Sensation and Intentionality in Kant's Theory of Empirical Cognition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sensation and Intentionality in Kant's Theory of Empirical Cognition UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO Sensation and Intentionality in Kant’s Theory of Empirical Cognition A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Timothy P. Jankowiak Committee in Charge: Professor Eric Watkins, Chair Professor Rick Grush Professor Don MacLeod Professor William O’Brien Professor Clinton Tolley 2012 Copyright 2012 Timothy P. Jankowiak All rights reserved The Dissertation of Timothy P. Jankowiak is approved, and it is accept- able in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: Chair University of California, San Diego 2012 iii DEDICATION To my mother, Annabelle, for showing the unwavering and single-mindedly optimistic confidence in me that only a mother can show with sincerity; to the memory of my father, Paul, for always encouraging me to do with my life whatever I would find most satisfying; and to my wife, Joy, for keeping me happy and sane over the last seven years. iv EPIGRAPH Is our soul in itself so empty that unless it borrows images from outside it is nothing? (Leibniz, New Essays) For how else should the cognitive faculty be awakened into exercise if not through objects that stimulate our senses and in part themselves produce representations, in part bring the activity of our under- standing into motion to compare these, to connect or separate them, and thus to work up the raw material of sensible impressions into a cognition of objects that is called ex- perience? (Kant, Critique of Pure Reason) Shall I project a world? If not project then at least flash some arrow on the dome to skitter among constellations and trace out your Dragon, Whale, Southern Cross. Anything might help. (Thomas Pynchon, The Crying of Lot 49) v TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page. iii Dedication........................................................ iv Epigraph......................................................... v Table of Contents................................................. vi ListofFigures.................................................... ix Acknowledgements................................................ x Vita.............................................................. xii Abstract.......................................................... xiii Chapter 1: Introduction ....................................... 1 1.1 Reading Kant on Sensation and Intentionality . 1 1.2 Outline of the Work . 8 1.3 Sensation in Early Modern Thought . 15 1.3.1 The Representationality of Sensation . 18 1.3.2 Sensations and Beliefs About External Objects . 23 1.3.3 The Relation Between Sensing and Thinking . 27 1.4 Preliminaries Regarding Kantian Representation . 32 1.4.1 Metaphysical Status and Cognitive Function . 33 1.4.2 Matter and Form...................................... 37 1.4.3 Relation to an Object.................................. 40 Part I: SENSIBILITY ......................................... 49 Chapter 2: The “Objectivity” of Sensation.................. 50 2.1 Three Accounts of Sensation in Critique of Pure Reason ... 56 2.1.1 Sensation as Subjective Modification . 58 2.1.2 Sensation as Subjective Representation. 62 2.1.3 Sensation as Objective Representation . 65 2.2 Two Distinctions Between Subjective and Objective . 69 2.2.1 Sensation in Critique of Judgment ..................... 71 2.2.2 Sensation in the Anthropology ......................... 77 2.2.3 Summary . 80 2.3 Revisiting the First Critique . 82 2.4 Conclusion................................................. 97 vi Chapter 3: Empirical Intuition and the Objects of Percep- 98 tion 3.1 Two Kantian Theses about our Relations to Objects . 104 3.1.1 Phenomenalism . 105 3.1.2 Direct Realism......................................... 114 3.1.3 First Pass at a Solution . 121 3.2 Empirical Intuitions . 125 3.2.1 What are Empirical Intuitions? . 125 3.2.2 What do Empirical Intuitions Represent? . 135 3.2.3 How do Empirical Intuitions Represent?. 149 3.3 Empirical Intuitions and the Objects of Experience . 163 3.3.1 Intuition and Phenomenalism . 166 3.3.2 Intuition and Direct Realism . 171 3.4 Conclusion................................................. 175 Appendix A: Nonconceptualism and Intuitions ............. 178 Appendix B: Sensory Determination of the Content of In- 191 tuition Part II: UNDERSTANDING ................................. 209 Chapter 4: Sensation, Reality, and Intensive Magnitudes.. 210 4.1 Judgments of Reality . 214 4.1.1 The Category of Reality. 215 4.1.2 Substantial Reality. 222 4.1.3 Accidental Reality . 228 4.1.4 The Real of Sensation. 233 4.2 Anticipations of Perception . 235 4.2.1 The Argument . 236 4.2.2 The Inferred Cause Interpretation . 245 4.2.3 The Constructivist Interpretation . 250 4.3 Objections Considered . 257 4.3.1 The Cause of Sensation . 257 4.3.2 Sensory Determination of Judgments of Reality . 259 4.3.3 Transcendental Necessity Undermined?. 262 4.4 Conclusion................................................. 267 vii Chapter 5: Things “Outside Me”: Actual Objects and 269 Things in Themselves 5.1 The Actuality of Empirical Objects . 272 5.1.1 Actuality in Intentional Object Phenomenalism . 272 5.1.2 Skepticism Regarding the External World . 279 5.2 Sensations and Things in Themselves . 288 5.2.1 There is no “Problem of Double Affection” . 289 5.2.2 The Existence of Things in Themselves. 296 5.3 Conclusion................................................. 304 Chapter 6: Summary and Conclusion ........................ 306 6.1 Kant’s Theory of Sensation . 306 6.2 Intentional Object Phenomenalism. 311 Bibliography .................................................... 318 viii LIST OF FIGURES Figure 1: Summary of the Interpretation . 307 Figure 2: Appearances as Intentional Objects . 311 Figure 3: Things in Themselves as Intentional Objects . 313 Figure 4: The Langton/Allais Model . 314 Figure 5: The Two-World Model . 316 ix ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This dissertation and the thought process that led up to it would not have been even remotely possible were it not for the intellectual stimulation provided by my years of interaction with the very smart people in and around the UCSD philosophy department. I owe thanks to all of my professors and fellow graduate students who have helped me develop as a philosopher over the last seven years. Several people in particular, though, stand out as meriting special acknowledgement. Some of my best interlocutors over the course of the development of the dissertation have been my fellow graduate students. The other students of German philosophy proved to be an especially valuable resource for helping me work out the details of my interpretation of Kant’s view. Most noteworthy here are James Messina, Peter Yong, Silje Eggestad, Daniel Althof, Ben Sheredos, and Kim Brewer. I have also benefitted from detailed feedback from the participants in a dissertation writing workshop: Adam Streed, Joyce Havstad, and Erick Ramirez gave me invaluable feedback which ultimately helped me improve the intelligibility and expression of my views. Other students with whom I’ve had the opportunity to discuss my ideas include Per Milam, Marta Halina, Justin Knoepfler, Nate Rockewood, Dan Schwartz, Dan Burnston, Julie Walsh, Spencer Hey, Craig Agule, Erin Frykholm, Amanda Brovold, Amy Berg, Veronica Pear, and Mike Tiboris. Among the faculty whose expertise has helped me in my development, I must acknowledge first and foremost my advisor, Eric Watkins. During my time at UCSD, Eric has consistently been more than generous with his time and effort in paying close attention to the progress of my work. Between reading, critiquing, and discussing multiple drafts of the various chapters of the dissertation, encouraging my profes- sional development in various ways, and working to ensure that I had sufficient x employment to keep from starving during the summer months, Eric has gone far above and beyond what is expected from an advisor, and for this I am immensely grateful. Clinton Tolley has also always shown a great deal of focussed attention to the development of my interpretation. My conversations with him consistently chal- lenged me to think through the possible alternatives and objections to my claims, and the final product is clearly the better for this. Other faculty members whose feedback was particularly helpful, especially in the context of the History of Philos- ophy Roundtable discussion group, include Don Rutherford, Rick Grush, Michael Hardimon, Monte Johnson, Sam Rickless, and Gila Sher. Each of the above has, in various ways, helped make this dissertation better than it could otherwise have been. The responsibility for any and all remaining imperfections lies only with myself. Lastly, and most importantly, I must thank my wife, Joy. She was more than understanding and encouraging during the many long days and late nights of work on this document, and the fact that I have come away from it with my sanity mostly intact can only be attributed to the comfort and support she provided. xi VITA Education 2005 Bachelor of Arts, University of Illinois, Chicago 2006-2012 Teaching Assistant, UCSD Philosophy Departments and Revelle Human- ities Program 2009 Master of Arts, University of California, San Diego 2012 Doctor of Philosophy, University of California, San Diego Areas of Specialization Kant Early Modern Philosophy Areas of Competence German Philosophy Phenomenology Philosophy of Mind and Perception Scholarly Work Editorial work for De Gruyter for Proceedings of the 2010 International Kant Congress, (2011) Editorial work for Eric Watkins for
Recommended publications
  • Expressions of Mind/Body Dualism in Thinspiration
    MIND OVER MATTER: EXPRESSIONS OF MIND/BODY DUALISM IN THINSPIRATION Annamarie O’Brien A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2013 Committee: Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Dr. Rebecca Kinney Dr. Jeremy Wallach © 2013 Annamarie O’Brien All Rights Reserved iii ABSTRACT Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Thinspiration images, meant to inspire weight-loss, proliferate online through platforms that encourage the circulation of user-generated content. Despite numerous alarmist critiques in mass media about thinspiration and various academic studies investigating ‘pro-anorexia’ sites, surprisingly little attention has been given to the processes of creation and the symbolic potential of thinspiration. This thesis analyzes the formal hybridity of thinspiration, and its use as an expressive medium. The particularities of thinspiration (including its visual characteristics, creative processes, and exhibition) may be considered carefully constructed instances of self- representation, hinging on the expression of beliefs regarding the mind and body. While these beliefs are deeply entrenched in popular body management discourse, they also tend to rely on traditional dualist ideologies. Rather than simply emphasizing slenderness or reiterating standard assumptions about beauty, thinspiration often evokes pain and sadness, and employs truisms about the transcendence of flesh and rebellion against social constraints. By harnessing individualist discourse and the values of mind/body dualism, thinspiration becomes a space in which people struggling with disordered eating and body image issues may cast themselves as active agents—contrary to the image of eating disorders proffered by popular and medical discourse. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First, I would like to thank my thesis committee chair, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Implications of Naturalism As an Educational Philosophy in Jordan from the Perspectives of Childhood Education Teachers
    Journal of Education and Practice www.iiste.org ISSN 2222-1735 (Paper) ISSN 2222-288X (Online) Vol.7, No.11, 2016 The Implications of Naturalism as an Educational Philosophy in Jordan from the Perspectives of Childhood Education Teachers Omar Khasawneh Ahmed Khaled Mohammad Al Momani Al Ain University of Science and Technology Al Ain, United Arab Emirates & Yarmouk University- Jordan Abstract The purpose of this study was to identify the educational implications of naturalism as an educational philosophy from the Jordanian childhood education teachers' perspectives. Each philosophy simply represents a unique conviction concerning the nature of the teaching/learning process. This study could serve as a grounded theory for Jordanian childhood teachers to comprehend the need for a clear educational philosophy within the Jordanian educational system. In addition, this research study would draw Jordanian childhood teachers' interest to be acquainted more with the educational principles of such philosophical theory. The researchers employed a questionnaire consisted of twenty one items, which correspond to the educational principles of naturalism. The quantitative approach is used to gather data as one of the techniques and descriptive due to its suitability for this study. The study findings revealed that Jordanian childhood education teachers' perspectives toward the implications of naturalism as an educational philosophy were positive for all domains; curriculum, aims, and activities. Based on the findings, the researchers provided some relevant recommendations. Keywords : Naturalism, Educational Philosophy, Childhood Education Teachers, Jordan. 1. Introduction Teachers’ educational philosophies and their value systems influence their teaching styles and the way they deal with their students. So, the impact of teachers’ beliefs and values on teaching and learning is evident in each classroom (Conti, 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Does Wine Have a Place in Kant's Theory of Taste?1
    Does Wine Have a Place in Kant’s Theory of Taste?1 Rachel Cristy, Princeton University Kant’s own answer to my title question is “no.” One can make of a wine the merely subjective judgment that it is agreeable, never the universally valid judgment that it is beautiful. Here is Kant’s only remark on wine in the Critique of the Power of Judgment: With regard to the agreeable, everyone is content that his judgment, which he grounds on a private feeling, and in which he says of an object that it pleases him, be restricted merely to his own person. Hence he is perfectly happy if, when he says that sparkling wine from the Canaries is agreeable, someone else should improve his expression and remind him that he should say “It is agreeable to me”; and this is so not only in the case of the taste of the tongue, palate, and throat, but also in the case of that which may be agreeable to someone’s eyes and ears. (KU §7, 5: 212) Here is Kant’s explanation for why wine can’t be judged beautiful: “Aesthetic judgments can be divided into empirical and pure. The first are those which assert agreeableness or disagreeableness, the second those which assert beauty of an object… the former are judgments of sense (material aesthetic judgments), the latter (as formal) are alone proper judgments of taste” (§14, 5: 223). Not only flavors and aromas, but also “mere color, e.g., the green of a lawn” and “mere tone…say that of a violin” are relegated to judgments of agreeableness, because they “have as their ground merely the matter of the representations, namely mere sensation” (§14, 5: 224).
    [Show full text]
  • A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont Scripps Senior Theses Scripps Student Scholarship 2019 A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry Karina Bucciarelli Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses Part of the Epistemology Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Bucciarelli, Karina, "A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry" (2019). Scripps Senior Theses. 1365. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1365 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Scripps Student Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scripps Senior Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGICAL FRAMEWORK: PREVENTING KNOWLEDGE DISTORTIONS IN SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY by KARINA MARTINS BUCCIARELLI SUBMITTED TO SCRIPPS COLLEGE IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE DEGREE OF BACHELOR OF ARTS PROFESSOR SUSAN CASTAGNETTO PROFESSOR RIMA BASU APRIL 26, 2019 Bucciarelli 2 Acknowledgements First off, I would like to thank my wonderful family for supporting me every step of the way. Mamãe e Papai, obrigada pelo amor e carinho, mil telefonemas, conversas e risadas. Obrigada por não só proporcionar essa educação incrível, mas também me dar um exemplo de como viver. Rafa, thanks for the jokes, the editing help and the spontaneous phone calls. Bela, thank you for the endless time you give to me, for your patience and for your support (even through WhatsApp audios). To my dear friends, thank you for the late study nights, the wild dance parties, the laughs and the endless support.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to Our Second Lecture on Personhood and Identity
    PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to our second lecture on personhood and identity. We’re going to begin today what will be two lectures on Rene Descartes’ thoughts on this subject. The position that is attributed to him is known as mind/body dualism. Sometimes it’s simply called the dualism for short. We need to be careful, however, because the word dualism covers a number of different philosophical positions, not always dualisms of mind and body. In other words, there are other forms of dualism that historically have been expressed. And so I will refer to his position as mind/body dualism or as Cartesian dualism as it’s sometimes also called. I said last time that Descartes is not going to talk primarily about persons. He’s going to talk about minds as opposed to bodies. But I think that as we start getting into his view, you will see where his notion of personhood arises. Clearly, Descartes is going to identify the person, the self, with the mind as opposed to with the body. This is something that I hoped you picked up in your reading and certainly that you will pick up once you read the material again after the lecture. Since I’ve already introduced Descartes’ position, let’s define it and then I’ll say a few things about Descartes himself to give you a little bit of a sense of the man and of his times. The position mind/body that’s known as mind/body dualism is defined as follows: It’s the view that the body is a physical substance — a machine, if you will — while the mind is a non-physical thinking entity which inhabits the body and is responsible for its voluntary movements.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity in the Feminist Philosophy of Science
    OBJECTIVITY IN THE FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requisites for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Karen Cordrick Haely, M.A. ***** The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Louise M. Antony, Adviser Professor Donald C. Hubin _______________________ Professor George Pappas Adviser Philosophy Graduate Program ABSTRACT According to a familiar though naïve conception, science is a rigorously neutral enterprise, free from social and cultural influence, but more sophisticated philosophical views about science have revealed that cultural and personal interests and values are ubiquitous in scientific practice, and thus ought not be ignored when attempting to understand, describe and prescribe proper behavior for the practice of science. Indeed, many theorists have argued that cultural and personal interests and values must be present in science (and knowledge gathering in general) in order to make sense of the world. The concept of objectivity has been utilized in the philosophy of science (as well as in epistemology) as a way to discuss and explore the various types of social and cultural influence that operate in science. The concept has also served as the focus of debates about just how much neutrality we can or should expect in science. This thesis examines feminist ideas regarding how to revise and enrich the concept of objectivity, and how these suggestions help achieve both feminist and scientific goals. Feminists offer us warnings about “idealized” concepts of objectivity, and suggest that power can play a crucial role in determining which research programs get labeled “objective”.
    [Show full text]
  • Easychair Preprint the Indeterminist Objectivity of Quantum Mechanics
    EasyChair Preprint № 3891 The Indeterminist Objectivity of Quantum Mechanics Versus the Determinist Subjectivity of Classical Physics Vasil Penchev EasyChair preprints are intended for rapid dissemination of research results and are integrated with the rest of EasyChair. July 16, 2020 The indeterminist objectivity of quantum mechanics versus the determinist subjectivity of classical physics Vasil Penchev, [email protected] Bulgarian Academy of Sciences: Institute of Philosophy and Sociology: Dept. of Logic and Philosophy of Science Abstract. Indeterminism of quantum mechanics is considered as an immediate corollary from the theorems about absence of hidden variables in it, and first of all, the Kochen – Specker theorem. The base postulate of quantum mechanics formulated by Niels Bohr that it studies the system of an investigated microscopic quantum entity and the macroscopic apparatus described by the smooth equations of classical mechanics by the readings of the latter implies as a necessary condition of quantum mechanics the absence of hidden variables, and thus, quantum indeterminism. Consequently, the objectivity of quantum mechanics and even its possibility and ability to study its objects as they are by themselves imply quantum indeterminism. The so-called free-will theorems in quantum mechanics elucidate that the “valuable commodity” of free will is not a privilege of the experimenters and human beings, but it is shared by anything in the physical universe once the experimenter is granted to possess free will. The analogical idea, that e.g. an electron might possess free will to “decide” what to do, scandalized Einstein forced him to exclaim (in a letter to Max Born in 2016) that he would be а shoemaker or croupier rather than a physicist if this was true.
    [Show full text]
  • Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology's
    Augsburg Honors Review Volume 12 Article 4 2019 Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire Allison Mangan Augsburg University Follow this and additional works at: https://idun.augsburg.edu/honors_review Part of the Epistemology Commons Recommended Citation Mangan, Allison (2019) "Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire," Augsburg Honors Review: Vol. 12 , Article 4. Available at: https://idun.augsburg.edu/honors_review/vol12/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate at Idun. It has been accepted for inclusion in Augsburg Honors Review by an authorized editor of Idun. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Allison Mangan Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire Alio Maga, Augbug Univesty ualia are layered and complex, the basic philosophic understanding a labyrinth of a concept, of qualia today. We will see how Q rife with debate as to their consciousness is necessary for qualia, existence, state, and what they mean and why this makes defning qualia for our understanding of knowledge, a challenge. Next, we will go over the relationship with the world, and explanatory gap of qualia. From there, ourselves. Toughtful exploration into we will see how qualia relate to the mind- the complexities of what qualia are body problem, and the early exploration and how they relate to the mind-body of this problem through Descartes, problem will be wrestled with though Locke, and Berkeley. Additionally, we research applied within this paper. will go over the main schools of thought Qualia can be found in philosophical that surround the mind-body problem: debates surrounding epistemology materialism, idealism, and dualism.
    [Show full text]
  • There Is More to Quality Than Continuous Improvement: Listening to Plato
    Sower article 12/20/04 11:16 AM Page 8 There is More to Quality than Continuous Improvement: Listening to Plato VICTOR E. SOWER AND FRANK K. FAIR, SAM HOUSTON STATE UNIVERSITY © 2005, ASQ Quality programs that focus on continuous improve- ment are vital in providing incremental improvement INTRODUCTION of processes, products, and services in an existing tech- Quality is a more complicated term than it appears. nological paradigm. These programs view quality as Dictionary definitions are usually inadequate in helping being measurable in some quantitative way. Breakthrough improvement that leads to development of a quality professional understand the concept. It seems new paradigms requires thinking of quality in a differ- that every quality expert defines quality somewhat dif- ent way. The transcendent view of quality is necessary ferently, and there are a variety of perspectives that can for development of paradigm-shifting technologies. be taken in defining quality (for example, customer’s Plato’s divided line represents four stages of awareness. perspective, specification-based perspective). The understanding stage is necessary for effective con- The purpose of this article is to discuss the tran- tinuous improvement but inadequate for paradigm- shifting improvement. That requires Plato’s insight stage scendent approach to thinking about quality. The of awareness. Drawing from Plato’s divided line model, transcendent approach is the least understood and this article develops the approach to quality that is best least utilized of the five approaches identified by suited for developing radical innovations. Garvin (1984). At best, the transcendent approach is The authors believe that organizations operating at mentioned as being the realm of philosophers before Plato’s level of understanding that focus almost exclu- discussion is quickly shifted to more “practical” sively on continuous improvement may be blind to approaches.
    [Show full text]
  • Madness, Reason, and Truth: an Examination of Two Philosophical Debates
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 7-2012 Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates Catherine Leigh Robey College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Robey, Catherine Leigh, "Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates" (2012). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 534. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/534 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Madness, Reason, and Truth: An Examination of Two Philosophical Debates A thesis in partial fulfillment of the requirement for an award of honors in the department of Religious Studies from The College of William and Mary by Catherine Leigh Robey Williamsburg, VA May 3, 2012 Table of Contents I. INTRODUCTION 5 II. HEGEL, PLATO, AND KIERKEGAARD: AN ANALYSIS OF THE SUBJECTIVITY OF AN OBJECTIVE PHENOMENON 8 INTRODUCTION 8 HEGEL – THREE MAIN FORMS OF MADNESS 9 “IDIOCY” 9 “MADNESS PROPER” 11 “MANIA OR FRENZY” 12 HEGEL – REASON, UNIVERSALITY, OBJECTIVITY, AND THE DOCTRINE OF MEDIATION 13 PLATO AND “DIVINE MADNESS” 16 “MADNESS OF PROPHECY” 17 “MADNESS OF THE MYSTIC” 18 “MADNESS
    [Show full text]
  • Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science Stephen G
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 1980 "Cool Reflexion" and the Criticism of Values: Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science Stephen G. Salkever Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Political Science Commons Custom Citation Salkever, Stephen G. "'Cool Reflexion' and the Criticism of Values: Is, Ought, and Objectivity in Hume's Social Science." American Political Science Review 74 (1980): 70-77. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/17 For more information, please contact [email protected]. "Cool Reflexion"and the Criticismof Values: Is, Ought,and Objectivityin Hume's SocialScience STEPHENG. SALKEVER Bryn MawrCollege Is the fact/value distinction incompatiblewith the possibility of a social science which is both objectiveand evaluative(or normative)?Does support of the latterrequire rejection of the former and vice versa? This article presents an indirect argument against the incompatibilityof the fact/value distinction and an objectively evaluativesocial science. My procedureis to show that David Hume, whose is/ought distinction is the locus classicusof the fact/value distinction, is committed both to the view that valuescannot be derivedfrom facts and to the view that social science is not (and should not be) value-neutral.Furthermore, Hume's position is free from any logical flaws. My conclusion is that it is false to say that the fact/value distinction entails a value-neutralsocial science, and that it is thereforeutterly unnecessaryfor criticsof such a science to waste their time attemptingto "bridgethe gap" betweenfacts and values.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato: the Virtues of Philosophical Leader
    Center for Open Access in Science ▪ https://www.centerprode.com/ojsp.html Open Journal for Studies in Philosophy, 2018, 2(1), 1-8. ISSN (Online) 2560-5380 ▪ https://doi.org/10.32591/coas.ojsp.0201.01001k _________________________________________________________________________ Plato: The Virtues of Philosophical Leader Ioanna-Soultana Kotsori University of Peloponnese, Kalamata Faculty of Humanities and Cultural Studies Received 22 February 2018 ▪ Revised 25 May 2018 ▪ Accepted 11 June 2018 Abstract The entrance into the reflection of the present work is made with the philosophical necessity of the leader in society, the leader with the particular characteristics of love and wisdom, from which his personality must possess so that by art he can compose opposing situations and move society towards the unity and bliss of citizens. A gentle royal nature (genotype), which blends with the excellent treatment of morality, body and spirit, will create the ideal model leader (phenotype). Thus, noble nature and royal law will give the state the excellent leader. Even if the forms and the conditions that determine them change, the one that remains stable and permanent is the Platonic ethos in art and the science of politics and administration in general. The salvation from corruption is from childhood the cultivation of man by treating at the same time the moral of the soul, the beauty of the body and the wisdom of the spirit. Keywords: philosophical king, education, wisdom, ethos, leader, excellent state, virtues. 1. Introduction Plato’s works demonstrate that he cared for man and society, trying to radically improve morality. Plato’s character was not such as to pursue leadership positions to meet his personal needs and shows his responsibility to the leader’s heavy role.
    [Show full text]