SCIENCE, LABOR and SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS by George Borg B.Sc

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

SCIENCE, LABOR and SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS by George Borg B.Sc TITLE PAGE SCIENCE, LABOR AND SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS by George Borg B.Sc. in Chemistry, University of California, Berkeley 1999 Ph.D. in Chemistry, Harvard University, 2007 M.A. in Philosophy, Tufts University, 2012 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2020 COMMITTE E PAGE UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by George Borg It was defended on June 5, 2020 and approved by Paolo Palmieri, Associate Professor, History and Philosophy of Science Kevin Zollman, Associate Professor, Philosophy at Carnegie Mellon University Dissertation Co-Director: John D. Norton, Distinguished Professor, History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Co-Director: Michael R. Dietrich, Professor, History and Philosophy of Science ii Copyright © by George Borg 2020 iii ABST RACT SCIENCE, LABOR AND SCIENTIFIC PROGRSS George Borg, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2020 My dissertation introduces a new materialist theory of scientific progress built on a novel characterization of scientific work and an analysis of progress appropriate to it. Two questions, crucial for understanding scientific progress, are answered: Why is it possible for scientists at a given time to have more epistemic abilities than scientists at an earlier time? How can knowledge acquired in the past be used in on-going or future research? I argue that these questions are best answered by analyzing science as a form of labor. The elements of the labor process, involving both intellectual and material means, provide a starting-point for the systematic study of how scientific abilities evolve. As a unit of analysis, the labor process exposes features of the dynamics of knowledge accumulation that traditional analyses do not. I analyze historical cases from chemistry and the Scientific Revolution, attending carefully to how scientific work is conducted and conceived. First, I argue that scientific progress consists not just in the growth of theoretical or empirical knowledge, as in traditional philosophy of science, but also in the growth of know-how. The tools of science play a crucial role in determining the abilities scientists can and must have to do science. Tools also determine how scientists’ abilities change over time, by enabling, but also constraining, the incorporation of knowledge into the labor process. I argue that an extremely important mechanism of progress in science consists of a feedback loop between the production of new knowledge and instrument construction. This process requires the integration, and transformation into material form, of different kinds of knowledge. As the process is repeated over the long term, scientific work is transformed because it becomes less dependent on native human epistemic abilities. iv Second, the evolution of scientific abilities depends on ambient ideological conditions: Social attitudes towards different kinds of work are critical, as are notions about the proper object of science. What results is a picture of scientific change involving the interactions of different kinds of knowledge and in which internal and external factors, as well as instrumental rationality, play a significant role. v TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ...............................................................................................xv 1.0 INTRODUCTION........................................................................................................1 1.1 References ...................................................................................................................11 2.0 MODELS OF SCIENCE AND SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS ..................................13 2.1 Introduction ................................................................................................................13 2.2 Scientific progress ......................................................................................................14 2.2.1 Varieties of scientific progress ..............................................................16 2.2.2 The broad conception of scientific progress ........................................17 2.3 Three models of science .............................................................................................26 2.3.1 The intellectualist model ........................................................................26 2.3.2 The labor process model ........................................................................30 2.3.2.1 Excursus on the labor process .................................................. 33 2.3.2.2 The Radical Science Journal collective .................................... 39 2.3.2.3 Edgar Zilsel and the merging of intellectual and manual labor ................................................................................................................. 42 2.3.2.4 Science as practice ..................................................................... 46 2.3.3 The sociological model ...........................................................................50 2.4 Scientific progress and the labor process model .....................................................56 2.4.1 Abilities in philosophy of action and in philosophy of science ...........56 2.4.2 Abilities, instruments, and scientific progress .....................................60 2.5 References ...................................................................................................................71 3.0 HISTORICAL-EPISTEMOLOGICAL CONSIDERATIONS ON THE ORIGINS OF THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD .......................................................77 3.1 Introduction ................................................................................................................77 3.2 The Scholastics, manual labor and the role of maker’s knowledge in science .....78 3.2.1 Introduction ............................................................................................78 3.2.2 Randall’s two theses ...............................................................................80 vi 3.2.3 The Scholastics’ contribution to scientific method according to Randall .............................................................................................................82 3.2.4 Schmitt on experience and experiment in Zabarella ..........................85 3.2.5 The experimental method as production .............................................87 3.2.6 Ways forward? .......................................................................................95 3.2.6.1 Logic as instrument ................................................................... 95 3.2.6.2 Newman on the “perfective arts” ............................................. 97 3.2.7 Conclusion .............................................................................................102 3.3 From perception to measurement in Kepler’s Optics ...........................................103 3.3.1 Introduction ..........................................................................................103 3.3.2 Gal and Chen-Morris on the “disappearing observer” ....................106 3.3.3 Kepler and the perspectivists ..............................................................109 3.3.4 Error, perception and measurement ..................................................120 3.3.5 The problem of the certainty of measurement ..................................125 3.3.6 The eye and the problem of systematic measurement error ............137 3.3.7 Concluding remarks ............................................................................148 3.4 Conclusion of chapter 2 ...........................................................................................149 3.5 References .................................................................................................................151 4.0 ON “THE APPLICATION OF SCIENCE TO SCIENCE ITSELF:” CHEMISTRY, INSTRUMENTS, AND THE SCIENTIFIC LABOR PROCESS ................................................................................................................155 4.1 Introduction ..............................................................................................................155 4.2 Models and machines of scientific revolutions ......................................................158 4.3 Structure determination before and after the instrumental revolution .............164 4.4 Marx’s analysis of the labor process and the industrial revolution ....................173 4.5 Parallels between the Industrial Revolution and the Instrumental Revolution .179 4.5.1 Conceptions of progress .......................................................................180 4.5.2 Common features .................................................................................181 4.5.3 Disanalogies ..........................................................................................189 4.6 Explication of the analytical claim .........................................................................191 4.7 Objections and replies .............................................................................................196 vii 4.8 Conclusion: The Instrumental Revolution or an instrumental revolution? .......199 4.9 References .................................................................................................................203 5.0 THE INSTRUMENTAL REVOLUTION AND THE HEURISTICS OF CHEMICAL RESEARCH .....................................................................................211
Recommended publications
  • Abstracts-Significant Digits
    SIGNIFICANT DIGITS Responsible Use of Quantitative Information @Brussels, Fondation Universitaire 9-10 June 2015 Joint Research Centre Joint Research Centre Brussels, 09-10 June 2015 Preamble We live in an age when good policies are assumed to be evidence-based. And that evidential base is assumed to be at its best when expressed in numbers. The digital information may be derived from quantitative data organised in statistics, or from qualitative data organised in indicators. Either way, evidence in digital form provides the accepted foundation of policy arguments over a very broad range of issues. In the policy realm there are frequent debates over particular policy issues and their associated evidence. But only rarely is the nature of the evidence called into question. Such a faith in numbers can be dangerous. Policies in economic and financial policy, based on numbers whose significance was less than assumed, recently turned out to be quite disastrously wrong. Other examples can easily be cited. The decades-long period of blaming dietary fats for heart disease, rather than sugar, is a notable recent case. We are concerned here with the systemic problem: whether we are regularly placing too much of an evidentiary burden on quantitative sciences whose strength and maturity are inherently inadequate. The harm that has been done to those sciences, as well as to the policy process, should be recognised. Only in that way can future errors be avoided. In this workshop we will review a seminal essay by Andrea Saltelli and Mario Giampietro, ‘The Fallacy of Evidence Based Policy’. That paper contains positive recommendations for the development of a responsible quantification.
    [Show full text]
  • Supersizing Daubert Science for Litigation and Its Implications for Legal Practice and Scientific Research
    Volume 52 Issue 4 Article 6 2007 Supersizing Daubert Science for Litigation and Its Implications for Legal Practice and Scientific Research Gary Edmond Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr Part of the Evidence Commons Recommended Citation Gary Edmond, Supersizing Daubert Science for Litigation and Its Implications for Legal Practice and Scientific Research, 52 Vill. L. Rev. 857 (2007). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr/vol52/iss4/6 This Symposia is brought to you for free and open access by Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Villanova Law Review by an authorized editor of Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. Edmond: Supersizing Daubert Science for Litigation and Its Implications f 2007] SUPERSIZING DAUBERT SCIENCE FOR LITIGATION AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR LEGAL PRACTICE AND SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH GARY EDMOND* I. INTRODUCTION: SCIENCE FOR LITIGATION AND THE EXCLUSIONARY ETHOS T HIS essay is about sciencefor litigation, its implications and limitations.' "Science for litigation" is expert evidence specifically developed for litigation-extant, pending or anticipated.2 Although, as we shall see, federal judges have demonstrated a curious tendency to restrict the concept to expert evidence associated with litigation which is underway or pending. Ordinarily, expert evidence developed for, or tailored to, litigation carries an epistemic stigma. Conventionally, the fact that expert evidence is ori- ented toward a specific goal is thought to impair the independence of the experts and the reliability of their evidence. This often manifests in con- cerns that evidence developed for litigation is inconsistent with scientific knowledge and the opinions of experts not embroiled in litigation.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstract Papers
    Workshop on Philosophy & Engineering WPE2008 The Royal Academy of Engineering London November 10th-12th 2008 Supported by the Royal Academy of Engineering, Illinois Foundry for Innovation in Engineering Education (iFoundry), the British Academy, ASEE Ethics Division, the International Network for Engineering Studies, and the Society for Philosophy & Technology Co-Chairs: David E. Goldberg and Natasha McCarthy Deme Chairs: Igor Aleksander, W Richard Bowen, Joseph C. Pitt, Caroline Whitbeck Contents 1. Workshop Schedule p.2 2. Abstracts – plenary sessions p.5 3. Abstracts – contributed papers p.7 4. Abstracts – poster session p.110 1 Workshop Schedule Monday 10 November 2008 All Plenary sessions take place in F4, the main lecture room 9.00 – 9.30 Registration 9.30 – 9.45 Welcome and introduction of day’s theme(s) Taft Broome and Natasha McCarthy 09.45 – 10.45 Billy V. Koen: Toward a Philosophy of Engineering: An Engineer’s Perspective 10. 45 – 11.15 Coffee break 11. 15 – 12.45 Parallel session – submitted papers A. F1 Mikko Martela Esa Saarinen, Raimo P. Hämäläinen, Mikko Martela and Jukka Luoma: Systems Intelligence Thinking as Engineering Philosophy David Blockley: Integrating Hard and Soft Systems Maarten Frannsen and Bjørn Jespersen: From Nutcracking to Assisted Driving: Stratified Instrumental Systems and the Modelling of Complexity B. F4 Ton Monasso: Value-sensitive design methodology for information systems Ibo van de Poel: Conflicting values in engineering design and satisficing Rose Sturm and Albrecht Fritzsche: The dynamics of practical wisdom in IT- professions C. G1 Ed Harris: Engineering Ethics: From Preventative Ethics to Aspirational Ethics Bocong Li: The Structure and Bonds of Engineering Communities Priyan Dias: The Engineer’s Identity Crisis:Homo Faber vs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Renaissance Society of America Annual Meeting
    CHICAGO 30 March–1 April 2017 RSA 2017 Annual Meeting, Chicago, 30 March–1 April Photograph © 2017 The Art Institute of Chicago. Institute The Art © 2017 Photograph of Chicago. Institute The Art © 2017 Photograph The Renaissance Society of America Annual Meeting The Renaissance Society of America Annual Meeting Program Chicago 30 March–1 April 2017 Front and back covers: Jacob Halder and Workshop, English, Greenwich, active 1576–1608. Portions of a Field Armor, ca. 1590. Steel, etched and gilded, iron, brass, and leather. George F. Harding Collection, 1982.2241a-h. Art Institute of Chicago. Contents RSA Executive Board .......................................................................5 RSA Staff ........................................................................................6 RSA Donors in 2016 .......................................................................7 RSA Life Members ...........................................................................8 RSA Patron Members....................................................................... 9 Sponsors ........................................................................................ 10 Program Committee .......................................................................10 Discipline Representatives, 2015–17 ...............................................10 Participating Associate Organizations ............................................. 11 Registration and Book Exhibition ...................................................14 Policy on Recording and Live
    [Show full text]
  • Pico, Plato, and Albert the Great: the Testimony and Evaluation of Agostino Nifo EDWARD P
    Pico, Plato, and Albert the Great: The Testimony and Evaluation of Agostino Nifo EDWARD P. MAHONEY Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (1463-1494) is without doubt one of the most intriguing figures of the Italian Renaissance. It is thus no surprise that he has attracted the attention of many modern scholars. By reason of the varied interests that are reflected in his writings, contrasting interpretations of Pico have been proposed.1 Our purpose here is not to present a new and different picture of Pico but, rather, to offer a contribution to one fruitful area of research pursued by some recent historians of philosophy, namely, Pico's debt to, and 1. For general presentations of Pico's life and thought, see the classic study of Eugenio Garin, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola: Vita e dottirina (Florence: F. Le Monnier, 1937); Garin's magisterial Storia della filosofia italiana, 2d ed. (Turin: G. Einaudi 1966), 1:458-495. Among more recent general accounts are Pierre-Marie Cordier, Jean Pic de la Mirandole (Paris: Debresse, 1958); Engelbert Monnerjahn, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (Wiesbaden: F. Steiner, 1960); Paul Oskar Kristeller, Eight Philosophers of the Italian Renaissance (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1964), pp. 54-71; Giovanni di Napoli, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola e laproblemaύca dottrinale del suo tempo (Rome: Desclee, 1965); Charles Trinkaus, In Our Image and Likeness (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), 2:505-526; and Henri de Lubac, Pic de la Mirandole: Etudes et discussions (Paris: Aubier Montaigne, 1974). 165 166 EDWARD P. MAHONEY use of, medieval philosophy in his overall philosophical enterprise.2 Of particular concern will be the influence of Albert the Great on Pico, which can be established by a connection that has apparently not been noticed by Pico's historians.
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION Agostino Nifo Was a Prolific Writer. During His
    INTRODUCTION Agostino Nifo was a prolific writer. During his lifetime, thirty-five works were published, and after his death another five came out. His books appeared in more than one hundred and sixty editions, from to , at Venice, Pavia, Lyon, Paris, Naples, Florence, Augsburg, Bologna, Rome,Leiden,Basel,Marburg,Troyes,Rouen,Parma,andGenoa.1 In , Nifo published De intellectu,themajorworkofhisearly career, touching on questions of philosophical psychology. Based on a detailed assessment of the views of his predecessors, Nifo in this work presented an analysis of the main issues of Peripatetic noetics, namely origin and immortality of the intellect or rational soul, its relation to the body, its unity and parts, the speculative intellect, and intellectual beatitude. Although the bulk of the work was presumably composed in the early s at Padua, there is good evidence that it was completed and drastically reorientated before publication. This introduction offers a cursory view of Peripatetic noetics and the doctrinal context of Nifo’s work, as well as a short analysis of his shift toward anti-Averroism. It also dwells on Nifo’s use of philosophical and other sources, and on the issue of the ‘lost’ works of Siger of Brabant quoted in De intellectu. Subsequently, the general structure of the work, i.e. its main themes and issues, recurring argumentative strategies, and the fortune of the work are discussed. Finally, I present a note on the transcription of this text and on the works quoted or cited by Nifo. The Introduction is followed by an extensive analytical summary ofthe contents of the work.
    [Show full text]
  • Post Normal Science: Working Deliberatively Within Imperfections
    Copernicus Institute Studium Generale Wageningen Science, Policy and Complex Phenomena 21 March 2007 Post Normal Science: working deliberatively within imperfections Dr. Jeroen P. van der Sluijs Copernicus Institute for Sustainable Development and Innovation Utrecht University & Centre d'Economie et d'Ethique pour l'Environnement et le Développement, Université de Versailles Saint-Quentin-en-Yvelines, France Universiteit Utrecht Copernicus Institute Haugastøl group: Jeroen van der Sluijs; Ragnar Fjelland; Jerome Ravetz; Anne Ingeborg Myhr; Roger Strand; Silvio Funtowicz; Kamilla Kjølberg; Kjellrun Hiis Hauge; Bruna De Marchi; Andrea Saltelli Universiteit Utrecht Copernicus Institute Complex - uncertain -risks Typical characteristics (Funtowicz & Ravetz): • Decisions will need to be made before conclusive scientific evidence is available; • Potential impacts of ‘wrong’ decisions can be huge • Values are in dispute • Knowledge base is characterized by large (partly irreducible, largely unquantifiable) uncertainties, multi- causality, knowledge gaps, and imperfect understanding; • More research ≠ less uncertainty; unforeseen complexities! • Assessment dominated by models, scenarios, assumptions, extrapolations • Many (hidden) value loadings reside in problem frames, indicators chosen, assumptions made Knowledge Quality Assessment is essential Universiteit Utrecht Copernicus Institute Universiteit Utrecht Copernicus Institute 3 paradigms of uncertain risks 'deficit view' • Uncertainty is provisional • Reduce uncertainty, make ever more complex
    [Show full text]
  • On Beautiful Women, Parmigianino
    On BeautifulWomen, Parmigianino,Petrarchismo, and the VernacularStyle ElizabethCropper Among PietroTesta's notes on painting,which were unsys- Finallyon this side of the sheet Testa shows the back of tematicallycollected after his deathin 1650, is one foliodedi- the neck, which mustbe rosyand white and not too deeply catedto "Particolariperfetioni che fannola donnabellissima" furrowedby the line of the spine. (Figs. 1 and 2).1 It is devoted, as the heading indicates, The diagrammaticnature of the marginalsketches makes it to the artist'sdefinitions of thosefeatures that render a woman quiteclear that they werenot intendedto be perfectacademic mostbeautiful. The notes areunusually clear and precise, and models,nor were they drawnfrom life. They werebrief aids in the marginnext to the writtendescription of eachparticular to Testa'sunderstanding, to help him visualizethe contents featureTesta drew a smallillustrative sketch. The rectoof the of the noteshe wastaking-notes thatwere not hisown formu- sheet (Fig. 1) is concernedwith qualitiesof the head and lationof the idealfemale beauty, but that he madeas he read shoulders.Testa required that the hairbe long, fine, blonde, Agnolo Firenzuola'sDialogo delle bellezze delle donne.2 This and knottedsimply. For the browhe madea diagramof two book, completedin 1542, a centurybefore Testa readit, it- squares,representing its correctwide proportions.In the left self drawsupon the visionsof manyearlier writers, and it is squarehe showshow the browshould curve in an arctowards probablythe most completeexposition of the beautyof the the top. The eyebrowsare to be dark,and they too should ideal woman among the multitude of sixteenth-century curve in perfectarches that tapergently towardsthe ends. treatmentsof the theme, beingconcerned not only with her Beautifuleyes are largeand prominent,oval in shape, and perfectfeatures, but also with her colors, proportions,and blue or dark chestnut in color.
    [Show full text]
  • Science on the Verge
    Science on the Verge Andrea Saltelli Centre for the Study of the Sciences and the Humanities (SVT) - University of Bergen (UIB) & Institut de Ciència i Tecnologia Ambientals (ICTA) - Universitat Autonoma de Barcelona (UAB) Symposium at Copernicus Institute, Utrecht, Ruppertbuilding room 134, 25 February 2016, h16.30-18.00 Published by the Consortium for Science, Policy and Outcomes at Arizona State University, March 2016, on Amazon. http://www.amazon.com/Rightful-Place-Science- Verge/dp/0692596380/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1456255907&sr=1-1&keywords=saltelli http://www.andreasaltelli.eu/science-on-the-verge Dan Sarewitz, Preface Almodóvar, Swift, Laputa’s portrayal of XVIII science, science’s present predicaments Chapter 1. Andrea Saltelli, Jerome Ravetz, Silvio Funtowicz, Who will solve the crisis in science? This talk Chapter 2. Andrea Saltelli, Mario Giampietro, The fallacy of evidence based policy Quantification as hypocognition; socially constructed ignorance & uncomfortable knowledge; ancien régime; quantitative story telling Chapter 3. Alice Benessia, Silvio Funtowicz, Never late, never lost, never unprepared Trajectories of innovation and modes of demarcation of science from society: ‘separation’, ‘hybridization’ and ‘substitution’; what contradictions these trajectories generate Chapter 4. Ângela Guimarães Pereira, Andrea Saltelli , Institutions on the verge: working at the science policy interface The special case of the commission’s in house science service; the Joint Research Centre as a boundary institutions; diagnosis,
    [Show full text]
  • The Granada Venegas Family, 1431-1643: Nobility, Renaissance and Morisco Identity
    The Granada Venegas Family, 1431-1643: Nobility, Renaissance and Morisco Identity By Elizabeth Ashcroft Terry A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction Of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in History in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Thomas Dandelet, Chair Professor Jonathan Sheehan Professor Ignacio E. Navarrete Summer 2015 The Granada Venegas Family, 1431-1643: Nobility, Renaissance, and Morisco Identity © 2015 by Elizabeth Ashcroft Terry All Rights Reserved The Granada Venegas Family, 1431-1643: Nobility, Renaissance and Morisco Identity By Elizabeth Ashcroft Terry Doctor of Philosophy in History University of California-Berkeley Thomas Dandelet, Chair Abstract In the Spanish city of Granada, beginning with its conquest by Ferdinand and Isabella in 1492, Christian aesthetics, briefly Gothic, and then classical were imposed on the landscape. There, the revival of classical Roman culture took place against the backdrop of Islamic civilization. The Renaissance was brought to the city by its conquerors along with Christianity and Castilian law. When Granada fell, many Muslim leaders fled to North Africa. Other elite families stayed, collaborated with the new rulers and began to promote this new classical culture. The Granada Venegas were one of the families that stayed, and participated in the Renaissance in Granada by sponsoring a group of writers and poets, and they served the crown in various military capacities. They were royal, having descended from a Sultan who had ruled Granada in 1431. Cidi Yahya Al Nayar, the heir to this family, converted to Christianity prior to the conquest. Thus he was one of the Morisco elites most respected by the conquerors.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Raphael: "The School of Athens" and Its Pre-Text Author(S): Glenn W
    Reading Raphael: "The School of Athens" and Its Pre-Text Author(s): Glenn W. Most Reviewed work(s): Source: Critical Inquiry, Vol. 23, No. 1 (Autumn, 1996), pp. 145-182 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1344080 . Accessed: 01/06/2012 12:49 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Critical Inquiry. http://www.jstor.org Reading Raphael: The School of Athens and Its Pre-Text Glenn W. Most At least since the winter of 1786, when Goethe stood in the Stanza della Segnatura in the Vatican and struggled to decipher the so-called Schoolof Athens (1509-10) as though he were trying "to study Homer in a partially obliterated, damaged manuscript," the question of how this painting is to be understood has often been formulated in terms of whether, and if so how, it is to be read.' The aesthetic appeal of the elegance and vivacity of its colors and forms stands in remarkable tension with the cognitive challenge the figures and their dramatic activity seem to pose.
    [Show full text]
  • Neo-Latin News
    334 SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY NEWS NEO-LATIN NEWS Vol. 50, Nos. 3 & 4. Jointly with SCN. Subscriptions: $15.00 ($20.00 international) for one year; $28.00 ($37.00) for two years; $40.00 ($52.00) for three years. Checks or money orders are payable to Seventeenth-Century News, 4227 TAMU, Col- lege Station, Texas 77843-4227. NLN is the official publica- tion of the American Association for Neo-Latin Studies. Edited by Craig Kallendorf, Texas A&M University; Western European Editor: Gilbert Tournoy, Leuven; Eastern European Editors: Jerzy Axer, Barbara Milewska-Waïbi½ska, and Katarzyna Tomaszuk, Centre for Studies in the Classical Tradi- tion in Poland and East-Central Europe, University of Warsaw. Founding Editors: James R. Naiden, Southern Oregon Univer- sity, and J. Max Patrick, University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee and Graduate School, New York University. ‘In the Footsteps of the Ancients’: The Origins of Humanism from Lovato to Bruni. By Ronald G. Witt. Studies in Medieval and Reformation Thought, 74. Leiden, Boston, and Cologne: Brill, 2000. xiv + 562 pp. $132. Upon picking up this book for the first time, one is likely to think that the last thing the world needs is another general history of humanism in early Renaissance Italy. This book, however, shows how dangerous it is to rely on first impressions. Scholars who are active in this field have been hearing about Witt’s study for some time before it was actually published–it has been some twenty years in the making–and from this point on it will serve as the standard treatment of its subject.
    [Show full text]