Mathematical Solution of the Gibbs Paradox V

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mathematical Solution of the Gibbs Paradox V ISSN 0001-4346, Mathematical Notes, 2011, Vol. 89, No. 2, pp. 266–276. © Pleiades Publishing, Ltd., 2011. Original Russian Text © V. P. Maslov, 2011, published in Matematicheskie Zametki, 2011, Vol. 89, No. 2, pp. 272–284. Mathematical Solution of the Gibbs Paradox V. P. Maslov * Moscow State University Received December 20, 2010 Abstract—In this paper, we construct a new distribution corresponding to a real noble gas as well as the equation of state for it. DOI: 10.1134/S0001434611010329 Keywords: Zeno line, partitio numerorum, phase transition, cluster, dimer, critical tempera- ture, Boyle temperature, jamming effect, Bose–Einstein distribution, Gibbs paradox. Since all the papers of the author dealing with this problem1 were published in English, here we present a short survey of these papers in both Russian and English. The Gibbs paradox has been a stumbling block for many physicists, including Einstein, Gibbs, Planck, Fermi, and many others (15 Nobel laureates in physics studied this problem) as well as for two great mathematicians Von Neumann and Poincare.´ Poincare´ did not obtain the mathematical solution of the Gibbs paradox, but attempted to solve this problem from the philosophical point of view.2 A careful analysis of Poincare’s´ philosophy shows that it is especially constructed so as to justify the contradiction between two physical theories. He writes, in particular, “If a physicist finds a contradiction between two theories that are equally dear to him, he will sometimes say: let’s not worry about this; the intermediate links of the chain may be hidden from us, but we will strongly hold on to its extremities. ... It may turn out that both theories express real relations, while the contradiction lies only in the symbols with which we have attired them.” [2, p. 104]. Just as the rules of arithmetic are used in mathematics, so are those of phenomenological thermody- namics in hydrodynamics, chemistry, and biology. For mathematicians, the Gibbs paradox is equivalent to the statement that 5=2. Therefore, this contradiction in the calculation of entropy obtained by Gibbs is so significant that, from Lenin’s materialistic point of view, Poincare´ “had fallen into heresy.” If symbols for attiring reality are not searched for, then, in order to provide a final solution of this problem, the Maxwell–Boltzmann distribution must be replaced by a new one-particle distribution which coincides with the Maxwell–Boltzmann distribution for certain parameter values and leads not only to the results of natural experiments carried out at the time of Poincare,´ but also correspond to contemporary observations, especially, those performed in the state of weightlessness. In fact, the new distribution presented by the author in this paper implies not only all phenomenologi- cal laws that were discovered by great physicists, but also touches on modern attempts to explain certain aspects of phase transitions, such as fractal dimension, percolation, dimers, and clusters. Up to now, these new theoretical considerations have not been fully tied up to the old conceptions of the classics. The new distribution completely removes this divergence: it contains fractional (fractal) dimensions and dimers, and, most importantly, it contains metastable states, which were, in principle, rejected by the old thermodynamic conception, although they appear in the empirical Van-der-Waals formula, although were not close to the natural experimental data. Later numerous attempts were made to improve similar empirical formulas (to make them fitspecific experiments). *E-mail: [email protected] 1These papers were published in “Mathematical Notes” (the English version of “Matematicheskie Zametki”) beginning with Vol. 85 (5) and ending with Vol. 88 (6). 2TheexistenceoftheGibbsparadoxinthemodelofthePoincare´ ideal gas was established by V.V. Kozlov [1]. 266 MATHEMATICAL SOLUTION OF THE GIBBS PARADOX 267 As Dirac put it, one must understand the solution of the main (central) problem of a particular science, and the solution of the other problems will appear automatically. This reflects a general property of physics. The distribution given here depends on the prescribed interaction potential for the particles. The numerical results that we refer to are related to the Lennard–Jones potential, which is the most often used potential. But even if we take another interaction potential, then we still have the same scheme of defining the critical constants (Tcr, Zcr, ρcr and TB, ρB), and the fundamentals of the theory of the distribution of integers remain unchanged. All the data given by the author coincide with those for noble gases inasmuch as the noble gases coincide with one another by the law of corresponding states. The construction of the distribution in question consists of two parts. The first part is number theory and number-theoretic distributions for fractional (“fractal”) dimensions,3 varying between 3 and 2. This part is the same for all interactions. It is divided into two alternatives (instant stopping, which is an analog of the Bose condensate, and slow descent, which is the alternative to the Bose condensate). The second part is the classical statistics for the scattering of pairs of particles corresponding to the Lennard–Jones potential. This part can be divided into two parts: 2a) without regard for the “dressed” interaction, i.e., only the interaction of two particles is taken into account, which corresponds to a negligibly small interaction with the other particles (Tcr and TB are determined); 2b) the interaction of all particles is taken into account, which allows us to find the constants Zcr, TB, ρB, and the so-called Zeno line. The first part implies that the focus at these points is so large that these quantities are also preserved in the statistics of the number theory of fractional dimension. And the Zeno line Z =1already implies a transition to the classical Boltzmann statistics. 1. NUMBER THEORY 1.1. A Famous Problem of Number Theory The problem of the partition of integers into summands goes back to ancient times. Euler’s survey “Introduction to the analysis of infinite quantities” (“Introductio in analysin infinitorum”) published in 1748 contained a whole chapter dealing with “partitio numerorum” (the partition of numbers into summands). The author has already discussed, several times, the scene from Bulgakov’s novel “Master and Margarita" in which Korov’ev throws money at the spectators of a variety show. The number of spectators in this example corresponds to the number of particles N, while the number of banknotes E , up to a certain unit of energy, corresponds to the energy. Korov’ev threw E banknotes to N spectators, and he must determine the probability of the event that a given number of spectators gets at least one banknote. The probability question is quite difficult in principle. The great mathematician Henri Poincare,´ who headed the Chair of Probability and Mathematical Physics at the University of Paris since the age of 32, devoted Chap. XI of his book [2] to the calculus of probabilities. In it, he gives the standard definition of probability as the ratio of the number of favorable outcomes to the total number of outcomes, and then presents a counterexample to such a definition of probability. He writes that, to this definition, one should add the additional phrase “provided that all outcomes are equiprobable" [2, p. 116 (Russian transl.)] and notes that we have completed a vicious circle—defined probability in terms of probability. Thus, the problem is to define what outcomes should be regarded as equiprobable. “We must look for mathematical ideas," Poincare´ writes, “where they remain pure, i.e., in arithmetic" [2, p. 13 (Russian transl.)]. And that’s what we do. A famous problem in arithmetic (number theory) “partitio numerorum” is to find the number of partitions of a natural number E into summands, for example, 5=1+1+1+1+1=2+1+1+1=2+2+1=2+3=4+1=3+1+1=5, (1) 3Here we do not prove that fractional dimensions considered by the author coincide with Hausdorff dimensions, but use the definitions given by Vershik [3] and Manin [4]. MATHEMATICAL NOTES Vol. 89 No. 2 2011 268 MASLOV where there are 7 possibilities, provided that the order of summation is not taken into account. If the partition is chosen at random (see [2, Chap. IV “Randomness"] then all the variants are equally possible, and it is natural to regard them as equiprobable, i.e., the probability of any variant is 1/7. Thus, we are returning to the “purest" mathematical ideas. The initial well-known identity for the above problem in number theory has the form of the following Diophantine equation for the unknown integers Ni: ∞ ∞ Ni = N, iNi = E . (2) i=0 i=0 If there are no more than N spectators (the theater has N seats, but, possibly, not all are occupied), then when the ratio of E to N varies, the probability may undergo a jump, i.e., a phase transition may occur. Indeed, in the case N =1and in the case N = E (whatever the value of N) there is only one variant (each spectator gets one banknote), its probability for large E is very small. Therefore, there exists a value Ncr (not necessarily unique) for which the number of cases (variants) of the partition of E into Ncr summands is maximum. This number Ncr was calculated by Erdos˝ in [5]. It is √ 1 E Ncr = ln E (1 + o(1)). (3) 2 π2/6 We consider the original mathematical problem in a different setting. Given E and N ≤ N,where N is a prescribed number, we must find N<N for which the number of solutions of the Diophantine inequality ∞ ∞ Ni ≤ N, iNi = E i=0 i=0 is maximum (and hence more probable than any other number).
Recommended publications
  • Gibbs' Paradox and the Definition of Entropy
    Entropy 2008, 10, 15-18 entropy ISSN 1099-4300 °c 2008 by MDPI www.mdpi.org/entropy/ Full Paper Gibbs’ Paradox and the Definition of Entropy Robert H. Swendsen Physics Department, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA 15213, USA E-Mail: [email protected] Received: 10 December 2007 / Accepted: 14 March 2008 / Published: 20 March 2008 Abstract: Gibbs’ Paradox is shown to arise from an incorrect traditional definition of the entropy that has unfortunately become entrenched in physics textbooks. Among its flaws, the traditional definition predicts a violation of the second law of thermodynamics when applied to colloids. By adopting Boltzmann’s definition of the entropy, the violation of the second law is eliminated, the properties of colloids are correctly predicted, and Gibbs’ Paradox vanishes. Keywords: Gibbs’ Paradox, entropy, extensivity, Boltzmann. 1. Introduction Gibbs’ Paradox [1–3] is based on a traditional definition of the entropy in statistical mechanics found in most textbooks [4–6]. According to this definition, the entropy of a classical system is given by the product of Boltzmann’s constant, k, with the logarithm of a volume in phase space. This is shown in many textbooks to lead to the following equation for the entropy of a classical ideal gas of distinguishable particles, 3 E S (E; V; N) = kN[ ln V + ln + X]; (1) trad 2 N where X is a constant. Most versions of Gibbs’ Paradox, including the one I give in this section, rest on the fact that Eq. 1 is not extensive. There is another version of Gibbs’ Paradox that involves the mixing of two gases, which I will discuss in the third section of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Gibbs Paradox: Mixing and Non Mixing Potentials T
    Physics Education 1 Jul - Sep 2016 Gibbs paradox: Mixing and non mixing potentials T. P. Suresh 1∗, Lisha Damodaran 1 and K. M. Udayanandan 2 1 School of Pure and Applied Physics Kannur University, Kerala- 673 635, INDIA *[email protected] 2 Nehru Arts and Science College, Kanhangad Kerala- 671 314, INDIA (Submitted 12-03-2016, Revised 13-05-2016) Abstract Entropy of mixing leading to Gibbs paradox is studied for different physical systems with and without potentials. The effect of potentials on the mixing and non mixing character of physical systems is discussed. We hope this article will encourage students to search for new problems which will help them understand statistical mechanics better. 1 Introduction namics of any system (which is the main aim of statistical mechanics) we need to calculate Statistical mechanics is the study of macro- the canonical partition function, and then ob- scopic properties of a system from its mi- tain macro properties like internal energy, en- croscopic description. In the ensemble for- tropy, chemical potential, specific heat, etc. malism introduced by Gibbs[1] there are of the system from the partition function. In three ensembles-micro canonical, canonical this article we make use of the canonical en- and grand canonical ensemble. Since we are semble formalism to study the extensive char- not interested in discussing quantum statis- acter of entropy and then to calculate the tics we will use the canonical ensemble for in- entropy of mixing. It is then used to ex- troducing our ideas. To study the thermody- plain the Gibbs paradox. Most text books Volume 32, Number 3, Article Number: 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Gibb's Paradox for Distinguishable
    Gibb’s paradox for distinguishable K. M. Udayanandan1, R. K. Sathish1, A. Augustine2 1Department of Physics, Nehru Arts and Science College, Kerala-671 314, India. 2Department of Physics, University of Kannur, Kerala 673 635, India. E-mail: [email protected] (Received 22 March 2014, accepted 17 November 2014) Abstract Boltzmann Correction Factor (BCF) N! is used in micro canonical ensemble and canonical ensemble as a dividing term to avoid Gibbs paradox while finding the number of states and partition function for ideal gas. For harmonic oscillators this factor does not come since they are considered to be distinguishable. We here show that BCF comes twice for harmonic oscillators in grand canonical ensemble for entropy to be extensive in classical statistics. Then we extent this observation for all distinguishable systems. Keywords: Gibbs paradox, harmonic oscillator, distinguishable particles. Resumen El factor de corrección de Boltzmann (BCF) N! se utiliza en ensamble microcanónico y ensamble canónico como un término divisor para evitar la paradoja de Gibbs, mientras se busca el número de estados y la función de partición para un gas ideal. Para osciladores armónicos este factor no viene sin que éstos sean considerados para ser distinguibles. Mostramos aquí que BCF llega dos veces para osciladores armónicos en ensamble gran canónico para que la entropía sea ampliamente usada en la estadística clásica. Luego extendemos esta observación para todos los sistemas distinguibles. Palabras clave: paradoja de Gibbs, oscilador armónico, partículas distinguibles. PACS: 03.65.Ge, 05.20-y ISSN 1870-9095 I. INTRODUCTION Statistical mechanics is a mathematical formalism by which II. CANONICAL ENSEMBLE one can determine the macroscopic properties of a system from the information about its microscopic states.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Particle Indistinguishability, Precisely
    Classical Particle Indistinguishability, Precisely James Wills∗1 1Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method, London School of Economics Forthcoming in The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science Abstract I present a new perspective on the meaning of indistinguishability of classical particles. This leads to a solution to the problem in statisti- cal mechanics of justifying the inclusion of a factor N! in a probability distribution over the phase space of N indistinguishable classical par- ticles. 1 Introduction Considerations of the identity of objects have long been part of philosophical discussion in the natural sciences and logic. These considerations became particularly pertinent throughout the twentieth century with the develop- ment of quantum physics, widely recognized as having interesting and far- reaching implications concerning the identity, individuality, indiscernibility, indistinguishability1 of the elementary components of our ontology. This discussion continues in both the physics and philosophy literature2. ∗[email protected] 1. This menagerie of terms in the literature is apt to cause confusion, especially as there is no clear consensus on what exactly each of these terms mean. Throughout the rest of the paper, I will be concerned with giving a precise definition of a concept which I will label `indistinguishability', and which, I think, matches with how most other commentators use the word. But I believe it to be a distinct debate whether particles are `identical', `individual', or `indiscernible'. The literature I address in this paper therefore does not, for example, overlap with the debate over the status of Leibniz's PII. 2. See French (2000) for an introduction to this discussion and a comprehensive list of references.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 6: Entropy
    Matthew Schwartz Statistical Mechanics, Spring 2019 Lecture 6: Entropy 1 Introduction In this lecture, we discuss many ways to think about entropy. The most important and most famous property of entropy is that it never decreases Stot > 0 (1) Here, Stot means the change in entropy of a system plus the change in entropy of the surroundings. This is the second law of thermodynamics that we met in the previous lecture. There's a great quote from Sir Arthur Eddington from 1927 summarizing the importance of the second law: If someone points out to you that your pet theory of the universe is in disagreement with Maxwell's equationsthen so much the worse for Maxwell's equations. If it is found to be contradicted by observationwell these experimentalists do bungle things sometimes. But if your theory is found to be against the second law of ther- modynamics I can give you no hope; there is nothing for it but to collapse in deepest humiliation. Another possibly relevant quote, from the introduction to the statistical mechanics book by David Goodstein: Ludwig Boltzmann who spent much of his life studying statistical mechanics, died in 1906, by his own hand. Paul Ehrenfest, carrying on the work, died similarly in 1933. Now it is our turn to study statistical mechanics. There are many ways to dene entropy. All of them are equivalent, although it can be hard to see. In this lecture we will compare and contrast dierent denitions, building up intuition for how to think about entropy in dierent contexts. The original denition of entropy, due to Clausius, was thermodynamic.
    [Show full text]
  • Gibbs Paradox of Entropy of Mixing: Experimental Facts, Its Rejection and the Theoretical Consequences
    ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF THEORETICAL CHEMISTRY, VOL. 1, 135±150 (1996) Gibbs paradox of entropy of mixing: experimental facts, its rejection and the theoretical consequences SHU-KUN LIN Molecular Diversity Preservation International (MDPI), Saengergasse25, CH-4054 Basel, Switzerland and Institute for Organic Chemistry, University of Basel, CH-4056 Basel, Switzerland ([email protected]) SUMMARY Gibbs paradox statement of entropy of mixing has been regarded as the theoretical foundation of statistical mechanics, quantum theory and biophysics. A large number of relevant chemical and physical observations show that the Gibbs paradox statement is false. We also disprove the Gibbs paradox statement through consideration of symmetry, similarity, entropy additivity and the de®ned property of ideal gas. A theory with its basic principles opposing Gibbs paradox statement emerges: entropy of mixing increases continuously with the increase in similarity of the relevant properties. Many outstanding problems, such as the validity of Pauling's resonance theory and the biophysical problem of protein folding and the related hydrophobic effect, etc. can be considered on a new theoretical basis. A new energy transduction mechanism, the deformation, is also brie¯y discussed. KEY WORDS Gibbs paradox; entropy of mixing; mixing of quantum states; symmetry; similarity; distinguishability 1. INTRODUCTION The Gibbs paradox of mixing says that the entropy of mixing decreases discontinuouslywith an increase in similarity, with a zero value for mixing of the most similar or indistinguishable subsystems: The isobaric and isothermal mixing of one mole of an ideal ¯uid A and one mole of a different ideal ¯uid B has the entropy increment 1 (∆S)distinguishable = 2R ln 2 = 11.53 J K− (1) where R is the gas constant, while (∆S)indistinguishable = 0(2) for the mixing of indistinguishable ¯uids [1±10].
    [Show full text]
  • PHYS 521: Statistical Mechanics Homework #4
    PHYS 521: Statistical Mechanics Homework #4 Prakash Gautam May 08, 2018 1. Consider an N−dimensional sphere. (a) If a point is chosen at random in an N− dimensional unit sphere, what is the probability of it falling inside the sphere of radius 0:99999999? Solution: The probability of a point falling inside a volume of radius r within a sphere of radius R is given by V (r) p = (1) V (R) where V (x) is the volume of sphere of radius x. The volume of N dimensional sphere of radius x is n=2 (π ) n V (x) = n x Γ 2 + 1 The progression of volume for different radius. 100 n= 2 n= 5 80 n= 24 n= 54 60 40 20 Percentage of Volume 0 0 0:1 0:2 0:3 0:4 0:5 0:6 0:7 0:8 0:9 1 Radius Using this in (1) we obtain ( ) r n p = (2) R This gives the probability of a particle falling within a radius r in a Ndimensional sphere of radius R. □ (b) Evaluate your answer for N = 3 and N = NA(the Avogadro Number) Solution: 23 For r = 0:999999 and N = 3 and N = NA = 6:023 × 10 we get ( ) ( ) × 23 0:999999 3 0:999999 6:023 10 p = = 0:999997000003 p = = 0:0000000000000 3 1 NA 1 1 The probability of a particle falling within the radius nearly 1 in higher two-dimensional sphere is vanishningly small. □ (c) What do these results say about the equivalence of the definitions of entropy in terms of either of the total phase space volume of the volume of outermost energy shell? Solution: Considering a phase space volume bounded by E + ∆ where ∆ ≪ E.
    [Show full text]
  • A Note on Gibbs Paradox 1. Introduction
    1 A note on Gibbs paradox P. Radhakrishnamurty 282, Duo Marvel Layout, Anathapuragate, Yelahanka, Bangalore 560064, India. email: [email protected] Abstract We show in this note that Gibbs paradox arises not due to application of thermodynamic principles, whether classical or statistical or even quantum mechanical, but due to incorrect application of mathematics to the process of mixing of ideal gases. ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Key Words: Gibbs paradox, Amagat’s law, Dalton’s law, Ideal gas mixtures, entropy change 1. Introduction ‘It has always been believed that Gibbs paradox embodied profound thought’, Schrodinger [1]. It is perhaps such a belief that underlies the continuing discussion of Gibbs paradox over the last hundred years or more. Literature available on Gibbs paradox is vast [1-15]. Lin [16] and Cheng [12] give extensive list of some of the important references on the issue, besides their own contributions. Briefly stated, Gibbs paradox arises in the context of application of the statistical mechanical analysis to the process of mixing of two ideal gas samples. The discordant values of entropy change associated with the process, in the two cases: 1. when the two gas samples contain the same species and, 2. when they contain two different species constitutes the gist of Gibbs paradox. A perusal of the history of the paradox shows us that: Boltzmann, through the application of statistical mechanics to the motion of particles (molecules) and the distribution of energy among the particles contained in a system, developed the equation: S = log W + S(0), connecting entropy S of the system to the probability W of a microscopic state corresponding to a given macroscopic equilibrium state of the system, S(0) being the entropy at 0K.
    [Show full text]
  • Dynamical Manifestation of Gibbs Paradox After a Quantum Quench
    Dynamical manifestation of Gibbs paradox after a quantum quench M. Collura1, M. Kormos2 and G. Takács2;3∗ 1The Rudolf Peierls Centre for Theoretical Physics, Oxford University, Oxford, OX1 3NP, United Kingdom 2BME “Momentum” Statistical Field Theory Research Group, H-1117 Budapest, Budafoki út 8. 3BME Department of Theoretical Physics, H-1117 Budapest, Budafoki út 8. (Dated: 29th September 2018) We study the propagation of entanglement after quantum quenches in the non-integrable para- magnetic quantum Ising spin chain. Tuning the parameters of the system, we observe a sudden increase in the entanglement production rate, which we show to be related to the appearance of new quasi-particle excitations in the post-quench spectrum. We argue that the phenomenon is the non- equilibrium version of the well-known Gibbs paradox related to mixing entropy and demonstrate that its characteristics fit the expectations derived from the quantum resolution of the paradox in systems with a non-trivial quasi-particle spectrum. I. INTRODUCTION parameter hx shows another kind of anomalous behav- ior: a sudden increase setting in at the threshold value of A quantum quench is a protocol routinely engineered hx where a new quasi-particle excitation appears in the in cold-atom experiments [1–9]: a sudden change of the spectrum. Hamiltonian of an isolated quantum system followed by Using the physical interpretation of the asymptotic en- a non-equilibrium time evolution. The initial state cor- tanglement of a large subsystem as the thermodynamic responds to a highly excited configuration of the post- entropy of the stationary (equilibrium) state [2, 12, 33, quench Hamiltonian, acting as a source of quasi-particle 37, 38], this can be recognized as arising from the con- excitations [10].
    [Show full text]
  • Statistical Physics University of Cambridge Part II Mathematical Tripos
    Preprint typeset in JHEP style - HYPER VERSION Statistical Physics University of Cambridge Part II Mathematical Tripos David Tong Department of Applied Mathematics and Theoretical Physics, Centre for Mathematical Sciences, Wilberforce Road, Cambridge, CB3 OBA, UK http://www.damtp.cam.ac.uk/user/tong/statphys.html [email protected] { 1 { Recommended Books and Resources • Reif, Fundamentals of Statistical and Thermal Physics A comprehensive and detailed account of the subject. It's solid. It's good. It isn't quirky. • Kardar, Statistical Physics of Particles A modern view on the subject which offers many insights. It's superbly written, if a little brief in places. A companion volume, \The Statistical Physics of Fields" covers aspects of critical phenomena. Both are available to download as lecture notes. Links are given on the course webpage • Landau and Lifshitz, Statistical Physics Russian style: terse, encyclopedic, magnificent. Much of this book comes across as remarkably modern given that it was first published in 1958. • Mandl, Statistical Physics This is an easy going book with very clear explanations but doesn't go into as much detail as we will need for this course. If you're struggling to understand the basics, this is an excellent place to look. If you're after a detailed account of more advanced aspects, you should probably turn to one of the books above. • Pippard, The Elements of Classical Thermodynamics This beautiful little book walks you through the rather subtle logic of classical ther- modynamics. It's very well done. If Arnold Sommerfeld had read this book, he would have understood thermodynamics the first time round.
    [Show full text]
  • The Gibbs Paradox: Early History and Solutions
    entropy Article The Gibbs Paradox: Early History and Solutions Olivier Darrigol UMR SPHere, CNRS, Université Denis Diderot, 75013 Paris, France; [email protected] Received: 9 April 2018; Accepted: 28 May 2018; Published: 6 June 2018 Abstract: This article is a detailed history of the Gibbs paradox, with philosophical morals. It purports to explain the origins of the paradox, to describe and criticize solutions of the paradox from the early times to the present, to use the history of statistical mechanics as a reservoir of ideas for clarifying foundations and removing prejudices, and to relate the paradox to broad misunderstandings of the nature of physical theory. Keywords: Gibbs paradox; mixing; entropy; irreversibility; thermochemistry 1. Introduction The history of thermodynamics has three famous “paradoxes”: Josiah Willard Gibbs’s mixing paradox of 1876, Josef Loschmidt reversibility paradox of the same year, and Ernst Zermelo’s recurrence paradox of 1896. The second and third revealed contradictions between the law of entropy increase and the properties of the underlying molecular dynamics. They prompted Ludwig Boltzmann to deepen the statistical understanding of thermodynamic irreversibility. The Gibbs paradox—first called a paradox by Pierre Duhem in 1892—denounced a violation of the continuity principle: the mixing entropy of two gases (to be defined in a moment) has the same finite value no matter how small the difference between the two gases, even though common sense requires the mixing entropy to vanish for identical gases (you do not really mix two identical substances). Although this paradox originally belonged to purely macroscopic thermodynamics, Gibbs perceived kinetic-molecular implications and James Clerk Maxwell promptly followed him in this direction.
    [Show full text]
  • Demonstration and Resolution of the Gibbs Paradox of the First Kind
    Demonstration and resolution of the Gibbs paradox of the first kind Hjalmar Peters Karlsruhe Institute of Technology, Karlsruhe, Germany E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. The Gibbs paradox of the first kind (GP1) refers to the false increase in entropy which, in statistical mechanics, is calculated from the process of combining two gas systems S1 and S2 consisting of distinguishable particles. Presented in a somewhat modified form, the GP1 manifests as a contradiction to the second law of thermodynamics. Contrary to popular belief, this contradiction affects not only classical but also quantum statistical mechanics. The present paper resolves the GP1 by considering two effects: 1. The uncertainty about which particles are located in S1 and which in S2 contributes to the entropies of S1 and S2. 2. S1 and S2 are correlated by the fact that if a certain particle is located in one system, it cannot be located in the other. As a consequence, the entropy of the total system consisting of S1 and S2 is not the sum of the entropies of S1 and S2. PACS numbers: 05.30.Ch, 05.30.-d, 05.20.-y arXiv:1306.4638v2 [cond-mat.stat-mech] 1 Oct 2013 Demonstration and resolution of the Gibbs paradox of the first kind 2 1. Introduction, motivation, and outline In physics, there are two distinct paradoxes which are both known as the \Gibbs paradox" and are often confused with each other. In the following, the false increase in entropy which, in statistical mechanics, is calculated from the process of combining two gases of the same kind consisting of distinguishable particles will be referred to as the Gibbs paradox of the first kind (GP1) [1{5].
    [Show full text]