overcome ‘feeling stuck’. But most of all I have learned that it takes determination and discipline to write a dissertation. Yet discipline and determination, though necessary, are not, in my experience, sufficient for success. I could not have written this dissertation without the help and support of many others, whom I am greatly indebted to and would like to thank here. First of all, I want to thank my director, René van Woudenberg, who has greatly shaped my philosophical thinking ever since the very first class I took with him. I have been very fortunate to work so closely with René throughout college and graduate school, and I have learned more than I can say from him both as a philosopher and as a person. I would like to thank René for teaching me what it means to be a philosopher, for trusting me to carry out this project, for his detailed and helpful comments on papers and drafts of chapters, and for x • encouraging me every step of the way. I could not have written this dissertation without his unrelenting support. I also wish to thank my co-director, Leopold Stubenberg, for his comments and suggestions for improvement on an earlier draft of this dissertation. I greatly enjoyed and learned very much from the classes I took with him at the University of Notre Dame. is project was carried out at the Department of Philosophy at the Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam. I want to thank the board for its hospitality and for allowing me to spend a semester at the University of Notre Dame as a visiting student. My time at Notre Dame proved to be very inspirational through the classes I attended and the many discussions I had with other graduate students. I would like to thank the University of Notre Dame, especially the Department of Philosophy, for its part in making this possible. At the Vrije Universiteit, the research group provided a wonderful opportunity to get feed- back on earlier drafts of the dissertation. I am grateful to the members of this group for their helpful comments and suggestions, especially Arianna Betti, Martijn Blaauw, Lieven Decock, Rik Peels and Jeroen de Ridder. I would like to give a special thanks to Jeroen for his detailed comments on Chapter . In the very last stage I got help from a couple of different directions. First, I want to thank my mother-in-law, Margo Tepley, for proofreading and copy- editing the entire manuscript. I am very grateful for her incredible effort, and any remaining errors are, of course, entirely my responsibility. Second, I am very happy to have chosen Zink Typografie for designing the lay-out of my dissertation. I want to thank Job and Roel Zinkstok for their fast and professional work. On a more personal note, I would like to take the opportunity to thank my parents, Tom Berk and Ineke Slootweg, for encouraging me to study and pursue a Ph.D. in philosophy and for all their advice, love, and support. I am very lucky to have them as my parents. I also want to thank my oma, Oma Slootweg, for being the best oma in the entire world. Last but not least, I want to thank my husband, Joshua Tepley, for reading earlier drafts of this dissertation, for talking with me (and listening to me talk) about my project on a daily basis, and for all the times philosophy was far from our minds (at least from mine). I benefited greatly from sharing the intellectual and emotional burden of writing a dissertation with a fellow philosopher who knows, from his own experience, what it is like to write a philosophy dissertation. e main question that this dissertation aims at answering is whether the subjectivity of experience is compatible with naturalism or not. In order to be able to establish this, two sub-questions need answering first: What is the subjectivity of experience? And: What is naturalism? However, before doing even so much, we need to pause and consider why one should care to ask the question whether the subjectivity of experience is compatible with naturalism. Let me give a short summary of the answer before going on to explain it in more detail. A great many philosophers think that the subjectivity of experience is a very important phenomenon, not just in theory or for philos- ophy, but also in and for (daily) life. Because this real-life phenomenon is so important, it ought to have its place in, or at least be compatible with, any metaphysics or ontology that is to be taken seriously, especially one which is frequently adopted and enjoys popularity. Nowadays the ontology that is by far the most popular is naturalism; virtually everyone, scientists, philosophers and laymen alike, claim to be naturalists, a trend which will most likely only expand in the near future. Given the importance of the subjectivity of experience and the popularity of naturalism, whether the phenomenon of subjectivity can be accounted for or have its place within a naturalistic ontology is a relevant and pressing question. Maybe unnecessary to add, I think that it is very important for this phenomenon to be compatible with this theory, and if it is not, I think this is a good reason to reject naturalism.
Recommended publications
  • Studies in the Social Sciences Definition/Overview
    1 www.onlineeducation.bharatsevaksamaj.net www.bssskillmission.in “Culture and Psychology”. In Section 1 of this course you will cover these topics: Understanding Cross-Cultural Psychology Methodology Of Cross-Cultural Research Critical Thinking In Cross-Cultural Psychology Topic : Understanding Cross-Cultural Psychology Topic Objective: At the end of this topic student would be able to: Explain Cross-Cultural Psychology Explain Ethnocentrism Explain Psychological underpinnings of ethnocentrism Explain Sociobiology Explain Definition Explain Introductory example Explain History of Sociobiology Explain Sociobiological theory Explain Richard Dawkins, a well known sociobiologist Explain Cross-CulturalWWW.BSSVE.IN Studies in the Social Sciences Definition/Overview: Cross-cultural psychology is the critical and comparative study of cultural effects on human psychology. As a comparative field, cross-cultural psychology draws its conclusions from at least two samples that represent at least two cultural groups. The act of comparison requires a particular set of critical thinking skills. Cross-cultural psychology examines psychological diversity and the underlying reasons for such diversity. Using a comparative approach, cross-cultural psychology examines the links between cultural norms and behavior and the ways in which particular human activities are influenced by various cultural forces. Cross-cultural psychology establishes psychological universals, that is, phenomena common for people in several, many, or perhaps all cultures. www.bsscommunitycollege.in www.bssnewgeneration.in www.bsslifeskillscollege.in 2 www.onlineeducation.bharatsevaksamaj.net www.bssskillmission.in Cultural psychology seeks to discover meaningful links between culture and psychology of individuals living in this culture. At least four types of knowledge about psychology can be recognized: scientific, popular (folk), ideological (value-based), and legal.
    [Show full text]
  • A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont Scripps Senior Theses Scripps Student Scholarship 2019 A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry Karina Bucciarelli Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses Part of the Epistemology Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Bucciarelli, Karina, "A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry" (2019). Scripps Senior Theses. 1365. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1365 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Scripps Student Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scripps Senior Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGICAL FRAMEWORK: PREVENTING KNOWLEDGE DISTORTIONS IN SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY by KARINA MARTINS BUCCIARELLI SUBMITTED TO SCRIPPS COLLEGE IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE DEGREE OF BACHELOR OF ARTS PROFESSOR SUSAN CASTAGNETTO PROFESSOR RIMA BASU APRIL 26, 2019 Bucciarelli 2 Acknowledgements First off, I would like to thank my wonderful family for supporting me every step of the way. Mamãe e Papai, obrigada pelo amor e carinho, mil telefonemas, conversas e risadas. Obrigada por não só proporcionar essa educação incrível, mas também me dar um exemplo de como viver. Rafa, thanks for the jokes, the editing help and the spontaneous phone calls. Bela, thank you for the endless time you give to me, for your patience and for your support (even through WhatsApp audios). To my dear friends, thank you for the late study nights, the wild dance parties, the laughs and the endless support.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity in the Feminist Philosophy of Science
    OBJECTIVITY IN THE FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requisites for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Karen Cordrick Haely, M.A. ***** The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Louise M. Antony, Adviser Professor Donald C. Hubin _______________________ Professor George Pappas Adviser Philosophy Graduate Program ABSTRACT According to a familiar though naïve conception, science is a rigorously neutral enterprise, free from social and cultural influence, but more sophisticated philosophical views about science have revealed that cultural and personal interests and values are ubiquitous in scientific practice, and thus ought not be ignored when attempting to understand, describe and prescribe proper behavior for the practice of science. Indeed, many theorists have argued that cultural and personal interests and values must be present in science (and knowledge gathering in general) in order to make sense of the world. The concept of objectivity has been utilized in the philosophy of science (as well as in epistemology) as a way to discuss and explore the various types of social and cultural influence that operate in science. The concept has also served as the focus of debates about just how much neutrality we can or should expect in science. This thesis examines feminist ideas regarding how to revise and enrich the concept of objectivity, and how these suggestions help achieve both feminist and scientific goals. Feminists offer us warnings about “idealized” concepts of objectivity, and suggest that power can play a crucial role in determining which research programs get labeled “objective”.
    [Show full text]
  • Easychair Preprint the Indeterminist Objectivity of Quantum Mechanics
    EasyChair Preprint № 3891 The Indeterminist Objectivity of Quantum Mechanics Versus the Determinist Subjectivity of Classical Physics Vasil Penchev EasyChair preprints are intended for rapid dissemination of research results and are integrated with the rest of EasyChair. July 16, 2020 The indeterminist objectivity of quantum mechanics versus the determinist subjectivity of classical physics Vasil Penchev, [email protected] Bulgarian Academy of Sciences: Institute of Philosophy and Sociology: Dept. of Logic and Philosophy of Science Abstract. Indeterminism of quantum mechanics is considered as an immediate corollary from the theorems about absence of hidden variables in it, and first of all, the Kochen – Specker theorem. The base postulate of quantum mechanics formulated by Niels Bohr that it studies the system of an investigated microscopic quantum entity and the macroscopic apparatus described by the smooth equations of classical mechanics by the readings of the latter implies as a necessary condition of quantum mechanics the absence of hidden variables, and thus, quantum indeterminism. Consequently, the objectivity of quantum mechanics and even its possibility and ability to study its objects as they are by themselves imply quantum indeterminism. The so-called free-will theorems in quantum mechanics elucidate that the “valuable commodity” of free will is not a privilege of the experimenters and human beings, but it is shared by anything in the physical universe once the experimenter is granted to possess free will. The analogical idea, that e.g. an electron might possess free will to “decide” what to do, scandalized Einstein forced him to exclaim (in a letter to Max Born in 2016) that he would be а shoemaker or croupier rather than a physicist if this was true.
    [Show full text]
  • Madness, Reason, and Truth: an Examination of Two Philosophical Debates
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 7-2012 Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates Catherine Leigh Robey College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Robey, Catherine Leigh, "Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates" (2012). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 534. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/534 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates A thesis in partial fulfillment of the requirement for an award of honors in the department of Religious Studies from The College of William and Mary by Catherine Leigh Robey Williamsburg, VA May 3, 2012 Table of Contents I. INTRODUCTION 5 II. HEGEL, PLATO, AND KIERKEGAARD: AN ANALYSIS OF THE SUBJECTIVITY OF AN OBJECTIVE PHENOMENON 8 INTRODUCTION 8 HEGEL – THREE MAIN FORMS OF MADNESS 9 “IDIOCY” 9 “MADNESS PROPER” 11 “MANIA OR FRENZY” 12 HEGEL – REASON, UNIVERSALITY, OBJECTIVITY, AND THE DOCTRINE OF MEDIATION 13 PLATO AND “DIVINE MADNESS” 16 “MADNESS OF PROPHECY” 17 “MADNESS OF THE MYSTIC” 18 “MADNESS
    [Show full text]
  • Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science Stephen G
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 1980 "Cool Reflexion" and the Criticism of Values: Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science Stephen G. Salkever Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Political Science Commons Custom Citation Salkever, Stephen G. "'Cool Reflexion' and the Criticism of Values: Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science." American Political Science Review 74 (1980): 70-77. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/17 For more information, please contact [email protected]. "Cool Reflexion"and the Criticismof Values: Is, Ought,and Objectivityin Hume's SocialScience STEPHENG. SALKEVER Bryn MawrCollege Is the fact/value distinction incompatiblewith the possibility of a social science which is both objectiveand evaluative(or normative)?Does support of the latterrequire rejection of the former and vice versa? This article presents an indirect argument against the incompatibilityof the fact/value distinction and an objectively evaluativesocial science. My procedureis to show that David Hume, whose is/ought distinction is the locus classicusof the fact/value distinction, is committed both to the view that valuescannot be derivedfrom facts and to the view that social science is not (and should not be) value-neutral.Furthermore, Hume's position is free from any logical flaws. My conclusion is that it is false to say that the fact/value distinction entails a value-neutralsocial science, and that it is thereforeutterly unnecessaryfor criticsof such a science to waste their time attemptingto "bridgethe gap" betweenfacts and values.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness and Cosmos
    Alfredo Pereira Jr.,1 Chris Nunn,2 Massimo Pregnolato3 and Greg Nixon4 Consciousness and Cosmos Building an Ontological Framework Abstract: Contemporary theories of consciousness are based on widely different concepts of its nature, most or all of which probably embody aspects of the truth about it. Starting with a concept of con- sciousness indicated by the phrase ‘the feeling of what happens’ (the title of a book by Antonio Damasio), we attempt to build a framework capable of supporting and resolving divergent views. We picture con- sciousness in terms of reality experiencing itself from the perspective of cognitive agents. Each conscious experience is regarded as com- posed of momentary feeling events that are combined by recognition and evaluation into extended conscious episodes that bind cognitive Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2018 contents with a wide range of apparent durations (0.1 secs to 2 or more secs, for us humans, depending on circumstances and context). For personal use only -- not for reproduction Three necessary conditions for the existence of consciousness are identified: a) a ground of reality, envisaged as a universal field of potentiality encompassing all possible manifestations, whether material or ‘mental’; b) a transitional zone, leading to; c) a manifest Correspondence: Email: [email protected] 1 Department of Education, Institute of Biosciences, State University of São Paulo, Brazil. 2 Royal College of Psychiatrists, England. 3 Department of Drug Sciences, University of Pavia, Italy. 4 University of Northern British Columbia, Prince George, Canada. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 25, No. 3–4, 2018, pp. 181–205 182 A. PEREIRA, C. NUNN, M.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflexive Monism
    Reflexive Monism Max Velmans, Goldsmiths, University of London; email [email protected]; http://www.goldsmiths.ac.uk/psychology/staff/velmans.php Journal of Consciousness Studies (2008), 15(2), 5-50. Abstract. Reflexive monism is, in essence, an ancient view of how consciousness relates to the material world that has, in recent decades, been resurrected in modern form. In this paper I discuss how some of its basic features differ from both dualism and variants of physicalist and functionalist reductionism, focusing on those aspects of the theory that challenge deeply rooted presuppositions in current Western thought. I pay particular attention to the ontological status and seeming “out- thereness” of the phenomenal world and to how the “phenomenal world” relates to the “physical world”, the “world itself”, and processing in the brain. In order to place the theory within the context of current thought and debate, I address questions that have been raised about reflexive monism in recent commentaries and also evaluate competing accounts of the same issues offered by “transparency theory” and by “biological naturalism”. I argue that, of the competing views on offer, reflexive monism most closely follows the contours of ordinary experience, the findings of science, and common sense. Key words: Consciousness, reflexive, monism, dualism, reductionism, physicalism, functionalism, transparency, biological naturalism, phenomenal world, physical world, world itself, universe itself, brain, perceptual projection, phenomenal space, measured space, physical space, space perception, information, virtual reality, hologram, phenomenological internalism, phenomenological externalism, first person, third person, complementary What is Reflexive Monism? Monism is the view that the universe, at the deepest level of analysis, is one thing, or composed of one fundamental kind of stuff.
    [Show full text]
  • Velmans, Max and Nagasawa, Yujin. 2012. Introduction to Monist Alternatives to Physicalism
    Velmans, Max and Nagasawa, Yujin. 2012. Introduction to Monist Alternatives to Physicalism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 19(9-10), pp. 7-18. ISSN 1355-8250 [Article] https://research.gold.ac.uk/id/eprint/26069/ The version presented here may differ from the published, performed or presented work. Please go to the persistent GRO record above for more information. If you believe that any material held in the repository infringes copyright law, please contact the Repository Team at Goldsmiths, University of London via the following email address: [email protected]. The item will be removed from the repository while any claim is being investigated. For more information, please contact the GRO team: [email protected] 1 Introduction to Monist Alternatives to Physicalism Max Velmans and Yujin Nagasawa In M. Velmans & Y. Nagasawa (eds.) (2012) Journal of Consciousness Studies: Special Issue on Monist Alternatives to Physicalism, Vol. 19, No. 9-10, 7-18. In the history of Western thought, attempts to understand the relationship of mind and consciousness to body and brain have largely been shaped by competing monist versus dualist convictions about whether these are different types of entity or process. Bodies and brains seem to be very different from minds and consciousness. Arms and legs for example seem to be made of completely different “stuff” to thoughts and feelings. Nor can one find qualia by examining bits of the brain. Consequently, dualists argue that body/brain and mind/consciousness are different types of thing. There is also extensive evidence that the body and brain affect mind and consciousness via the senses (for example that the visual system affects visual experience) and that mind and consciousness affect the body and brain (for example in the way that visual experiences, thoughts, and conscious choices influence subsequent actions).
    [Show full text]
  • Let's Not Talk About Objectivity
    Chapter 2 Let’s Not Talk About Objectivity Ian Hacking The first landmark event in twenty-first-century thinking about objectivity was, as is well known, Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison’s Objectivity (2007). It is a magisterial historical study of an epistemological concept, namely “objectivity”. Hence I call it a contribution to what I call (if it wants a name) meta-epistemology, although other prefer the less apt but better sounding historical epistemology. You will find more food for thought, not to mention headaches, in their book, than in any other body of work about objectivity. It will seem that Objectivity rejects the injunction stated in my title, for what is the book about, but objectivity? The authors are talking about objectivity if anyone is! Analytic philosopherslike myself make what others regard as too many distinctions, and I shall illustrate that here. Objectivity is about the concept of objectivity, its past uses, and the practices associated with it. For me, a concept is a word in its sites (Hacking 1984). In this context, that means the sites in which words cognate with “objective” were used over the past three centuries, the practices within which they were deployed, who had authority when using them, the actual modes of inscription, which in this case is closely associated with the use of pictures and other types of images. For me, as for a builder, a site is a rich field of activity to be described from many points of view, almost innumerable perspectives. Objectivity is a triumph of that type of analysis; it is not talking about objectivity but about the concept of objectivity (a distinction we most clearly owe to Gottlob Frege writing about number).
    [Show full text]
  • Realism and the Epistemic Objectivity of Science
    Realism and the Epistemic Objectivity of Science Howard Sankey Abstract The paper presents a realist account of the epistemic objectivity of science. Epistemic objectivity is distinguished from ontological objectivity and the objectivity of truth. As background, T.S. Kuhn's idea that scientific theory-choice is based on shared sci- entific values with a role for both objective and subjective factors is discussed. Kuhn's values are epistemologically ungrounded, hence provide a minimal sense of objectivity. A robust account of epistemic objectivity on which methodological norms are reliable means of arriving at the truth is presented. The problem remains that deliberative judgement is required to determine the relevance and relative significance of a range of methodological norms. A role is sketched for cognitive virtues which may be exercised in the course of the deliberative judgement. Keywords: scientific realism, objectivity, theory-choice, values, method 1 Introduction In this paper, I propose a realist account of the epistemic objectivity of science. Baldly stated, epistemic objectivity arises from the adoption of norms which promote truth about the objective world. Epistemic objec- tivity is explained in reliabilist terms as compliance with truth-conducive epistemic norms. To the extent that the scientist must deliberate on the application of competing epistemic norms, the account draws on the re- sources of virtue epistemology. The aim of the paper is not to defend a realist account of objectivity against anti-realist accounts of objectivity. The aim of the paper is to develop an account of epistemic objectivity that is suited to a realist conception of scientific inquiry. It is not my intention to argue for scientific realism here.
    [Show full text]
  • FAITH and OBJECTIVITY FAITH and OBJECTIVITY FRITZ Burl and the HERMENEUTICAL FOUNDATIONS of a RADICAL THEOLOGY
    FAITH AND OBJECTIVITY FAITH AND OBJECTIVITY FRITZ BURl AND THE HERMENEUTICAL FOUNDATIONS OF A RADICAL THEOLOGY by CHARLEY D. HARDWICK PREFACE by VAN A. HARVEY MARTINUS NIJHOFF I THE HAGUE I 1972 © 1972 by Martinus Nijhoff. The Hague, Netherlands Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1972 All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13: 978-90-247-1201-4 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-2760-1 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-010-2760-1 FOR ALLIE AND KEVIN AND CARY VII TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS USED XI PREFACE BY VAN A. HARVEY XIII FOREWORD XVI INTRODUCTION XIX I. THE PROBLEM OF OBJECTMTY IN THE GENESIS OF BURl'S THEOL- OOY 1 A. Consistent Eschatology and Philosophy of Religion: Burl's Early Position 2 B. Objectivity and Self-Understanding: The Transition to Burl's Mature Position 7 PART I THE PROBLEM OF OBJECTIVITY IN THE FOUNDATIONS OF A THEOLOGICAL HERMENEUTIC II. THE THEOLOGICAL PROBLEM OF OBJECTIVITY AND NON-OBJEC- TIVITY 23 A. Objectivity and Non-Objectivity in the Contemporary Dis- cussion 24 B. Knowledge and the Meanings of Objectivity 1. The Conditions of Objectivity in General 39 2. The Conditions of Scientific Objectivity 42 C. The Problem of Objectivity and Theological Language 45 D. The Limits of Objectivity 51 1. The Transparency of the Subject-Object Structure 53 2. The Limits of Scientific Objectivity 56 VIII TABLE OF CONTENTS E. BUrl's Clarification of the Problem of Objectivity 69 III. THE NON-OBmCTlVlTY OF FAITH AND REVELATION 72 A.
    [Show full text]