Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-44089-9 — Sight, Touch, and Imagination in Byzantium Roland Betancourt Index More Information

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-44089-9 — Sight, Touch, and Imagination in Byzantium Roland Betancourt Index More Information Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-44089-9 — Sight, Touch, and Imagination in Byzantium Roland Betancourt Index More Information Index The family name emerged only in middle Byzantium. Late antique and early Byzantine persons are normally listed by first name; later on, by family name. Abgar, Alexios I Komnenos, absence, see presence Al-Kindī, Achilles Tatius, –, Alkmaeon of Croton, activity, see energeia Anderson, David, adsensus, see synkatathesis Andida, see Nicholas and Theodore of Andida Aelian, Annas, Julia, Aenesidemus, , Annunciation, –, Aeschines, anointing, – Aeschylus, sense organs, – Aetios of Amida, , Anthemios of Tralles, Aetios of Antioch, , , , , antilambano (grasp), –; see also antilepsis; aporroe, , – katalambano, kataleptikos influence on Nemesios, Photios, Michael Psellos and, sight and, – theory of vision, – antilepsis (apprehension), , , ; see also Agathias, , – antilambano air Photios, cognitive medium, – Porphyry, –, linked with hearing, – Aphthonios, –, –, linked with light, – Apollodorus, nerves and, – Apollonius of Tyana, – relation to pneuma, – aporroe (efflux), –, – walking stick, Aetios, aisthesis (sensation), , , Alexander of Aphrodisias, common sense and, applicable to exteriority, differentiated from sense organ, compared to prochysis, mediates phantasia and the body, evil eye, akatalēptikē, see katalambano, kataleptikos Michael Psellos, – akatalēptikē phantasia (non-graspable fantasy), Theophrastus, Akbari, Suzanne Conklin, , apotyposis, see typosis Alcinous, apples, – Alexander of Aphrodisias, , , , –, apprehension, see antilepsis; katalambano, –, kataleptikos; prolepsis aporroe, haptic metaphors for, comparison of common sense and phantasia, Apuleius, source for Nemesios, Arabic science, , – theory of vision, – archetype, see prototype Alexander of Tralles, architecture, © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-44089-9 — Sight, Touch, and Imagination in Byzantium Roland Betancourt Index More Information Index Arethas of Caesarea, – atomists, Aristophanes, theories of vision, – Aristotelianism, relation to Platonism, Augustine of Hippo, Aristotle, Avicenna, common sense, – compared to Pentcheva, – bakterion, see walking stick metaphor compared to Plato, Barber, Charles, , , , –, comparison of taste and smell, Bartsch, Shadi, distinction between doxa and phantasia, Basil of Caesarea, Galen and, enargeia, metaphor as ekphrasis, – evil eye, , , – metaphor of wax for common sense, – on painting, metaxy, Basil, pseudo-, – Michael of Ephesus and, Basilakes, Nikephoros, – notion of interval compared to Plato’s, belief, see doxa on common sense, , , – Belting, Hans, , on metaphor, Beneker, Jeffrey, on touch, – biblical realism, Patriarch Nikephoros and, Birmelin, Ella, phantasia, , Blachernai, usual miracle at, – place in education, Blemmydes, Nikephoros, , , – Plato and Galen and, – in fourteenth century, – pneuma in, – reconciliation, , – Blumenthal, H. J., –, Plotinos and, Blundell, Sue, Poetics, body, mediated to phantasia by aisthesis, remediation and, Bolter, Jay David, source for Nemesios, Bouras Vallianatos, Petros, source of philosophical theories of vision, breath compared to incense, – – Bryennios, Manuel theory of vision, –, – katalambano, kataleptikos, touch as common sense, use of Porphyry, – wax seal metaphor, Butler, Shane, – art, see icons; painting Bydén, Börje, , , , artists’ knowledge of rhetoric, – Byzantium “as if,” see metaphor extramission allegedly preferred in, – ekphrasis and, relationship to late antiquity, enargeia and, , represented in sermons, – icons, –, sources as representative of, – in Michael the Deacon, wrongly thought of as Platonic, necessary for mediation, necessary for medium, Cairns, Douglas, , remediation and, Camille, Michael, – representation and, Cassius Dio, ash on eyes, Catrein, Christoph, aspazomai (greet), , , – Chase, Michael, John of Damascus, Choiroboskos, George, kataspazomai and, Choumnos, Nikephoros, –, – assent, see synkatathesis chrismation, – assumption, see hypolepsis compared to veneration of relics, Asterios of Amaseia, –, –, , Christ – as medium, – Athanasia of Aegina, as united rays, – Athanasios of Alexandria, likened to sight, – Athenaeus, sweetness, – © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-44089-9 — Sight, Touch, and Imagination in Byzantium Roland Betancourt Index More Information Index Christianity, early relationship to other senses, cognitive process, self-awareness and, phantasia, –, , –, touch, veneration compared to pagan, –, typos and, Chrysippos, , , common sensibles, , disagreement with Zeno, commonality of sense phantasia, – across all senses, – Cicero, , Nemesios of Emesa, – city, analogy of touch, – for liturgy, communion, for senses, sight and, – to Protheoria, – comprehend, see perilambano Clark, Elizabeth, – conception, see syllepsis clasp, see periptysso cone, see walking stick metaphor Clement of Alexandria, –, – Constantine VII Porphyrogennetos, , , Stoicism and, – – cognition, see phantasia Constantine IX Monomachos, – active process, Constantine X Doukas, , Annunciation, – Constantine the Philosopher, described with haptic language, , Constas, Maximos (Nicholas), five stages, – contact, see epaphao haptic language, contemplation, see theoria, theoreo Nemesios of Emesa, – veneration and, sight and, – Corrigan, Kevin, stages and sequence of, , , , – Cosmas Indicopleustes, councils, see First Iconoclastic Council; Second synesthesia and, , Iconoclastic Council; Seventh Theodore of Stoudios, – Ecumenical Council veneration and, Craik, Elizabeth, via air, – Cross, via water, – Cyril of Jerusalem, – Cohen, Simon Baron, color, –, , –; see also pharmaka da Vinci, Leonardo, aporroe, damnatio memoriae, difference in perceiving, Darrigol, Olivier, mode of light, De Lacy, Phillip, not subject to touch, – Delling, Gerhard, Plato, Demetrios, common notion Democritus, , , , , – prolepsis and, Photios and, Souda, Demosthenes, Stoic, desire, – common sense, –, –, – icons and, , aisthesis and, dianoesis (thought), Aristotle, , krisis, kritike, – doxa and, , , Photios, Gregory of Nyssa, – synkatathesis (assent) and, hypolepsis, types of, metaphor for wax, – dianoia (thought), –, , Nemesios of Emesa, errant, not a sixth sense, mediates mind and soul, phantasia and, –, –, – phantasia and, –, – like metaphor, – diaphanes (medium), –, ; see also Aristotle; primacy among senses, Choumnos; metaxy; pneuma prolepsis, Galen, © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-44089-9 — Sight, Touch, and Imagination in Byzantium Roland Betancourt Index More Information Index diastema (interval), icon surface as, truth and, – Dickie, Matthew, – virtues, Dio Chrysostom, Elsner, Jaś, , , , , , , , Diogenes Laertius, –, –, –, , embrace, see aspazomai; kataspazomai; phantasia, perilambano; periptysso Dionysios the Areopagite, pseudo-, John of Damascus and Constantine IX commentary on, compared, – on images, physical versus spiritual, Dioscurides, Empedocles, , , , discernment, see katalambano, kataleptikos enargeia (graphical quality, vividness), , discursive thought, see dianoia – Doctrina patrum, “as if” and, , doxa (belief, opinion), , , definition, , common sense and, , , energeia and, – John Philoponos, Epicurus, mediates soul and phantasia, evincing unmediated truth, – Nemesios of Emesa, – function, , phantasia and, , , , icons and, Aristotle’s distinction, katalēptikē phantasia and, prolepsis and, limits, – Souda, Maximos the Confessor on, uncritical, – meaning shift in middle Byzantium, doxastike hypolepsis (belief-making assumption), , –, – metaphor and, drugs, see pharmaka not sight only, , Duffy, John, painting and, Dumbarton Oaks, – perception and, dynamis eikoniste (image-making faculty), phantasia, , – promise unfulfilled, Dyson, Henry, remediation and, – Stoic, Ecumenical Council, see Seventh Ecumenical synesthesia and, , Council translation, education, –; see also Progymnasmata encompassing, see antilambano primary (propaideia), energeia (activity, operation), – rhetoric in, enfold, see periptysso effluence, see aporroe ennoia (thought), efflux, see aporroe envy, – Egeria, epaphao (contact, touch), –, eidola (replicas), , , , Epicureans, – eidos (form), Epicurus, –, , , – compared to morphe, , enargeia, ekphrasis, – Epiphanios of Salamis, “as if” and, episteme (knowledge), , – definition, – ekphrasis and, – episteme and, – perception and, genre versus technique, – Photios, limits, , – sweetness, – medium, – Zeno, metaphor, epistemology, see episteme; truth not sight only, haptic language, painting and, – representation, phantasia and, , – Stoic, –, sight and, via smell and taste, © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-44089-9 — Sight, Touch, and Imagination in Byzantium Roland Betancourt Index More Information Index eros, –, – Frede, Michael, , , evil eye, Freeman, Elizabeth, gaze, – erudition, as representative of Byzantine society, Gabriel, Archangel, – Galen, – ethopoeia, criticism of pneuma, Eucharist criticized by Symeon Seth, compared to icons, critique of Stoics, – John Chrysostom, – critique of walking stick metaphor, –, perception, – phantasia, – depended
Recommended publications
  • The Heraclitus Anecdote: De Partibus Animalium I 5.645A17-23
    Ancient Philosophy 21 (2001) ©Mathesis Publications 1 The Heraclitus Anecdote: De Partibus Animalium i 5.645a17-23 Pavel Gregoric Chapter 5 of the first book of Aristotle’s De Partibus Animalium contains a short self-contained treatise (644b22-645a36) which has been characterised as a ‘protreptic to the study of animals’ (Peck in Aristotle 1937, 97). Such a charac- terisation of the treatise may be misleading, because Aristotle does not seem to have composed it in order to motivate his audience to go out in the field and study animals, but rather to kindle their interest in the scientific account of ani- mals which he is about to provide. It is reasonable to suppose that Aristotle’s audience, eager to learn something valuable and dignified, needed an explanation of why they should like to hear, amongst other animals, about sponges, snails, grubs, and other humble creatures which are displeasing even to look at, not to mention witnessing the dissections that might have accompanied Aristotle’s lec- tures on animals (cf. Bonitz 1870, 104a4-17; Lloyd 1978). Aristotle explains why such ignoble animals deserve a place in a scientific account of animals and he illustrates that with an anecdote about Heraclitus. So one must not be childishly repelled by the examination of the humbler animals. For in all things of nature there is some- thing wonderful. And just as Heraclitus is said to have spoken to the visitors who wanted to meet him and who stopped as they were approaching when they saw him warming himself by the oven (e‰don aÈtÚn yerÒmenon prÚw t“ fipn“)—he urged them to come in without fear (§k°leue går aÈtoÁw efisi°nai yarroËntaw), for there were gods there too (e‰nai går ka‹ §ntaËya yeoÊw)—so one must approach the inquiry about each animal without aversion, since in all of them there is something natural and beautiful.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Testimony on the Platonist Gaius
    A New Testimony on the Platonist Gaius Michele Trizio PART FROM a single Delphic inscription (FD III.4 103), the testimonia of the life and work of second-century AMiddle Platonist Gaius fall into two classes.1 The first includes first-hand observations of later philosophers up to Proclus: Porphyry, for instance, reports that Gaius was one of several authors read regularly by Plotinus’ entourage.2 Galen tells us that he followed the classes of two of Gaius’ pupils in Pergamum and Smyrna respectively.3 As to Proclus, he twice mentions Gaius, among other Platonists, in his commentaries on the Republic and the Timaeus.4 The second class of testimonia includes statements concerning Gaius’ scholarship on Plato in three important Greek MSS. The first of these, Paris.gr. 1962, is a ninth-century MS. of the so-called ‘philosophical collection’, which, among others entries, contains a pinax at f. 146v men- tioning ᾿Αλβίνου τῶν Γαίου σχολῶν ὑποτυπώσεων πλατωνικῶν δογµάτων. That is to say, Albinus’ edition of Gaius’ scholia on 1 On Gaius and the related bibliography see J. Whittaker, “Gaius,” in R. Goulet (ed.), Dictionnaire de philosophes antiques III (Paris 2000) 437–440. All testimonia on Gaius are collected and discussed with reference to previous literature in A. Gioè, Filosofi medioplatonici del II secolo d.c. (Naples 2002). 2 V.Plot. 14, ed. P. Henry and H.-R. Schwyzer, Plotini opera I (Leiden 1951) 19.10–14. 3 De propriorum animi 41, ed. W. de Boer (CMG V.4.1.1, Leipzig 1937); Libr.propr. 2.1, ed. V. Boudon-Millot (Paris 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Synopsis of the Aristotelian Commentary Tradition (In Less Than Sixty Minutes)
    HISTORICAL SYNOPSIS OF THE ARISTOTELIAN COMMENTARY TRADITION (IN LESS THAN SIXTY MINUTES) Fred D. Miller, Jr. CHAPTER 1 PERIPATETIC SCHOLARS Aristotle of Stagira (384–322 BCE) Exoteric works: Protrepticus, On Philosophy, Eudemus, etc. Esoteric works: Categories, Physics, De Caelo, Metaphysics, De Anima, etc. The legend of Aristotle’s misappropriated works Andronicus of Rhodes: first edition of Aristotle’s works (40 BCE) Early Peripatetic commentators Boethus of Sidon (c. 75—c. 10 BCE) comm. on Categories Alexander of Aegae (1st century CE)comm. on Categories and De Caelo Adrastus of Aphrodisias (early 1st century) comm. on Categories Aspasius (c. 131) comm. on Nicomachean Ethics Emperor Marcus Aurelius establishes four chairs of philosophy in Athens: Platonic, Peripatetic, Stoic, Epicurean (c. 170) Alexander of Aphrodisias (late 2nd —early 3rd century) Extant commentaries on Prior Analytics, De Sensu, etc. Lost comm. on Physics, De Caelo, etc. Exemplar for all subsequent commentators. Comm. on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Only books 1—5 of Alexander’s comm. are genuine; books 6—14 are by ps.-Alexander . whodunit? Themistius (c. 317—c. 388) Paraphrases of Physics, De Anima, etc. Paraphrase of Metaphysics Λ (Hebrew translation) Last of the Peripatetics CHAPTER 2 NEOPLATONIC SCHOLARS Origins of Neoplatonism Ammonius Saccas (c. 175—242) forefather of Neoplatonism Plotinus (c. 205—260) the Enneads Reality explained in terms of hypostases: THE ONE—> THE INTELLECT—>WORLD SOUL—>PERCEPTIBLE WORLD Porphyry of Tyre (232–309) Life of Plotinus On the School of Plato and Aristotle Being One On the Difference Between Plato and Aristotle Isagoge (Introduction to Aristotle’s Categories) What is Neoplatonism? A broad intellectual movement based on the philosophy of Plotinus that sought to incorporate and reconcile the doctrines of Plato, Pythagoras, and Aristotle with each other and with the universal beliefs and practices of popular religion (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Arabatzis.Ffinal Version
    Michael of Ephesus and the philosophy of living things (In De partibus animalium, 22.25–23.9) GEORGE ARABATZIS Introduction As in other scientific disciplines, for biological knowledge the Byzantines depended largely on ancient Greek science, especially of the Hellenistic pe- riod. Under the appellation ‘biology’, we should understand those sciences which had to do with medicine, pharmacology, veterinary medicine, zool- ogy, and botany.1 As regards theories about living things (animals and plants), Byzantium carried on a tradition that synthesized elements from an- cient Greek philosophy and the Christian religion (especially the philosophy of the Church Fathers). The crucial point here is the introduction by Christianity of the theory of the historical creation of the world, from its initial elements to the formation of humans, who were seen as the crown of the universe. In a rural civilization like Byzantium, proximity to the world of plants and animals produced popular literary works that played with the idea of human primacy over all other living beings, primarily animals, often through prosopopoeia.2 Since Greco-Roman times, Aristotelian reflection on the conditions of knowledge of biological phenomena, in other words Aristotle’s biological epistemology, had fallen into oblivion;3 what re- mained from his contribution to biology was the collection of natural data and curiosities that offered, together with other sources, material for late ancient compilations. We have to wait for the eleventh–twelfth centuries in order to see, in the person of Michael of Ephesus, a commentator on Aristotle’s philosophy of biology, and this paper will focus on him.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS in BYZANTIUM* York: George Braziller
    Linos G. BENAKIS Vahanian, G. (1965b, December 8). Swallowed Vahanian, G. (1966b). Theology and ‘The End UDC 1/14:17 up by Godlessness. The ChristianCen- of the Age of Religion’. (J. B. Metz, Linos G. BENAKIS tury, LXXXII(49), 1505-1507. Ed.) Concilium: Theology in the Age Vahanian, G. (1966a). No other God. New of Renewal, XVI, 99-110. ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS IN BYZANTIUM* York: George Braziller. Abstract This paper argues that research in the primary sources must precede the investigation of Byzan- tine philosophy. Two points are to be considered, on the one hand, the gathering of texts, and, on the other hand, the study of texts in relation to their sources. Thus the external evidence as well as the internal evidence of texts should be examined. In this double regard, the manuscripts containing Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics are considered. Their authors are Michael of Ephesos, Eustratios of Nicaea, “Anonymus”, Heliodoros of Prussa, Georgios Pachymeres, Michael Psellos, John Italos, Nikephoros Blemmydes, George Gemistos Plethon. Keywords: Byzantine philosophy, Aristotle’s Byzantine Commentators, Michael of Ephesos, Eustratios of Nicaea, “Anonymus”, Heliodoros of Prussa, Georgios Pachymeres, Michael Psellos, John Italos, Nikephoros Blemmydes, George Gemistos Plethon. This paper is primarily technical in nature. b. The study of texts in relation to their It will argue that when one begins to examine a sources. Namely, the identification of less investigated area of the field of Byzantine sources – distinguishing between instan- Philosophy, research in the primary sources ces of mere borrowing and instances of a must still precede every interpretative act and more critical incorporation of such sour- critical approach.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Philosophy in Michael Psellos: the Chronographia Read in Relation to His Philosophical Work
    Political philosophy in Michael Psellos: the Chronographia read in relation to his philosophical work DOMINIC J. O’MEARA The political thought explicitly or implicitly present in Michael Psellos’ historical masterpiece, the Chronographia, has attracted the attention of modern readers and given rise to studies using diverse methods and reaching diverse results.1 In general, however, this has been done without taking much account of the large body of texts produced by Psellos in relation to his teaching activities as a philosopher, with one notable exception: the autobiographical section in the Chronographia (VI 36ff.) where Psellos presents his philosophical education and interests, a passage evidently con- nected with Psellos’ own philosophical work. The absence of research com- paring the political thought of the Chronographia with what might be found in Psellos’ philosophical works has the disadvantage of giving the impres- sion of a double personality in Psellos: the political thinker and actor of the Chronographia and the teacher in the philosophical works. There is also the danger that we may deprive ourselves of means allowing us better to under- stand passages in the Chronographia involving fairly technical concepts and theoretical constructs which find fuller expression in the philosophical works, with the result that we may fail to grasp, or even misinterpret, Psellos’ views in the Chronographia. One reason for this situation is the long-standing absence of critical edi- tions of Psellos’ philosophical works, a problem which is now slowly being resolved. A further reason may be that historians might be tempted to think sometimes (may Clio forgive my rudeness!) that they can adequately dis- cuss philosophers of the past without having a serious grasp of their phi- losophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Observations on Michael of Ephesus’ Comments on Nicomachean Ethics X
    SOME OBSERVATIONS ON MICHAEL OF EPHESUS’ COMMENTS ON NICOMACHEAN ETHICS X Katerina Ierodiakonou A study of the Byzantine twelfth-century composite commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics cannot pass over Michael of Ephesus’ contribution to it. For it is not only that Michael is undoubtedly the writer of the comments on books V, IX and X,1 it has also been plausibly suggested that it was he who compiled this commentary, bringing together the comments of Aspasius, Eustratios and two anonymous commentators.2 He thus produced an invaluable tool for a better understanding of Aristotle’s ethical theories, a tool which proved to be of great help not only to the Byzantines, but also to the students of Aristotle in the medieval West, who extensively used its Latin translation made by Robert Grosseteste in the thirteenth century. Nevertheless, we know next to nothing about Michael’s life, and little attention has been given so far to the content of his comments on the Nicomachean Ethics. At least we now can say with confidence, thanks to Browning’s and Ebbesen’s research, that he lived not in the eleventh century, as Praechter had argued, but in the twelfth century, and more- over that he most probably, together with Eustratios, belonged to Anna Komnena’s circle of intellectuals.3 It still remains unsettled, however, whether Michael wrote his commentaries only while he was working under Anna, or whether he worked on Aristotle also before and after this period.4 On the other hand, we seem to be well informed about the remarkable breadth of his writings as an Aristotelian commenta- tor.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernity
    The New Synthese Historical Library Volume 57 Moral Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernity edited by Jill Kraye and Risto Saarinen MORAL PHILOSOPHY ON THE THRESHOLD OF MODERNITY The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 57 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, University of Chicago RICHARD SORABJI, University of London Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Thomas-Institut, Universität zu Köln ROGER ARIEW, Virginia Polytechnic Institute E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University of Waterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University PAUL HOFFMAN, University of California, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, Northwestern University, Evanston ALAIN DE LIBERA, Université de Genève JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Università degli Studi di Genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN WOOD, Stanford University The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. MORAL PHILOSOPHY ON THE THRESHOLD OF MODERNITY Edited by JILL KRAYE Warburg Institute, University of London, U.K. and RISTO SAARINEN University of Helsinki, Finland Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data ISBN 1-4020-3000-2 (HB) ISBN 1-4020-3001-0 (e-book) Published by Springer, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Sold and distributed in North, Central and South America by Springer, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Springer, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, The Netherlands.
    [Show full text]
  • ANTHONY PREUS: Curriculum Vitae
    A. Preus, CV, April 27, 2020, page 1 ANTHONY PREUS: Curriculum Vitae Department of Philosophy Tel: 607-777-2886 (Philosophy) Binghamton University 607-777-2646 (CIW) Binghamton, NY 13902-6000 Fax: 607-777-6255 E-mail:[email protected] Degrees 1968 Ph.D. in Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University l966 M.A. in Literae Humaniores, Oxford University 1962 B.A. in Literae Humaniores, Oxford university 1958 B.A. in Classics, Summa Cum Laude etc., Luther College Positions 2009- Distinguished Teaching Professor of Philosophy 2000-2016 Collegiate Professor, College in the Woods, Binghamton University 1994-2000 Chair Department of Philosophy Spring 1993 Acting Chair Department of Philosophy Spring 1991 Acting Chair Department of Philosophy 1980- Professor of Philosophy, Binghamton University 1980-1998 Adjunct Associate Professor, Dept. of Preventive Medicine, Upstate Medical Center 1980-1983 Chair, Department of Classical and Near East Studies 1973-1974 Resident Director, SUNY Mediterranean Studies 1971-1980 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Binghamton University 1966-1971 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Binghamton University 1964-1966 Acting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Binghamton University Grants and Awards March 1983 Visiting Philosopher, Tougaloo College 1982-1983 NEH Summer Institute (Ethical Issues in the Human Services, $67,500) 1980-1981 NEH Demonstration Grant (Course Development, $20,000) 1978-1979 National Humanities Institute Fellow at the University of Chicago 1978 SUNY Foundation Summer Grants 1977-1978 NSF Grant (Early
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernity
    The New Synthese Historical Library Volume 57 Moral Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernity edited by Jill Kraye and Risto Saarinen MORAL PHILOSOPHY ON THE THRESHOLD OF MODERNITY The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 57 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, University of Chicago RICHARD SORABJI, University of London Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Thomas-Institut, Universität zu Köln ROGER ARIEW, Virginia Polytechnic Institute E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University of Waterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University PAUL HOFFMAN, University of California, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, Northwestern University, Evanston ALAIN DE LIBERA, Université de Genève JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Università degli Studi di Genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN WOOD, Stanford University The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. MORAL PHILOSOPHY ON THE THRESHOLD OF MODERNITY Edited by JILL KRAYE Warburg Institute, University of London, U.K. and RISTO SAARINEN University of Helsinki, Finland Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data ISBN 1-4020-3000-2 (HB) ISBN 1-4020-3001-0 (e-book) Published by Springer, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Sold and distributed in North, Central and South America by Springer, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Springer, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, The Netherlands.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Sophistical Refutations: a Translation with Introduction
    Aristotle’s Sophistical Refutations: A Translation with Introduction, Commentary, and Appendices John Myles McCarthy A dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Boston College Morrissey College of Arts and Sciences Graduate School September, 2018 © Copyright 2018 JOHN MYLES MCCARTHY Aristotle’s Sophistical Refutations: A Translation with Introduction, Commentary, and Appendices John Myles McCarthy Advisor: Gary Michael Gurtler, S.J., Ph.D. ABSTRACT Aristotle’s Sophistical Refutations (SE) investigates the five devices which sophists employ to appear wise in dialogue. The sophist’s primary device is the sophistical refutation which is a particular kind of fallacy. A sophistical refutation is a merely apparent refutation. Thus, the fallacy has two causes: the “causa apparentiae” and the “causa non existentiae." A genuine refutation is a syllogism based on an interlocutor’s opinions that leads necessarily to a conclusion which contradicts some other established position of the interlocutor. The sophist desires especially the apparent refutation of his opponent because the greatest glory follows upon seeming to expose the ultimate defect in opponent’s understanding, a contradiction. The SE neither accounts for every cause of error nor every type of false reasoning; “ad” arguments like ad baculum or ad hominem are not in investigated in the SE because they are not apparent refutations. After a description of the SE’s subject matter, the dissertation’s introduction locates the role of the SE in Aristotle’s Organon and explains why a dialectician would investigate and untie sophisms. Sophistic is the sham portion of the dialectic which is a ii universal art (τέχνη) of syllogizing from endoxes to the contradiction of an interlocutor.
    [Show full text]
  • Programma Delle Sessioni Ordinarie E Speciali
    MIUR Università di Bari European Graduate Programmi Dipartimento di School for Ancient and InterLink Scienze Filosofiche Medieval Philosophy Knowledge and Happiness: Philosophy as a Way of Life in the Middle Ages International Research Workshop in the context of the InterLink Project «Soggetto e statuto della filosofia nel Medioevo. Nuove prospettive di ricerca nell’edizione critica dei testi e nelle metodologie di indagine storiografica» and of EGSAMP (European Graduate School for Ancient and Medieval Philosophy) Promoted and coordinated by Pasquale Porro & Andreas Speer Lama di Luna (Montegrosso, Andria) July 22 / August 2, 2007 MIUR – InterLink Programmi per l’incentivazione del processo di internazionalizzazione del sistema universitario (D.M. 5 agosto 2004 n. 262, art. 23) http://interlink.cineca.it/ EGSAMP European Graduate School For Ancient and Medieval Philosophy www.egsamp.uni-koeln.de Università di Bari Dipartimento di Scienze Filosofiche Direttore: Prof. Ferruccio De Natale www.filosofia.uniba.it Sponsored by / con il patrocinio e il contributo di: Università di Bari Consiglio di Amministrazione Magnifico Rettore: Prof. Corrado Petrocelli Facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia Preside: Prof. Grazia Distaso Regione Puglia Assessorato al Mediterraneo Settore Mediterraneo Ufficio Pace, Intercultura e Integrazione tra i Popoli Assessore: Prof. Silvia Godelli Comune di Andria Assessorato alla Cultura Nell’ambito del Progetto «Il dialogo filosofico, scientifico e religioso tra le culture del Mediterraneo in età sveva e angioina» Assessore: Prof. Paolo Farina Provincia di Bari Assessorato al Turismo Assessore: Dott. Sebastiano De Feudis Knowledge and Happiness: Philosophy as a Way of Life in the Middle Ages International Research Workshop in the context of the InterLink Project «Soggetto e statuto della filosofia nel Medioevo.
    [Show full text]