‘Saints without God’ Camus’s poetics of secular faith NJ

Grace Whistler

Abstract • This article addresses Camus’s response to Christianity and the problem of suffering in the context of the early twentieth century. Owing to his association with the existentialist movement, it is often assumed that Camus, like many other French intellectuals of the period, rejected Christianity altogether. For this reason, his sympathy with Christian thought is overlooked, and it seems altogether bizarre that some theologians even claimed Camus to be a convert. Among these wildly conflicting claims, Camus’s philosophical response to Christianity has become somewhat muddied; in this article I attempt to rectify this. I argue that Camus’s entire philosophy is underpinned by his response to Christianity, and that he wanted to re-establish the position of morality in the face of the problem of suffering. I thus demonstrate how his writings manifest this struggle to achieve this goal, in what I refer to as Camus’s ‘poetics of secular faith’. Camus once claimed, ‘I do not believe in God and I am not an atheist’. This article aims to elucidate just what is meant by a statement like this, as well as to catalogue and analyse Camus’s innovative attempts at reconciling spirituality and suffering through philosophical literature.

1. Introduction ‘Black Flakes’, and everything in between. What is of interest to this article, however, is not to be ‘In short,’ Tarrou said simply, ‘what interests found at either extreme, but somewhere in the me is to know how one becomes a saint.’ middle. , who was born in 1913 ‘But you don’t believe in God.’ in predominately Catholic French-Algeria, lost ‘Precisely. Can one become a saint his father in the First World War, and was an without God: that is the only concrete active member of the French Resistance, is an question that I know today.’ artist who was perfectly situated to feel the full (Albert Camus, ) force of this spiritual upheaval, and naturally The magnitude of suffering experienced and this is manifested in his writings. In this art­icle, witnessed in the first half of the twentieth I examine what I refer to as Camus’s ‘poetics century understandably led many people to of secular faith’. Camus wanted to re-establish re-evaluate their moral and spiritual position the position of morality in the face of the prob- in the world, and consequently their faith also. lem of suffering, and his writings manifest this No doubt for some, faith in God’s divine wis- struggle to do so: behind much of his work lies dom was sufficient consolation, but many others the implicit question of whether this is possible­ rejected religion altogether, unable to accept that without religion – as Tarrou put it in The Plague any theodicy could justify the immense pain and (1947), ‘Can one become a saint without God’? chaos around them. The art that the world wars (Camus 2002: 196). Camus once claimed, ‘I inspired naturally embodies the whole spectrum do not believe in God and I am not an athe- of spiritual responses to suffering and doubt, ist’ (Camus 2008: 112, italics in the original). from the liturgy of T. S. Eliot’s ‘Ash-Wednesday’ This article aims to elucidate just what is meant all the way to the desolation of Anselm Kiefer’s by a statement like this, and thus this article

1 Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 49 catalogues and analyses Camus’s innovative a while to seem relevant to the young Albert, attempts at reconciling morality and suffering despite his being confirmed in a local church, through literature. While there is evidence of and having received holy communion (Todd such attempts throughout his works, this essay 1996: 33). But in spite of (and perhaps precisely will lay a particular focus on (1956), because of ) the indifference to religion in which because this work demonstrates more fully than Camus was raised, as a young adult he became any other, the troubled, conflicted nature of rec- fascinated with early Christian thought, the dis- onciling morality with a godless universe. tance from religion that his upbringing entailed So multifaceted was Camus’s engagement allowing him to approach the philosophical side with Christian thought that he is construed of Christianity, and evaluate it from the outside. in Christian scholarship as everything from This early interest in Christianity as philosophy­ an avid atheist to a ‘crypto-Christian’. I will inspired him to write his dissertation on Plotinus therefore begin by unpacking some of these and Saint Augustine for the Diplôme d’études claims, and attempting to give a firm account supérieures, which he submitted to the Univer- of Camus’s complex stance with regard to sity of Algiers in 1936 (Camus 2017: 1). Camus Christianity, making reference to both his continued to engage with Christian thought philosophical works and the life that informed throughout the entirety of his career, the formu- them (chs. 2–3). Following on from this, I shall lation of his own philosophy being in many ways begin my investigation of Camus’s poetics of a response to it. secular faith by looking at how he approaches Of course, Camus’s concern with religion theological and moral problems throughout comes not from a place of belief, but rather from his creative works – not only his criticisms, but a preoccupation with human finitude, and a also his longing for spiritual coherence (chs. yearning for meaning and coherence in the face 4–5). The subsequent section (ch. 6) will take of suffering and death. As Roger Quillot put it, The Fall as an extended case study for Camus’s ‘Camus was at once both a stranger to the reli- poetics of secular faith, as not only is this work gious spirit, but also profoundly moved by meta- particularly rich in Christian imagery, it also physical anxiety’ (Camus 2017: 6). Nevertheless, epitomises the spirit­ual conflict of mid-twen- his engagement with Christian thought is so tieth-century art. extensive that interpretations of his stance vary tremendously. Despite being a self-professed 2. Camus the Christian? agnostic, many writers continue to refer to ‘Camus’s atheism’ (e.g. Blackburn 2011: 315), Albert Camus grew up in French Algeria in while one critic, who refers to Camus as ‘the lay the early twentieth century, in the poor, work- saint’, claims that while Camus was ‘profoundly ing-class district of Belcourt, Algiers. While opposed to all Christianity stands for’ (Peyre Catholicism was an important part of French 1960: 23) he ‘found himself posthumously serv- society, the poorer classes only really observed ing as a theme for many sermons’ (ibid. 20). religion as a formality, the grandeur of the Others have called him ‘a religious thinker’ and ‘a church and its teachings seeming so very far religious moral philosopher’ (Hanna 1956: 224), from the mundane struggles of everyday life. In or suggested that ‘Camus’s apparently anti-reli- such an environment, Christianity represented gious thought’ is marked as ‘secretly religious’ by little more to the Camus family than the cere- the very fact he considers death to be a prob- monial pomp of special occasions, and thus the lem at all – apparently this proves that he ‘works moral and metaphysical aspects of religion took within the essentially religious apprehension

50 Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 that life, if it is to have meaning, must in some Camus tombe, sa philosophie tombe avec lui’ way be extended’ (Wood 1999: 93). (‘if Camus falls, his philosophy falls with him’: These supposed ‘subterranean theolog- Gaetani 2017: 60). Rather than dismiss this ic­al residues at work in Camus’s own corpus’ fanci­ful story as irrelevant, then, it would instead (Cristaudo 2011: 152), at the extreme, have even be prudent to investigate why a Christian minis- inspired several bizarre claims (for which there ter would even want Camus on their side. appears to be no real evidence) that Camus in fact converted to Christianity in secret. While 3. ‘Dialogue croyant–incroyant’ Jean Sarrochi (a sometime respected Camus scholar) called him a ‘crypto-Christian’ (Gaetani Of course, most believers will attest that faith is 2017: 51), perhaps the strangest of all comes not something constant and reassuring, despite from Protestant Minister Howard Mumma, what some atheists might assume. Believers who claims to have befriended and personally experi­ence times of doubt and uncertainty, and converted Camus. In 2000, Mumma wrote a in fact these incidents are a necessary part of book entitled Albert Camus and the Minister, faith; even non-religious philosophers can iden- which claimed that Camus, whilst living in tify with the need to question and investigate Paris, made a habit of attending the American our assumptions in order to formulate better church to listen to the organist, Marcel Dupré. theories, and thus something resembling cer- According to Mumma, Camus was captivated tainty. A philosopher­ like Camus, non-Christian by Mumma’s sermons, and the two men became though he may have been, nevertheless spent a friends. Mumma wrote that Camus had never great deal of his career tackling the challenges really read the Bible before (despite what we of Christianity, and saw the value in dialogue know of his fascination with Christian the­ between believers and non-believers (in French, ology), until Mumma made him the present ‘un dialogue croyant–incroyant’: Camus 1950: of a French translation. Until then, Camus had 212), so it is easy to understand why Christians apparently never thought of reading the Bible themselves would find engaging with his works in terms of allegory or symbolism, or the subtle a fruitful pursuit. In fact, there are undoubt- relationship between historical fact and spirit­ edly several key areas of Camus’s philosophy ual belief that the text encompasses (Cristaudo which respond directly to Christian thought; 2011: 146). While there is no evidence for these include (but perhaps are not limited to) the veracity of this story (and indeed the idea the faith/reason dichotomy, suffering, tran- that Camus, an author so skilled in allegorical scendence and of course morality itself. Before writing, had only previously considered literal demonstrating Camus’s creative approach to interpretations of the Bible seems preposter- such matters, it would be prudent to outline ous), it would be risky to dismiss this story as his philosophical responses. The most famous the wishful imagination of an old evangelist of Camus’s philosophical concepts is of course without venturing a response. If the entirety of the absurd, which he explains in The Myth of Camus’s thought was simply a journey towards Sisyphus­. The absurd, for Camus, signifies the conversion, this would seriously undermine his incongruity between the human desire for mean- entire philosophy, as Camus strove towards a ing and order, and the chaos and indifference of moral philosophy that was not founded on reli- the universe. Camus writes that ‘The absurd gion, and such a change of heart would relegate is sin without God’ (Camus 2005: 40), and by his entire œuvre to a series of stepping stones. this he means that like original sin, humans are Gaetani puts it rather more harshly, saying, ‘si born with this curse: it is through no fault of

Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 51 our own, but we are condemned to strive for the doubt and suffering he saw all around him. meaning in this finite existence. As James Wood Camus’s rejection of pure reason is a tragic hope puts it, the absurd ‘is the sentence passed on us for humanity and, as Wood put it, ‘it is within by life’ (Wood 1999: 94). This understanding of this tradition of unstable belief that his thinking humanity’s place in the universe is something breathes its unbelief ’ (Wood 1999: 89). that acts as a foundation for all of Camus’s phi- While Camus’s master’s dissertation is losophy, and it is necessary to keep it in mind neither his most mature nor his most devel- when considering his responses to Christianity. oped response to Christianity, it does illustrate In an insightful article, Daniel Berthold more clearly than anywhere else the kind of points out that the philosophies of Camus and Christianity that he admired most. He writes, Kierkegaard are in many ways more similar than ‘The dialogue of Faith and Reason is staged for they might at first appear (Berthold 2013: 137– the first time in plain light by Saint Augustine … 50). While Kierkegaard is very much a Chris­ Reason here becomes more supple. It is illumin­ tian philosopher, the picture of faith he presents ated by the light of Faith … It is not about God is by no means one of quiet contentment, it is that you must believe, but in God’ (Camus 2017: one of painful struggles in the face of obscurity 81) Camus, being interested in Christianity as and suffering (Kierkegaard 1974). Kierkegaard’s philosophy­ , wished to blur this line between faith concept of anxiety is also extremely close to and reason. As such, the convergence between Camus’s concept of absurdity; both illustrate the Greek and Christian thought that Camus profound sense of isolation the human experi- describes in this text is perhaps more illuminat- ences facing our place in the universe. Camus ing in terms of Camus’s own thought than in the recognises Kierkegaard’s awareness of the history of ideas – he wrote: absurd, claiming that ‘[Kierkegaard] does more than discover the absurd, he lives it’ (Camus Neoplatonism is a perpetual effort to reconcile 2005: 24), but despite this acknowledgment, he contradictory notion … Mystical Reason, sen- was nevertheless critical of his faith, bracketing sible Intelligence; immanent and transcendent him among those who commit ‘philosophical God: the oppositions abound. They all mark suicide’ (ibid. 35). Interestingly, Camus seems to however a constant balance between the sen- base this reading of Kierkegaard largely on that sible and the intellectual, the religious aspect of Leo Chestov, a religious thinker who simi- of the principles and their explanatory power. larly stood outside organised religion (Chestov In this dialogue at the heart of Reason, truth was Jewish, though he did not attend worship can only express itself in images … pouring and predominantly wrote on Christian philoso­ the intelligible into a sensible form, returning phy) – but along with Kierkegaard, Camus sees to intuition that which belonged to Reason. Chestov as a believer who is nevertheless sen- (Camus 2017: 68) sible of the absurd (ibid. 32–3). Thus, Camus certainly seems to have understood the struggle Here and elsewhere many of the claims he at the heart of faith, writing, ‘I have the impres- makes about Plotinus and Augustine could sion that faith is not so much a peace as a tragic just as easily be said of Camus himself: he was hope’ (Camus 1950: 225). What is often over- without a doubt ‘Greek in his need for coher- looked is the reverse effect, which is neverthe- ence; Christian in worries and in his sensibil- less true: Camus’s work exhibits a definite sense ity’ (Camus 2017: 72). When he writes that of faithfulness. Camus’s faith, however, is not in ‘Plotinus describes the intellect in a sensual God, but in the other – in humanity – despite fashion. His reason is living, material, and

52 Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 moving like a mixture of water and light’ (ibid. to Camus, the generation of Christians who 52), the style here is straight out of Camus’s own believed in this prophecy represent ‘a unique lyrical essays, a pagan mixture of carnality and example of a collective experience of death’. mysticism. Camus describes what he sees as the He argues that ‘to realize the idea of our death Christian ‘disdain for speculation’, writing ‘It gives us a new sense of our life’ (Camus 2017: is to the children that the Kingdom of God is 18) – this is a claim which is at the heart of his promised, but also to the wise people who have philosophy, and it is therefore clear that Camus known to despoil their knowledge in order to would like to replicate this collective experience understand the truth of the heart’ (ibid. 21). of death, in order for us to appreciate the gift of While this would ordinarily seem like a harsh life while we still possess it. criticism coming from a philosopher, we know But suffering does not only signify the cata- that Camus believed that reason is not the sole lyst for authenticity – it is also central to Camus’s key to philosophical truth – we must feel before rejection of transcendence. While, according to we know. This is the kind of secular faith to Camus, contemplation of suffering and death is which he aspires, which is why ‘he proceeded precisely what makes humans wish for an after- less by purely abstract analysis than by personal life (Camus 2005: 32), it is also the reason we engagement with problems that arose in the must reject this fantasy – we must never be rec- course of his life’ (Royal 2014: 27–8). onciled to suffering, as to legitimise it would be For the young Camus, another of the things unjust. The idea that an omnipotent­ God would that was so powerful about Christianity was its allow the existence of so much suffering, there- depiction of suffering and death – something fore, is unacceptable to Camus, and entails what which we all must face, according to him, on he refers to as ‘metaphysical injustice’ (Camus our quest of an authentic life in the face of the 2000b: 29–31). In a speech entitled ‘The unbe- absurd. As Roger Quilliot put it, Camus ‘has liever and the Christians’ (Camus 1950: 212), a Christian fascination with the death which which was addressed to a congregation at a triumphs over the flesh’ (Camus 2017: 8). In his Dominican monastery, Camus said, ‘I share with dissertation on early Christian thought (several you the same horror of evil. But I do not share years before he wrote ), he your hope, and I continue to struggle against this writes, universe where children suffer and die’ (Camus 1950: 213). This is exemplary of Camus’s true Christians are those who realize this approach to the problem of suffering. Not triumph of the martyred flesh. Jesus being only does he acknowledge the Christian moral man, the whole stress had been put on his response to suffering, he also suggests that for death: physically, one cannot go through him, there could never be a sufficient theodicy. something more horrible. It is upon … the He considers human life to be sacred, and there- torn-up hands and cracked joints, that one fore the only solution is to fight against cruelty. should reflect in order to imagine the terri­ From a theistic perspective, one might attrib- fying image of torture that Christianity estab- ute meaning to the suffering itself, but from an lished in this symbol. (Camus 2017: 18–19) agnostic perspective it would make more sense to accept that life isn’t fair, and in fact the exist- He takes this contemplation of suffering to ence of God can feel irrelevant when we are truly be central to Christian thought. For example, he touched by the suffering of the other. There is recounts the story of a fourth-century bishop who no solution to the problem of suffering, and thus predicts an impending apocalypse. According this is agnosticism chosen on ethical grounds.

Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 53 It is for this reason that Camus also rejects The unifying theme of Camus’s third cycle of the legitimacy of political violence. If we think philosophy was to be, as he put it, ‘love’ (Royal it just to commit murder in the name of an 2014: 25). As he died before its completion, ideal (no matter how lofty), we believe that the and left behind only a few vague, hand-writ- ideal is somehow transcendent to human life. ten notes, we can hardly guess how his moral For Camus, the end never justifies the means – philo­sophy would have been developed in these morality resides in every action, never a future works. From what he published in the years goal which justifies immorality (Camus 2000b: before, however, we can speculate on the role he 135). Truly virtuous motives therefore could envisaged the concept of love playing in moral never permit violence in the name of an ideal philosophy. Rowan Williams, a theologian and – nothing is worth causing human suffering. ex-archbishop of Canterbury, wrote that ‘At the Camus, above all then, believed in the value of heart of the desperate suffering there is in the human life. He wanted to demonstrate the value world, suffering we can do nothing to resolve of morality in a godless universe, and thus he or remove for good, there is an indestructible had a ‘yearning for a non-Christian concept of energy for love’ (Williams 2007: 10). This is the the sacred’ (Rathbone 2017: 121). Unlike the essence of both Christian and Camusian ethics.­ existentialists, who considered the lack of divine Indeed, on many occasions, Camus spoke of authority in the universe as a licence to act freely, love with regard to ethics. In Combat, the French from the very beginning Camus rejected the Resistance newspaper that he wrote for and idea of radical freedom. In The Myth of Sisyphus, edited, he wrote, ‘Humanists have much in com- he wrote, ‘The absurd does not liberate, it binds. mon with Christians: [Christians] are taught to It does not authorise all actions. Everything is love their neighbour. Yet others who do not share permitted does not mean that nothing is for- their faith may yet hope to arrive at the same goal’ bidden’ (Camus 2005: 65). While he does not (Camus 2006a: 32). In his notebooks, he jotted develop his moral philosophy fully until later down numerous notes about love, many harking in his career, it is clear from very early on that back to a Christian ideal. He wrote, ‘Whoever the lack of a guiding power should not mean gives nothing has nothing. The great misfortune the lack of morality. But for Camus, even the is not to be unloved, but not to love’ (Camus 2008: idea of a moral theory is corruptible. He jot- 39), and ‘Recognize the need for enemies. Love ted in a notebook, ‘I have abandoned the moral that they exist. Recover the greatest strength, point of view. Morals lead to abstraction and to not to dominate but to give’ (ibid. 204). We may injustice’ (Camus 2008: 246). By this Camus speculate, therefore, that Camus’s ethics would means that the delineation of rules by necessity have continued embody this focus on love as a marks out exceptions. As Wayne Cristaudo put kind of human solidarity, not abstracting from it, Camus ‘shares a deep affinity with the trad­ life, or upholding theoretic­al ideals, but respond- itional Christian rejection of the idea of salva- ing to the other with love and compassion. tion through morality, and for much the same reason – that the concrete requirements of love 4. Faith in the world cannot be compressed into a moral formula- tion’ (Cristaudo 2011: 147). The kind of moral- Having seen Camus’s conceptual responses to ity Camus wished for, then, was more holistic Christianity on a number of themes, it is now than this – something in fact much closer to the time to look at his creative responses, that is, Christian ideal – Camus’s ideal moral philoso- the poetics of Camus’s secular faith. I suggest phy is one of love and understanding. that there are two distinct types of secular faith

54 Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 which are manifest in Camus’s works, specific­ which is characterised subtly throughout the ally faith in the world and faith in humanity. novel, as when, on the day of Meursault’s trail, Camus’s earlier works are most characterised by his friend Emmanuel fails to present himself in the representation of this faith in the world – a court to give evidence. Emmanuel means ‘God rejection of vertical transcendence in favour of is with us’ in Hebrew, a name which, at the hour horizontal. Conversely, in response to suffer- of Meursault’s persecution, echoes not only, as ing witnessed in the Second World War, his Arthur Scherr writes, an ‘existential “absent later works are predominantly characterised in God” ’ (Scherr 2009: 197), but also the God his faith in humanity, and the search for a firm whom Christ beseeches from the cross, ‘My moral ground which circumvents abstraction. God, my God, why hast thou forsaken me?’ As we will see, each of these categories is replete There are numerous other subtle moments with Christian imagery. As one critic puts it, of allusion to the figure of Christ – Meursault is ‘Camus inverts all religious categories, in the even at one point depicted with a halo; he tells process converting them out of their baleful lit- us, ‘The chaplain looked at me almost sadly. By eralism and into the metaphorical’ (Wood 1999: now I had my back right up against the wall and 94) – thus Camus creates a symbolic, poetic lan- my forehead was bathed in light’ (Camus 2000a: guage perfectly suited to the problem of suffer- 114). It is also evident in his non-judgemental ing in the twentieth century. acceptance of Raymond’s friendship, a violently When Camus wrote in the preface to the sinful man whom he will ultimately sacrifice his English edition of The Outsider that Meursault life for. Raymond asks whether they are copains, is ‘the only Christ we deserve’ (Camus 2000a: approximately equivalent to ‘mates’ in English, 119), this contentious comment reflects his with its literal origins in the Latin ‘with + bread’, subversive approach to religious imagery. that is sharers of bread (the English ‘compan- Meursault commits murder – a very un-Christ- ion’ originating from the same etymological like act indeed – so Camus’s claim no doubt root). Meursault and Raymond are irrevocably seems improbable, if not scandalous. But bonded by a breaking of bread, as the evening Camus was, as one critic put it, ‘drawn to the on which they dine together is when Meursault figure of Jesus Christ, because of Jesus’ human- is passively coerced into Raymond’s grubby ity, his humility, his suffering and his com- affairs, which eventually lead to his demise. The passion for the suffering of others’ (Blackburn blood sausage and wine upon which they sup 2011: 322), and while it would be far-fetched to are ‘a caricature of the wine and bread that are apply such a defin­ition to Meursault, on further Christ’s body and blood in the Mass and at the examination it does become clear that he repre- Last Supper’ (Scherr 2009: 194) – at this Black sents a sort of inverted Christ, a misunderstood Mass, it is Meursault who betrays himself. This individual who is put to death by the masses. scene also echoes the temptation of Christ (in As Henry Patrick writes, ‘He is offered up as a Matt. 4:1–11 and Luke 4:1–13) (Scherr 2009: tribal sacrificial victim, not to placate the whims 194–5), in which hunger is a corrupting force, of a revered god, but to insure the validity of the but of course Meursault succumbs where Christ social structure … Neither attempts to save his doesn’t. Meursault is martyred on Raymond’s life, for each knows that, by doing so, he would account, as his violent dispute would no doubt lose the validity of that life, its authenticity and have continued if Meursault had not stepped in. its redeeming quality that are only sustained if He is also the sacrificial lamb of societal propri- they are maintained to the end’ (Patrick 1975: ety; in his unflinching honesty he is willing to 162). Thus he is a martyr in a godless universe, die for authenticity.

Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 55 But Camus’s symbolic treatment of Meur­ Here Meursault recognises the ‘benign sault as a Christ figure is just one element of the indifference’ of the universe that he will become novel’s response to Christianity. The mixture of part of very soon, as his concerns do not tran- innocence and culpability that Meursault rep- scend death. This does not bring him despair, resents, as well as his meaningless martyrdom, however, as life from this moment, so close to are both somewhat superficial compared to the death, seems all the more beautiful and sacred. philosophical movements made behind these Meursault’s understanding here even leads him features, which are far too often overlooked. to empathise with his mother, his recently dis- Right at the end of the novel, whilst awaiting covered immanence being something they, and execution, there is a passage of Meursault’s story indeed all of us, have in common. which most truthfully represents Camus’s own The contemplation of immanence that philosophical stance in the novel. Meursault, Meur­sault is swept away by in this final scene upon contemplating his imminent death, is is something that can be found throughout the transfigured. He does not look to a higher power works of Camus – as I mentioned earlier in to save him from his fate, however, like so many this section, they are most central in his early literary deathbed conversions. On the contrary, works, where they illustrate a kind of horizontal he has a kind of secular epiphany, a moment of transcendence. Camus spent his youth in north- communion with the world: ern Algeria, with its breath-taking (and to this day) unspoilt Mediterranean landscapes, and I woke up with the stars shining on my face. he clearly experienced an acute sense of com- Sounds of the countryside wafting in. The munion with the world. He wrote in Summer in night air was cooling my temples with the Algiers: smell of earth and salt. The wondrous peace of this sleeping summer flooded into me. At Unity expresses itself here in terms of sea that point, on the verge of daybreak, there was and sky. The heart senses it through a certain a scream of sirens. They were announcing a taste of the flesh that constitutes its bitterness departure to a world towards which I would and greatness. I am learning that there is no now be forever indifferent. For the first time superhuman happiness, no eternity outside in a very long time I thought of mother. I felt the curve of the days … Not that we should that I understood why at the end of her life behave as beasts, but I can see no point in the she’d taken a ‘fiancé’ and why she’d pretended happiness of angels. All I know is that this to start again. There at the home, where lives sky will last longer than I shall. And what faded away, there too the evenings were a kind can I call eternity except what will continue of melancholy truce. So close to death, mother after my death? What I am expressing here must have felt liberated and ready to live her is not the creature’s complacency about his life again. No one, no one at all had any right condition. It is something quite different. It to cry over her. And I too felt ready to live my is not always easy to be a man, even less to be life again. As if the great outburst of anger a man who is pure. But to be pure means to had purged all my ills, killed all my hopes, I rediscover that country of the soul where one’s looked up at the mass of signs and stars in the kinship with the world can be felt, where the night sky and I laid myself open for the first throbbing of one’s blood mingles with the vio- time to the benign indifference of the world. lent pulsations of the afternoon sun. (Camus (Camus 2000a: 117) 1970: 90)

56 Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 The kind of transcendence that Camus Camus thus sees the rejection of vertical depicts does not appeal to anything outside this transcendence as a return to something much world, it appeals precisely to this world – as older, which predates Christianity, almost a cor- something powerful, beautiful and incompre- ruption of horizontal transcendence, the kind of hensible, that will outlive us, but that we are pagan communion with the world which cele- part of, and will continue to be after we are brates the sacredness of life itself. Nevertheless, dead; as David Rathbone writes, ‘His concept it is undeniable that this rejection is very much of transcendence is explicitly this-worldly, and brought into being by his own experience of the inseparable from a kind of hyper-immanence events of the twentieth century, and the begin- (Rathbone 2017: 126–7). This horizontal tran- nings of an ethical element to this theory might scendence is therefore somewhat pantheistic, as have been present in 1942 when The Outsider all the spiritual feeling and profundity of emo- was published, but the following decade crystal- tion that humanity experiences is part of our lised the urgency of such a venture for Camus, physical world. As Camus wrote in A Happy as can be seen in the development of his poetics Death (1971), ‘the body has a soul in which the throughout the later creative works. soul has no part’ (Camus 2013a: 70). But the life of the physical is as mundane as 5. Faith in humanity it is profound; it consists in the everyday, even if we are sometimes able, philosophically speak- As has become abundantly clear, Camus’s brand ing, to look behind the curtain. As Claire in of agnosticism by no means renders life meaning- says, ‘on good days, if you trust less. What is also becoming more salient, too, is life, life has to answer you’ (Camus 2013a: 73). that Camus derives his ethics precisely from the All we can do, as part of this world, is to trust in fact that this life is all there is, as the suffering in it, to have faith in the vitality which belongs to this life becomes more tragic without the miti­ it, and to us. As Rathbone put it, ‘transcendence gating power of transcendence. It is therefore in conceived by Camus [is] temporary, pure, and contemplation of the suffering of the twentieth strictly mundane’ (Rathbone 2017: 131). This century that Camus introduces to his writing a relationship between profoundly spiritual feel- welcome and resounding faith in humanity. The ing, and the mundane physicality of matter we philosophical concept which Camus utilised to are part of, is so elusive that indeed the poetics expound this type of faith is ‘revolt’, as he for- we see in Camus is the only way to speak of a mulates in (Camus 2000b: 51), refer- faith in it. Rathbone again writes, ring to a kind of human solidarity that we have a duty to acknowledge in this brief existence. It can only be evoked with symbols, for life Alongside this seminal philosophical text, he must be transformed from absurdity into also develops a poetics of revolt in The Plague, meaningfulness by being taken as itself sym- an ethical fable which represents the need to bolic of the indestructibility of life itself. This struggle in the name of Other, whether that is not a representation of an other-worldly be against disease or totalitarianism. Through- eternal or immortal life, but an appreciation out this novel there are countless questions and that the fleeting and fragile lives of mortals answers directed at Christian thought, all within can themselves come to symbolise the insep- this ethical framework. Dialogues between the arable and everlasting mixture of vitality and narrator, Doctor Rieux, and the priest, Father mortality that is the reality of all life in this Paneloux, are a key area in which these ideas are world. (Rathbone 2017: 136) developed. Paneloux’s responses to the suffering

Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 57 of the plague is the driving force behind many is a ritualistic, pagan interpretation which seems of these conversations: early on in the novel he so alien to d’Arrast on his arrival, fresh from is able to dismiss the plague as an act of God, France. Out of respect and friendship towards a warning to sinners to change their ways or one of the townspeople who is unable to per- be smote too, but as he comes to witness the form their (Sisyphean) annual ritual of carrying suffering of innocents first hand he is thrown a boulder through the town to the church, he into spiritual turmoil. Surely we must trust the takes the task upon himself, instead carrying the divine wisdom and love of God in these trying boulder to the hearth of his friend who is suffer- times? Rieux rejects this stance absolutely, tell- ing from exhaustion, where he is welcomed and ing him, ‘I have a different notion of love; and celebrated. In this action, d’Arrast sets a prece- to the day I die I shall refuse to love this cre- dent for the humanisation and secularisation of ation in which children are tortured’ (Camus their practices. Thomas Claire writes, 2002: 169). Paneloux adopts the rhetoric of fire and brimstone in his sermons, but in reality he In examining the wealth of Christian imagery cannot accept this suffering either, and just like in ‘La Pierre qui pousse’, it is essential to the telling nomenclature of Emmanuel in The note the distinction between d’Arrast and the Outsider, he pleads to a seemingly absent God, Christ of the Christian tradition as seen by ‘My God, save this child!’ (ibid. 168). Elsewhere Camus: unlike Christ, who became an institu- in the novel, Tarrou, a fellow combatant of the tionalized figure preaching salvation through plague tries to formulate his own poetics of suf- faith in the future, d’Arrast opens the way fering. His search for morality without God is for the people of Iguape to find fulfilment in a Quixotic endeavour to become ‘A saint with- their present circumstances by teaching them out God’ (ibid. 196). For Rieux, the difficulties that man must be directly responsible for his posed simply by being human in the face of uni- actions. (Claire 1976: 28) versal suffering is enough, but Tarrou, who real­ ises that the pure and perfect ideal of sainthood D’Arrast’s actions are in honour of human is divorced from everyday struggles, believes the frailty and kinship which eludes social expect­ task of being human is even more ambitious ation, the solidarity which inspired him to take (ibid. 197). up his friend’s burden also provoking his subver- Of course, Camus believes that the only sion of religious rites. Camus sees this as the only way for humans to make any progress is to possible way forward for any kind of humanist work tirelessly at the paradoxically unavoid­ morality, as is summed up by the following sen- able and impossible task of simply being human timent taken from the aptly named The First (as indeed he tells us all the way back in The Man. The protagonist, Jacques Cormery, loosely Myth of Sisyphus), and as well as Rieux, he paints based on the young Camus himself, consid- other portraits of the kind of secular saviour we ers himself to be ‘with no past, without ethics, need to move on from the horrors of war and without guidance, without religion, but glad totalitarianism. One such example is d’Arrast, to be so and to be in the light’ (Camus 2013b: in the short story ‘The Growing Stone’ from 150). After the horrific events of the early to the collection (Camus mid-twentieth century, all that is left to do is to 2006b). Set in a remote town in Iguape, Brazil, start from scratch – not in innocence, like Adam this is yet another example of Camus’s image in the Garden of Eden, but in experience and of a pre-Christian world. While the tribal humility. people of the town do observe Christianity, it

58 Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 6. The Fall response to the moral questions which arise in the text. Clamence, on the surface, lived a life While The Fall is perhaps Camus’s bleakest of virtue. He was a lawyer who specialised in novel, it is also the one that is rooted most deeply representing vulnerable people (such as widows in Christian imagery – so much so that it would and orphans), went out of his way to perform be impossible to examine it comprehensively in good deeds, and was duly successful and cele- this short article. The title obviously alludes to brated for it. But Clamence is the epitome of a the story of Adam and Eve, and much like that selfish moralist – he does all the right things for story, The Fall mourns a loss of innocence – but all the wrong reasons. When Clamence finally of course it is not the paradise of the garden of owns up to himself about his duplicitous ego- Eden that is lost, but the relative bliss of a time tism, he abandons his career and adopts the before the Holocaust and trench-warfare. The mysterious title of ‘Judge-Penitent’, seeking (or protagonist, Jean-Baptiste Clamence, a self- so it seems) redemption through the practice of proclaimed ‘Judge-Penitent’, confesses his sordid confession. He confesses his mistreatment of life-story to a stranger in a bar over the course women, numerous misdeed and betrayals, and of several evenings, and leads the reader through even a bizarre episode in which he adopts the a nightmarish version of Amsterdam, the city’s position of ‘Pope’ of a prisoner of war camp, and concentric canals mimicking the circles of hell legitimises stealing water from a dying prisoner in Dante’s Inferno. Clamence, unlike his cre- because of his fictitious spiritual importance. ator, has no sense of the sacred, and his stories But unfortunately for Clamence, where there is paint a picture of feigned selflessness, cynicism no God, there is no divine redemption. Maher and cowardice. Nevertheless, this novel is, as writes, ‘the existentialists had killed God, yet Maher writes, ‘positively crying out for … spirit­ they offered nothing to replace Him, thus leaving ual redemption’ (Maher nd). The reader, in the a guilt-ridden man like Jean-Baptiste Clamence position of a priest hearing confession, is told with nowhere to turn … And so he turns to his (for example) of the night that Clamence, the only alternative, his fellow man’ (Maher nd). sole witness to a woman’s suicide attempt as she And so Clamence spends his days in bars, wait- jumped from a bridge in Paris, instead of trying ing for a sympathetic listener (reader) to come to save her simply left the scene without back- along and share in his spiritual anguish. ward glance. Clamence is apparently haunted While it is true that Clamence has no-one by this episode and ironically, considering his to turn to but his fellow man, it is not the case namesake John the Baptist, Clamence cannot that The Fall ‘provides no answers, only painful, stand the sight of water, and will no longer cross almost desperate questions’, as Maher goes on to a bridge at night. This sarcastic raconteur can- suggest (Maher nd). Through Clamence’s end- not escape his own sins, let alone cleanse those less embittered chatter, the desire for a Christ of others: he tells us, ‘With me, there is no bene­ figure is ever present; he asks, ‘Who would sleep diction, no absolutions are handed out’ (Camus on the floor for us, my dear sir?’ (Camus 2006c: 2006c: 82). The list of such allusions and sym- 21). The simple humility that Clamence begs for bols in the novel goes on. in such a question, however, is nothing miracu- While there is no room in the current art­ lous or transcendent – in fact this moving image icle to thoroughly catalogue the full wealth of self-sacrifice is purely human. This is the of religious imagery in The Fall, it is certainly kind of gesture that echoes Camus’s emphasis important to try to understand the role that on love and solidarity that we have already seen Christianity has in this novel, and Camus’s elsewhere, and in fact, as Barry and Paterson

Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 59 write, ‘Camus seems to be telling us that the key In this article I have given a brief account of to human community or communion is found Camus’s poetics of suffering and faith, demon- in the human Christ who alone was free and strating just some of the instances in his cre­ willing to ‘sleep on the floor for us’ (Barry and ative works when he has used Christianity as a Paterson 1976: 41), and thus The Fall ‘may … be springboard for developing his moral response read as an extended struggle towards dialogue to the chaos of the early to mid-twentieth cen- and relation’ (ibid. 38). In the world of The Fall, tury. From secular Christ-figures to prophetic there is no God, no ultimate redemption, and we plagues, Camus elaborated his need for a sec- must live with our guilt – but through recogni- ular faith explicitly through Christian symbol- tion of our position in the world, and solidarity ism, thereby demonstrating both his respect with our fellow human beings, we can all take on for Christian thought and scripture, as well as the role of the human Christ. critiquing the ways in which its morality failed to respond to the suffering around him. As one 7. Conclusion critic writes, ‘The works of Camus … have asked the right questions and constrained Christians As we have seen, Camus spent a great deal of to evolve ever more satisfactory answers to them’ his career responding to the questions raised by (Peyre 1960: 21). Through his rich weaving of Christianity, particularly focussing on theolog- Christian imagery and humanist ethics, Camus ical responses to suffering. Camus’s non-belief formulates a kind of faith that he sees as the only is not motivated by nihilism, or even scepticism way to move forward – faith in the world and in towards mysticism or concepts of the sacred – humanity itself. Given the extent to which Camus in fact Camus’s creative works demonstrate his investigated Christian theology, it is hardly a understanding and respect for these aspects of surprise that Minister Mumma saw his poten- Christian thought and writing. As John Cruick- tial as a powerful an ally. After all, what could shank writes, ‘What makes Camus so significant, be more persuasive in the process of conversion and in many ways representative, a figure of his than the idea that Camus, who had voiced so own generation is the fact that he experienced many nuanced concerns with Christianity, had a religious need in its widest sense yet was una- finally had his doubts assuaged? Unfortunately ble to accept religious belief ’ (Cruikshank 1967: for Mumma, Camus’s stance on Christianity is 324). Camus personally rejects Christianity on too clear to make his story believable – never­ the grounds that he can see no reason that suf- theless, Camus’s responses to Christianity fering could ever be legitimised, but his critique should earn him a place in Christian ethics for of Christianity is really only aimed at ‘phantas- many years to come.  mic Christianity, that is, Christianity when it is pathological in its otherworldliness, and either Grace Whistler is a PhD indifferent, masochistic, or destructive to the candidate at the University of York. Her thesis, entitled world’ (Cristaudo 2011: 154). Thus he continued ‘Between Content and Form: to engage with Christian thought, his ‘brilliant Camus’s Literary Ethics’, reassess the writings­ of Albert working at the frontier between belief and un­be- Camus in relation to current lief … and his effort to live honestly and decently debates at the intersection despite the ideological horrors of the twentieth of ethics and aesthetics. She has published articles in century’ (Royal 2014: 26) characterising his cre- Literature and Theology, the Journal of Camus Studies ative works, and motivating his choice of Chris- and the Journal of Life Writing, and is currently working on a chapter for Brill’s Companion to Albert tian symbolism to illustrate moral problems. Camus.

60 Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 References Camus” : faire le point sur les différentes tentatives de christianiser sa vie et sa pensée’, Barry, Catherine, and William Paterson, 1976. Albert Camus: Carte Blanche (Le Pontet, ‘The concepts of community and Christology Barthélemy), pp. 41–61 in Camus’ The Fall’, Christianity and Hanna, Thomas L., 1956. ‘Albert Camus and the Literature, 25, pp. 37–42 Christian faith’, The Journal of Religion, 36(4), Berthold, Daniel, 2013. ‘Kierkegaard and Camus: pp. 224–33 either/or?’, International Journal of Philosophy Kierkegaard, Søren, 1974. The Sickness unto Death, and Religion, 73, pp. 137–50 trans. W. Lowrie (Princeton University Press) Blackburn, Vivienne, 2011. ‘Albert Camus: the Maher, Jimmy, nd. ‘Camus, The Fall, and the challenge of the unbeliever’, Scottish Journal of question of faith’, (accessed 30.10.2017) Camus, Albert, 1950. Actuelles : Chroniques Patrick, Henry, 1975. Voltaire and Camus: The 1944–1948 (Paris, Gallimard) Limits of Reason and the Awareness of Absurdity ——1970. Lyrical and Critical Essays, ed. Philip (Banbury, The Voltaire Foundation) Thody (New York, Vintage) Peyre, Henri, 1960. ‘Camus the pagan’, Yale French ——2000a. The Outsider, trans. Joseph Laredo Studies, 25, pp. 20–5 (London, Penguin) Rathbone, David, 2017. ‘Postscript’, Between ——2000b. The Rebel, trans. Anthony Bower Plotinus and Saint Augustine by Albert (London, Penguin) Camus, trans. David Rathbone ——2005. The Myth of Sisyphus, trans. Justin (accessed 30.3.2018) O’Brien (London, Penguin) Royal, Robert, 2014. ‘Camus: between god and ——2006a. Camus at Combat: Writing 1944–1947, nothing’, First Things, 1, pp. 25–30 ed. Jacqueline Lévi-Valensi (Princeton and Scherr, Arthur, 2009. ‘Meursault’s dinner with Oxford, Princeton University Press) Raymond: a Christian theme in Albert ——2006b. Exile and the Kingdom, trans. Carol Camus’s L’Etranger’, Christianity and Cosman (London, Penguin) Literature, 58(2), pp. 187–210 ——2006c. The Fall, trans. Justin O’Brien Todd, Olivier, 1996. Une Vie (Paris, Gallimard) (London, Penguin) Williams, Rowan, 2007. Tokens of Trust (London, ——2008. Notebooks, Vol. III: 1951–1959, trans. Canterbury Press) Ryan Bloom (Chicago, Ivan Dee) Wood, James, 1999. ‘Camus and twentieth- ——2013a. A Happy Death, trans. Richard century clarity: the sickness unto life’, The Howard (London, Penguin) New Republic, pp. 88–96 ——2013b. , trans. David Hapgood (London, Penguin) ——2017. Between Plotinus and Saint Augustine, trans. David Rathbone (accessed 30.3.2018) Claire, Thomas, 1976. ‘Landscape and religious imagery in Camus’ “La Pierre Que Pousse”’, Studies in Short Fiction, 13(3), pp. 321–30 Cristaudo, Wayne, 2011. ‘The Johannine Christianity of Albert Camus’, Culture, Theory and Critique, 52(2–3), pp. 145–61 Cruickshank, John, 1967. ‘Albert Camus: sainthood without god’, Mansions of the Spirit: Essays in Literature and Religion, ed. George A. Panichas (New York, Hawthorn), pp. 313–24 Gaetani, Giovanni, 2017. ‘ “Les avocats de

Nordisk judaistik • Scandinavian Jewish Studies | Vol. 29, No. 1 61