1 Self-Consciousness, Embodiment, and the Narrativizing Self

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Self-Consciousness, Embodiment, and the Narrativizing Self N o t e s 1 Self-Consciousness, Embodiment, and the Narrativizing Self 1 . Fitzgerald critiques contemporary metaphysics and argues for physiological psychology as a basis for future metaphysics. 2 . Other key meditations on this methodological issue include James 1884, Dewey 1886, Bain 1893, and Ladd 1913. 3 . Rick Rylance offers an excellent account of associationism in Victorian Psychology and British Culture, 1850–1880. 4 . I n Popular Fiction and Brain Science in the Late Nineteenth Century, Ann Stiles describes the biological determinism of late-nineteenth-century neurology, particularly in relation to cerebral localization. Stiles explores how selected Gothic romances reacted to this determinism. 5 . By 1903, Ladd felt that psycho-physical parallelism had been dominant “a decade or two ago” (374). He emphasized the complexity of the stream of con- sciousness, and emphasizes a “real dynamical connexion” between “observed changes, produced by other things upon the thing-like body, [and] . changes in self-conscious states” (376). 6 . Others wondered in the pages of MIND , “Is Bergson’s Philosophy Monistic?” (Radhakrishnan 332). 7 . Chapter 3 of this study features and extended discussion of Joyce’s engagement with Bergson. See pages 79–80. 8 . Behaviorism, which became the dominant theoretical approach in American psychology, rejected introspection (and the problem of perspectives) altogether. As a methodology, behaviorism has infamous limitations while also providing some useful insight. 9 . The standard analogue of this is from chemistry: when you combine carbon atoms in a certain way, you get coal; in another, diamond; in still another, graphite. In this view, the properties of coal, diamond, and graphite could not be predicted by the properties of the atom. 196 Notes 10 . That is, how does this image correspond to or differ from the accumulated generic image, and what causal logic might reconcile them as part of the same framework? 11 . In its implication of a hierarchical, linear developmental arc from embodi- ment into abstraction, Ward’s model is reductive of experience. He does not consider the implications of his observation that higher-level abstraction is continually influenced by the organic sensations. He does not trace out the instability implicit in his “purely formal notion of a subject or pure ego” beyond the bounds of self-consciousness. He does not link the inchoate nar- rativity implied in proliferating self-images to the precipitation of personhood, nor does he consider the agency of narrativity as a locus for a sense of mastery or identification. He does not link personhood to shifting social contexts. He does not consider the possibility of discordant self-images, in which one’s pre- vious self-formulation is recognized as a form of bad faith. He does not con- sider how, within experiences of alienating or discordant self-consciousness, the correlation between primary affectivity and embodiment might lead to a renewed identification with the body (death drive). 12 . There were other perspectives that maintained the importance of self-consciousness while rejecting idealism. S. H. Mellone, for example, advo- cates rejecting the transcendental self, and believes the empirical self should go along with it. He believes that “the real self is that which is known and realized or lived in and through the actual process of conscious life” (Mellone 1901, 323). Mellone views self-consciousness as a product of the tendency of knowledge to go beyond itself, and thus holds an expansive view of the possible access to truth in self-consciousness. 13 . Royce views normal self-consciousness as a matrix of narrative processing, with self at the center: “the self of normal self-consciousness . is felt at any moment as this relatively stable group of inner states; it is also felt or conceived as the supposed spontaneous controller of the general or of the principal cur- rent of successive conscious states; it is remembered or expected as the past or future self, which is taken to be more or less precisely the same as the present self; and finally, it is viewed as having a curious collection of exterior func- tions that involve its actual value, potency, prowess, reputation, or office, in its external social relations to other actual or ideal selves, e.g., to its neighbors, to humanity at large, or, in case one’s faith extends so far, to God” (438). 14 . The inward turn of modernism is related to the methodology of introspection associated with psychology. Introspection was one approach, along with new experimental procedures. While its comparative advantage or disadvantage was often debated, it was consistently understood as what we colloquially call an “approach”—that is, a way into understanding particular dynamics, rather than a totalizing method. The use of introspection to capture aspects of con- sciousness is not unlike the way interior monologue emerges in fiction. Inner speech crept out of quotation marks through free indirect discourse before being expanded to consume the diegetic world of the story. This involved an alternating formal structure between the character viewed within experi- ence (in action) from outside and from within. As such, it involved building a Notes 197 portrait of volition and conduct that was multifactorial, and it was conducive to tracking continuities between the physical and mental. 15 . Galen Strawson has described self as a particularly malleable concept, verging on meaninglessness, because of the multiplicity of types of self that have been asserted in philosophical writings on the subject. 16 . Siegel is describing Dieter Henrich’s and Sydney Shoemaker’s positions, rather than asserting his own. 17 . Deleuze’s model is not simplistic: he views the self’s interaction with the other as crucial to self, seeing “the Other as the expression of a possible world ” (261). For Deleuze, “the I and the Self . are immediately characterized by functions of development or explication: not only do they experience qualities in general as already developed in the extensity of their system, but they tend to explicate or develop the world expressed by the other, either in order to participate in it or to deny it” (260). 2 Minding the Gap: Embodiment, Narrativity, and Identification in UNDER WESTERN EYES 1 . Michael Greaney focuses on the plot level, arguing that “in a culture of sur- veillance and superstition, Razumov is a blind spot, misread by the Russian authorities, by his would-be comrades, and, inevitably, by the first-time reader of the novel” (160). 2 . C o n r a d d e s c r i b e s Under Western Eyes as “the sustained psychology of a mood having its origin in a crime.” This chapter focuses upon Razumov’s individ- ual psychology and mood, rather than any collective psychology or mood. An oft-cited line from one of Conrad’s letters announces that the novel is “concerned with nothing but ideas, to the exclusion of everything else.” This would appear to be a problem for my emphasis upon embodiment and ontol- ogy. However, given the full quote—“I am concerned with nothing but ideas, to the exclusion of everything else, with no arrière pensée of any kind”—and thinking of it along with his statement about psychology, we see Conrad here distancing himself from readings of the novel as political statements (October 20, 1911, letter to Garnett; from Critical Heritage 236). Other critics who have offered political readings tend to implicitly agree, focusing upon the operations of the political and the fundamental unreadability of the novel as a coherent political statement. For a concise summary of influential political readings of the novel, see Greaney (153–5). This chapter supplements political readings by looking at the operations of ideas as part of experience in psychological and physical terms. 3 . Edward Said notes this change: “the dramatic protocol of much of Conrad’s fiction is the swapped yarn, the historical report, the mutually exchanged leg- end, the musing recollection . [which] implies . a speaker and a hearer . If we go through Conrad’s major work we will find, with the notable exception 198 Notes of Under Western Eyes , that the narrative is presented as transmitted orally” (qtd. in Greaney 3). 4 . This chapter focuses upon the materiality of identity in the St. Petersburg sec- tion of the novel, and the narrativity and sociality of identity in the Geneva section. While this division occurs for convenience, it also roughly tracks the emphases of each section. 5 . A note on method: my approach is to draw out how this novel creates an implicit, partial model of how consciousness works and what functions it fulfills. In pur- suing this goal, my reading of Under Western Eyes differs significantly from polit- ical and deconstructive readings of the novel. It considers dynamics, processes, and change involving identity, identification, thinking, and embodiment. 6 . By asserting this shift, I am offering a somewhat different perspective from crit- ics who emphasize epistemological problems throughout Conrad’s work. John Peters offers a useful summary of these perspectives (124) in his work Conrad and Impressionism , and he himself argues that the novels contain a “common element” of demonstrating that “the epistemological process is individual, and [Conrad’s] impressionism leads to human subjectivity” (123). Peters’ interest in the subjectivity of what we know is based upon factors (“physical circum- stances”) that make his interest in the “uncertainty” and character of knowl- edge complementary to my interest in how Conrad evokes the production and functionality of consciousness. 7 . That is to say, plotting involves a movement into instability followed by resolu- tion into relative order. 8 . S e e p a g e s 3 4 – 3 5 . 9 . Razumov’s delayed decision sounds a familiar note to Conrad scholars. Like Jim, Razumov arrives at consciousness of a choice he has made retrospectively (Jim, famously, only realizes he has jumped off the Patna , abandoning a ship full of helpless passengers, after the fact.
Recommended publications
  • The Personalized A-Theory of Time and Perspective
    The Personalized A-Theory of Time and Perspective Vincent Conitzer∗ Abstract A-theorists and B-theorists debate whether the “Now” is metaphysically distinguished from other time slices. Analogously, one may ask whether the “I” is metaphysically distin- guished from other perspectives. Few philosophers would answer the second question in the affirmative. An exception is Caspar Hare, who has devoted two papers and a book to arguing for such a positive answer. In this paper, I argue that those who answer the first question in the affirmative – A-theorists – should also answer the second question in the affirmative. This is because key arguments in favor of the A-theory are more effective as arguments in favor of the resulting combined position, and key arguments against the A-theory are ineffective against the combined position. Keywords: metaphysics, philosophy of time, philosophy of self. ∗Departments of Computer Science, Economics, and Philosophy, Duke University, Box 90129, Durham, NC 27708, USA; Email: [email protected] 1 1 Introduction In a series of unconventional but lucid works, Caspar Hare has laid out and defended a theory of egocentric presentism (or, in his more recent work, perspectival realism), in which a distinguished individual’s experiences are present in a way that the experiences of others are not (Hare, 2007, 2009, 2010). Closely related ideas appear in the writings of others. One example is Valberg (2007)’s notion of the “personal horizon,” especially considering his discussion of “the truth in solipsism” and his insistence that “my” horizon is really “the” (preeminent) horizon. Merlo (2016)’s “subjectivist view of the mental” is arguably even more closely related; he argues that “one’s own mental states are metaphysically privileged vis-a-vis` the mental states of others” and discusses in detail the relationship of his view to Hare’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Space and Time - Shahn Majid
    FUNDAMENTALS OF PHYSICS - Philosophy of Space And Time - Shahn Majid PHILOSOPHY OF SPACE AND TIME Shahn Majid Queen Mary, University of London, London, UK. Keywords: Born-reciprocity, relativity, quantum theory, momentum space, spacetime continuum, Planck scale, quantum gravity, quantum spacetime, quantum group, noncommutative geometry, relative realism, nature of time Contents 1. Introduction 2. Prehistory of Space and Time 3. Spacetime Continuum 4. Failure of the Spacetime Continuum 5. Quantum Geometry 6. Quantum Spacetime and Experiment 7. Time, Matter and Dark Energy 8. Philosophical Perspective 9. Conclusions Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch Summary It is easy to think that our notions of space and time have barely changed since the ancient Greeks. With the proviso of certain relativistic effects, we more or less take them for granted as the backdrop in which all other Sciences take place. But is this correct? We will see in this chapter that since the 1950s it has been clear that the assumption of a spacetime continuum is actually unjustified and could well be wrong. Only in the 1980s, however, were serious alternatives developed by mathematicians and since then a growing confluence of philosophical ideology, mathematical innovation and the possibility of experimental test has led to the emergence of a new science of space and time. UNESCO-EOLSS In principle thereSAMPLE are as many approaches toCHAPTERS spacetime as there are to the unsolved problem of a unified theory of quantum gravity. However, we will explain how a coherent new science has emerged in spite of that, based on the idea of „quantum spacetime‟ as a common framework.
    [Show full text]
  • A Manifestation of All Life : Intersections of Virtue Ethics, Philosophy of Emotion, and Philosophy of Literature
    University of Louisville ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository Electronic Theses and Dissertations 12-2010 A manifestation of all life : intersections of virtue ethics, philosophy of emotion, and philosophy of literature. Derek Lee Penwell 1965- University of Louisville Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.library.louisville.edu/etd Recommended Citation Penwell, Derek Lee 1965-, "A manifestation of all life : intersections of virtue ethics, philosophy of emotion, and philosophy of literature." (2010). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 1113. https://doi.org/10.18297/etd/1113 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. This title appears here courtesy of the author, who has retained all other copyrights. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A MANIFESTATION OF ALL LIFE: INTERSECTIONS OF VIRTUE ETHICS, PHILOSOPHY OF EMOTION, AND PHILOSOPHY OF LITERATURE By Derek Lee Penwell B.R.E., Great Lakes Christian College, 1987 M.A.R., Emmanuel School of Religion, 1990 M.Div., Lexington Theological Seminary D.Min., Lexington Theological Seminary A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Louisville in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Introduction to Philosophy of Psychedelics (Oxford University
    Introduction to Philosophy of Psychedelics (Oxford University Press, 2021) Chris Letheby Please quote from published version. 1 Introduction The unacceptability of psychedelic therapy… stems in part at least from this fundamental empirical fact: Through the psychedelic experience persons tend to accept beliefs which are at variance with the usual conception of the “scientific world view.” Willis Harman, ‘The Issue of the Consciousness Expanding Drugs’. Something very strange is happening in psychiatry. Clinicians and researchers are becoming increasingly interested in a “new” experimental treatment, with some suggesting it might herald a “new paradigm” in the treatment of disorders such as anxiety, depression, and addiction (Nichols et al. 2017, Schenberg 2018). If promising initial results are borne out, this new treatment may significantly outperform existing pharmacological and psychological therapies in terms of rapidity and efficacy. And yet this treatment has a number of properties that, from the standpoint of mainstream philosophy and science, can only be described as extremely weird. First, although it is a drug treatment, there is no daily dosing regimen of the kind familiar from existing antidepressant and antipsychotic medications. Patients receive one, or very few, doses of the drug—albeit with considerable interpersonal support and preparation—and then, in successful cases, their symptoms dramatically decrease for many months; no re-dosing required. Second, although it is in some sense a drug treatment, it’s far from clear that the drug itself is the direct cause of clinical improvement. Rather, it seems that the drug is merely a catalyst for a brief but intense conscious experience, and it is this experience that causes therapeutic effects.
    [Show full text]
  • Selfhood and the Metaphysics of Altruism
    Selfhood and the Metaphysics of Altruism A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI¢I AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY MAY 2017 By Kevin Perry Maroufkhani Dissertation Committee: Arindam Chakrabarti, Chairperson Ron Bontekoe George Tsai Peter Hershock Sai Bhatawadekar ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am indebted to my family, particularly, Rosanne Perry, Dariush Maroufkhani, and Roya Dennis for their moral support and stubborn belief that I could accomplish this project despite all the obstacles I created for myself. I would like to acknowledge my chair, Dr. Arindam Chakrabarti, for the breadth and vivacity of his philosophical imagination, which has continued to challenge me, and nudge me out of complacency and inevitable philosophical naps. His analytical rigor, teaching-presence, and facility in world philosophy is a testament to what is possible in the field of global philosophical discourse. I am grateful for the many hours of selfless instruction he provided, and the fertile ideas cultivated in his classrooms. I would like to acknowledge Dr. Ron Bontekoe, who has always challenged me in the true spirit of a philosophical friend. Dr. Bontekoe has been a careful and caring academic advisor, and, in the courses I’ve taken with him, has never let me off the hook. He does not mince words, and because of the background depth he has provided in hermeneutics, biology, and theoretical ethics, he has greatly benefited this project. I would like to acknowledge Dr. Peter Hershock, who continually reminds me that a hermeneutical lens can make or break the credibility, rigor and sensitivity of cross-cultural conversation.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Philosophy of the Self the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy
    Ancient Philosophy of the Self The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 64 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, Princeton University RICHARD SORABJI, University of London Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Thomas-Institut, Universität zu Köln ROGER ARIEW, University of South Florida E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University of Waterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University PAUL HOFFMAN, University of California, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, Northwestern University, Evanston ALAIN DE LIBERA, Université de Genève JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Università degli Studi di genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN WOOD, Stanford University For other titles published in this series, go to www.springer.com/series/6608 Pauliina Remes • Juha Sihvola Editors Ancient Philosophy of the Self Editors Pauliina Remes Juha Sihvola Uppsala University Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies Sweden University of Helsinki and Finland University of Helsinki Finland ISBN 978-1-4020-8595-6 e-ISBN 978-1-4020-8596-3 Library of Congress Control Number: 2008928521 © 2008 Springer Science + Business Media B.V. No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work.
    [Show full text]
  • Systems Philosophy and Cybernetics
    Systems Philosophy and Cybernetics Nagib Callaos Founding President of the International Institute of Informatics and Systemics (IIIS) Abstract1 The general purpose of this article is to outline the intellectual importance and the pragmatic value of Cybernetics Philosophy. With this orientation, we will try to show the plausibility that Cybernetics, in its essence, is not new but, on the contrary, it seems consubstantial with human nature and, plausibly with Nature itself. Based on this plausibility, we will try to reason why it is intellectually important and pragmatically valuable, to foster reflections oriented to a Philosophy of Cybernetics. Consequently, we will suggest that applying systems philosophy, to be applied to Cybernetic systems, as a species. Additionally, it would be required to identify the differentia specifica of cybernetic systems and, hence, add other predicates to the notion of Cybernetics. This does not mean that we will be suggesting the use of the Aristotelian Definition and adding another definition to the overwhelming number of definitions that already exist. What we are suggesting is to use the Aristotelian notion of ‘definition’, in a more comprehensive context, i.e., not to define but to describe the notion or the idea of Cybernetics. In this context, we suggest the support of ‘Control Philosophy’ as a source to identify the differentia specifica of “cybernetics” in the context of the genus “general system”. This suggestion will emerge as we provide details regarding the con-essential nature of cybernetics to human beings and potential with Nature and its Evolution. Based on the details, we will provide regarding the above paragraph, we will suggest cybernetic relationships that tacitly, implicitly, or explicitly exist between the most important notions; which we will provide as related to the general- purpose briefly described above.
    [Show full text]
  • On Autonomy and Self-Binding Charlie Coil University of Arkansas, Fayetteville
    University of Arkansas, Fayetteville ScholarWorks@UARK Theses and Dissertations 8-2018 Abandoning the Dream of Omnipotence: On Autonomy and Self-Binding Charlie Coil University of Arkansas, Fayetteville Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd Part of the Applied Behavior Analysis Commons, Behavioral Economics Commons, and the Comparative Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Coil, Charlie, "Abandoning the Dream of Omnipotence: On Autonomy and Self-Binding" (2018). Theses and Dissertations. 2893. http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd/2893 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UARK. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UARK. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Abandoning the Dream of Omnipotence: On Autonomy and Self-Binding A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Charles Coil, Jr. University of Arkansas Master of Arts in Philosophy, 2009 August 2018 University of Arkansas This dissertation is approved for recommendation to the Graduate Council. ______________________________ Eric Funkhouser, PhD Dissertation Director ______________________________ ______________________________ Jacob Adler, PhD Tom Senor, PhD Committee Member Committee Member Abstract I offer a prolegomenon to the philosophical study of a uniquely human activity—the self- binding act. This philosophical interest directly connects with the Enlightenment project of centralizing personal autonomy and individual freedom as primary values of personhood. Self- binding represents an easily referenced action that introduces a possible clash between autonomy and freedom on the one hand seen as in conflict with other ancient basic human values like self- control and avoiding akrasia.
    [Show full text]
  • Ego-Splitting and the Transcendental Subject. Kant's Original Insight And
    Ego-Splitting and the Transcendental Subject. Kant’s Original Insight and Husserl’s Reappraisal Marco Cavallaro Abstract In this paper, I contend that there are at least two essential traits that com- monly define being an I: self-identity and self-consciousness. I argue that they bear quite an odd relation to each other in the sense that self-consciousness seems to jeopardize self-identity. My main concern is to elucidate this issue within the range of the transcendental philosophies of Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. In the first section, I shall briefly consider Kant’s own rendition of the problem of the Ego- splitting. My reading of the Kantian texts reveals that Kant himself was aware of this phenomenon but eventually deems it an unexplainable fact. The second part of the paper tackles the same problematic from the standpoint of Husserlian phenom- enology. What Husserl’s extensive analyses on this topic bring to light is that the phenomenon of the Ego-splitting constitutes the bedrock not only of his thought but also of every philosophy that works within the framework of transcendental thinking. Keywords Kant, Immanuel · Husserl, Edmund · Ego-splitting · Transcendental philosophy · Subjectivity · Self-consciousness 1 Introduction There are two essential traits that, taken together, provide us with a general defini- tion of being an I: self-identity and self-consciousness.1 The first is straightforwardly a necessary condition. Any object whatsoever must be identical with itself to be thinkable or, more generally speaking, experienceable. Even a squared circle must be identical with itself if I state its nonexistence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science of Self, Mind and Body
    Open Journal of Philosophy 2012. Vol.2, No.3, 171-178 Published Online August 2012 in SciRes (http://www.SciRP.org/journal/ojpp) http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2012.23026 The Science of Self, Mind and Body Sung Jang Chung Morristown-Hamblen Healthcare System, Morristown, USA Email: [email protected] Received April 30th, 2012; revised May 29th, 2012; accepted June 12th, 2012 A relationship among self, mind and body in humans is still not clearly known in philosophy and science because of lack of human data that would enable to objectively explain it. Teachings related to their rela- tionship in religions have been given to humanity in general in terms of subjective words. Consequently, philosophers and scientists have been investigating to find objective proofs related to their relationship. The author proposed a theory in his book (2009) that there are in a human individual two selves, one, the inner self (the true self) and one, the physical self (the false self) that coexist in one individual person. McGonigal (2012) published her book in which she described two minds or two selves in one human in- dividual, naming them “I WILL” and “I WANT” self on the basis of extensive studies on adult subjects. More recent researches in neuroscience using functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) discovered that the prefrontal cortex of the human brain performs self-control, emotion regulation and guiding be- haviors with morality, future goals and rules. The author compared characteristic aspects of the inner and physical selves of Chung with the “I WILL” and “I WANT” selves of McGonigal.
    [Show full text]
  • Situating the Elusive Self of Advaita Veda¯Nta
    8 Situating the Elusive Self 1 of Advaita Veda¯nta CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD I. Introduction: Advaita and the Question of What is Denied When Self is Denied In this essay, I will explore some ambiguities concerning what it is to affirm or deny the self, through the view of the Hindu school of Advaita Veda¯nta on the nature of the ‘I’ and its relationship to the reflexivity of conscious- ness. In particular, I will seek to situate this elusive self between my understanding of Dan Zahavi’s notion of the minimal self (Zahavi 2005; 2009; and this volume) and one reading of the significance of Thomas Metzinger’s brief but provocative comparisons of his denial of self with Advaita and Buddhism (Metzinger 2003: 549–50; 566). As Zahavi (like others in this volume) observes in Section 4 of his essay, the boundaries between self and no-self theories depend on what the self is taken to be. Exposition of Buddhist denials of self in this volume range from Siderits’ uncompromising reductionism all the way to Albahari’s defence of a unitary and perspectival witness consciousness, which Zahavi points out appears to preserve many of the defining characteristics of theories of self. So it is clear that in the classical Indian traditions, within Buddhism itself, what it means to deny self is a highly disputed matter. So it is with the Hindu school of Advaita. As both Fasching’s paper and mine show, the Advaitic assertion of self is not a straightforward matter, for other senses of self are denied by them that look intuitively necessary for a theory of self.
    [Show full text]
  • Plotinus on Care of Self and Soul
    DANIEL REGNIER | 149 Plotinus on Care of Self and Soul Daniel Regnier St. Thomas More College, University of Saskatchewan [email protected] https://orcid.org/0000-0003-3757-2603 ABSTRACT Plotinus’ philosophical project includes an important Socratic element. Plotinus is namely interested in both self-knowledge and care of soul and self. In this study I examine how through his interpretation of three passages from Plato (Timaeus 35a, Phaedrus 246b and Theatetus 176a-b), Plotinus develops an account of the role of care in his ethics. Care in Plotinus’ ethical thought takes three forms. First of all, care is involved in maintaining the unity of the embodied self. Secondly, situated in a providential universe, our souls – as sisters to the world soul - take part in the providential order by caring for ‘lower’ realities. Finally, Plotinus develops an ethics of going beyond virtue, a process which involves care for the higher, potentially divine, self. Keywords: Plotinus; Care; Self; Soul; Self Knowledge; Virtue. https://doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_21_10 150 | Plotinus on Care of Self and Soul At the very centre of Plotinus’ philosophical higher and lower soul. He develops his unders- preoccupations is a concern for understanding tanding of care for the self primarily against who we really are. Indeed, we might say that the background of the distinction between in addition to qualifying as a Neoplatonic higher and lower soul. In this first section philosopher, Plotinus is also in a crucial sense of the paper, I make reference to the problem a Neosocratic philosopher.1 This is not how which Plotinus’ notion of the impassibility of Plotinus is usually perceived.
    [Show full text]