Universality of Science: Historical Validation of a Philosophical Idea

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Universality of Science: Historical Validation of a Philosophical Idea Universality of Science : Historical Validation of a Philosophical Idea Michel Paty To cite this version: Michel Paty. Universality of Science : Historical Validation of a Philosophical Idea. Habib, S. Irfan and Raina, Dhruv. Situating the history of science : Dialogues with Joseph Needham, Oxford India Paperbacks, p. 303-324, 2001. halshs-00184932 HAL Id: halshs-00184932 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00184932 Submitted on 3 Nov 2007 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Chap 12, in Habib, S. Irfan and Raina, Dhruv (eds.), Situating the history of science : Dialogues with Joseph Needham, Oxford University Press (New Delhi), 1999, p. 303-324 (Oxford India Paperbacks, 2001). (Trad. en anglais, par M.P. Original français : 1997f, 1999c). Universality of Science :Historical Validation of a Philosophical Idea A by MICHEL PATYB SUMMARY.- The question of the universality of science is considered, in contemporary debates, under the most varied and opposed positions depending whether one is sharing the point of view of an "ideal science" or that of a "social production of science". In the first case, science is conceived as the "hard core" of its statements and results at the period under consideration, and its supposed universality ignores factors that relativize its contents of knowledge, and which can be of a conceptual as well as a social nature. Conversely, an exclusive focalization on the social aspects of the production of scientific knowledge ignores the objective character of these knowledge contents, be they either thought objects such as mathematical ones, or phenomena of the real, physico-biological as well as human and social, world. These two extreme positions, although caricatural, are shared by many. They illustrate the absence or ignorance of interdisciplinar analyse between philosophy, the various sciences, history of sciences and general history. We shall first evoke very briefly elements of the critique set against the universality of science as they stand nowadays from inquiries of philosophy of knowledge, sociology of knowwledge, history of science, history and anthropology. Then we shall try to set philosophically the problem of the universality of science as a philosophical idea, strongly linked to science and to philosophy since their genesis. We shall see, by following the idea at various stages of the history of thought, that the philosophical statement of universality of science has to be confronted with the historical reality of the production, diffusion and assimilation or appropriation of scientific knowledge, always specifying the various dimensions of that one (which include its applications and its links to a Paper presented at the International Conference Science the Refreshing River. On the History of Science and Civilization, New Delhi, 2th-4th sept. 1996. b Equipe REHSEIS, UPR 318, CNRS, and Université Paris 7-Denis Diderot (2 Place Jussieu, F- 75251 Paris-Cedex 05, France MICHEL PATY UNIVERSALITY OF SCIENCE : A PHILOSOPHICAL IDEA TO THE PROOF OF HISTORY 2 techniques and to technology). MICHEL PATY UNIVERSALITY OF SCIENCE : A PHILOSOPHICAL IDEA TO THE PROOF OF HISTORY 3 1 THE NEED FOR A HISTORICAL ANALYSIS.` The problem of universality of science is considered, in contemporary debates, under the most varied and opposed positions depending whether one is sharing the point of view of an "ideal science" or that of a "social production of science". In the first case, science is conceived as the "hard core" of its statements and results at the period under consideration, and its supposed universality ignores factors that relativize its contents of knowledge, and which can be of a conceptual as well as a social nature. Conversely, an exclusive focalization on the social aspects of the production of scientific knowledge ignores the objective character of these knowledge contents, be they either thought objects such as mathematical ones, or phenomena of the real, physico-biological as well as human and social, world. These two extreme positions, although caricatural, are shared by many. They illustrate the absence or ignorance of interdisciplinar analyse between philosophy, the various sciences, history of sciences and general history. It is true to say, as we all are conscious, that science is not only a set of knowledge, ruled by the judgements of reason and of experience. Science is also involved in a cultural and axiological context, and stands on values that are commonly accepted by the culture in which it takes place. But science is also an activity and includes, as such, its practices, that are socialized ones or even directly social practices. Science contains also its applications which have consequences on the transformations of society, and these transformations have a direct retro-effect on science itself. Science, technology and society are closely related, and contemporary science is often considered as "technoscience", a concept invented to express this complexity. To-day science is inseparably the system of science and technology, in which the two dimensions I mentioned previously also take part, science as content of knowledge and science as practice. The fact that, when we speak of science, a system is at stake means that we are compelled to consider that the very notion of science means indissociation between knowledge as content and the concrete situations in which it is embedded. This means that, even if we would consider only the epistemological dimension of science, that is science as a type of thinking, we would have to consider the possibility of these effects or consequences as virtual properties of such a type of thinking. This expresses nothing else than the following evidence : human thinking, whatever be the form under which we consider it, carries with itself the virtuality of man's practices, actions and sociality. MICHEL PATY UNIVERSALITY OF SCIENCE : A PHILOSOPHICAL IDEA TO THE PROOF OF HISTORY 4 At every period of history, and in every cultural area, science, or its equivalent, is embedded in a cultural totality of an organic nature and constituting by itself a system. This systemic character makes difficult to conceive the possibility of transmission of a state of science and of culture to another one, be such transmission considered either in space at a given period, or in time along the flow of history : out of their systems, the elements that constitute these systems undergo a shift of meaning. Hence the difficulty of the question of transmission, which, as I shall try to show, is at the heart of the question of universality. This state of affairs is eventually taken as an excuse by those who consider that the debate on the universality of science is closed, because it is strictly related with the claim of universality made by the "western-positive- technological" conception of science. Those who share this conception consider that to-day science, “world science”, is the only universal science, and they would deny any other and further consideration. One could however object that “universality” meant in that way is not necessarily a feature of this science, but has been imposed by an economical mode of domination related systemically with the power of technology. On the contrary, radical opponents to this “imperialist” conception of science would deny any value to the notion of universality of science, precisely because of this systemic solidarity between science and domination. But they ignore that systems evolve and that elements taken from within a structure can be transferred to another structure without disappearing. In such a case, it will be intersting to inquire ourselves about the changes of meaning these elements suffer, or, eventually, about some permanencies that can be observed through the process of transmission. And, indeed, if translation is treatery, it might well, for this very reason, endow some creative effects. With this in mind, we can wonder whether there is not, in the case of "universality of science", something that resists the strong criticisms that have been opposed to it. I am sure that Joseph Needham - who wrote an admirable meditation on the historian of science as an œcumenical man1 - would not have liked to leave up the idea of universality of science, for it would mean at the same time to leave up the idea that science is value, and deprive us from one of our means - tools or arms -, to act in favour of the enlightenment and accomplishment of mankind. And it thus would make us leave the place for the benefit of growing obscurantisms and fundamentalisms. But, for sure, we have to question science and the idea of its universality, in order to understand better what kind of reality and effectiveness these notions have. I shall take as my point of departure, in this intended critical analysis and reconstruction, the state of criticism, now rather known, corresponding essentially to : 1) reflections on the insertion of science in the industrial and capitalistic society (see, for instance, the works of Max Weber, of Jurgen 1 Needham [1993]. MICHEL PATY UNIVERSALITY OF SCIENCE : A PHILOSOPHICAL IDEA TO THE PROOF OF HISTORY 5 Habermas, of Jacques Ellul, among many other); and 2) reflections on the link between science and imperialism, which have been growing during the last two decades and of which the studies on "Science and Empires" are a part. Admitting these analyse and criticisms as known, I shall try, in what follows, to develop some elements of argumentation which are more a call for further thematical investigations than mere statements or conclusions.
Recommended publications
  • The Synergy Between Philosophy and Science, Need of the Contemporary Society
    International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Research International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Research ISSN: 2455-2070; Impact Factor: RJIF 5.22 Received: 11-11-2019; Accepted: 12-12-2019 www.socialsciencejournal.in Volume 6; Issue 1; January 2020; Page No. 45-51 The Synergy between Philosophy and Science, need of the contemporary society Kabita Das1*, Biswaranjan Paital2 1 PG Department of Philosophy, Utkal University, Bhubaneswar, Odisha, India 2 Redox Regulation Laboratory, Department of Zoology, College of Basic Science and Humanities, Orissa University of Agriculture and Technology Bhubaneswar, India Abstract What the world will be like in the foreseeable future is a matter of concern for everyone, no matter how far removed the human is from scientific work, political struggle, or revolutionary moment. What is in store for man: the holocaust of war, or a peaceful life? What will the earth be like? Will nature survive or will it be annihilated as a result of scientific and technical progress? Will oppression and social injustice disappear from the world, or will they persist forever? These are general questions confronting each person living on society. However, is it possible to resolve above and all other social issues by only social science approaches, is the central story of this article. Social science is pre-dominated with predictable analyses while science is empirical. Humanities are academic disciplines that deal with the study on the aspects and issues of human society and culture, whereas, science is a systematic innovativeness that builds and organizes information in the form of testable explanations and predictions about the universal phenomena including social issues.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Fundamental Worldview of the Integral Culture Integrating Science, Religion, and Art: 2Nd Part
    Published in: World Futures. The Journal of General Evolution, 59(7): 535-556. On the Fundamental Worldview of the Integral Culture Integrating Science, Religion, and Art: 2nd Part Attila Grandpierre Konkoly Observatory H-1525 Budapest, P. O. Box 67, Hungary 4.1. The nature of philosophy and scientific worldview Dilthey (1911) recognised that the most important question of philosophy is defining the main task of philosophy itself. Actually, this main task of philosophy has not been a settled question since the ancient Greeks. Let us make now an attempt to overcome this difficulty. “Philosophy is the science searching and systemising the most general laws of nature, human society and evolution of thinking. (…) It is the life-concept, the worldview, the attitude forming a more or less coherent system of views on the outer world, on the facts and phenomena of life and their nature, aim and interpretation” (Dictionary of Hungarian Language, 1979, 817). It seems that in this definition concepts of philosophy and worldview are mixed. Plato formulated the first and most important mark of philosophy as being the study in which various special sciences are to be related together and understood as part of one system (Kneale, 1960, 756). Now if philosophy is the “cognition of the world” and if it is science that researches and systemises “the most general laws of nature, society and the evolution of thinking”, then philosophy should be based on these special sciences. Therefore, since fundamental sciences are concerned to three fundamental realms of reality, which are existence, life and consciousness (Grandpierre, 2001b), philosophy should be the unified science of the most general laws of physics, biology and psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics: a Contemporary Introduction: Third Edition
    Metaphysics Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction is for students who have already done an introductory philosophy course. Michael J. Loux provides a fresh look at the central topics in metaphysics, making this essential reading for any student of the subject. This third edition is revised and updated and includes two new chapters on Time and Causation. Topics addressed include: • the problem of universals • the nature of abstract entities • the problem of individuation • the nature of modality • identity through time • the nature of time • the Realism/anti-Realism debate Wherever possible, Michael J. Loux relates contemporary views to their classical sources in the history of philosophy. As an experienced teacher of philosophy and an important contributor to recent debates, Loux is uniquely qualified to write this book. The third edition retains the student-friendly features of previous editions: • chapter overviews summarizing the main topics of study • examples to clarify difficult concepts • annotated further reading at the end of each chapter • endnotes and a full bibliography Michael J. Loux is Shuster Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. He is also editor of Metaphysics: Contemporary Readings, designed to accompany this textbook and also published by Routledge. His book Substance and Attribute (1978) is one of the major metaphysics books of recent years. Routledge Contemporary Introductions to Philosophy Series editor: Paul K. Moser Loyola University of Chicago This innovative, well-structured series is for students who have already done an introductory course in philosophy. Each book introduces a core general subject in contemporary philosophy and offers students an access- ible but substantial transition from introductory to higher-level college work in that subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Modern Spiritualism: Its Quest to Become a Science Creative Works
    Southern Illinois University Carbondale OpenSIUC Modern Spiritualism: Its Quest to Become A Science Creative Works 2021 Modern Spiritualism: Its Quest to Become A Science John Haller Jr Follow this and additional works at: https://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/histcw_ms Copyright © 2020, John S. Haller, Jr. All Rights Reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means without the prior written permission of the publisher. ISBN (print): 9798651505449 Interior design by booknook.biz This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Creative Works at OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Modern Spiritualism: Its Quest to Become A Science by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Modern Spiritualism: Its Quest to Become A Science By John S. Haller, Jr. Copyright © 2020, John S. Haller, Jr. All Rights Reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means without the prior written permission of the publisher. ISBN (print): 9798651505449 Interior design by booknook.biz Spiritualism, then, is a science, by authority of self-evident truth, observed fact, and inevitable deduction, having within itself all the elements upon which any science can found a claim. (R. T. Hallock, The Road to Spiritualism, 1858) TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction 1 Chapters 1. Awakening 11 2. Rappings 41 3. Poughkeepsie Seer 69 4. Architect of the Spirit World 95 5. Esoteric Wisdom 121 6. American Portraits 153 7.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia Das Allgemeine Brouillon
    Novalis Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia Das Allgemeine Brouillon Translated, Edited, and with an Introduction by David W. Wood Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia SUNY series, Intersections: Philosophy and Critical Theory Rodolphe Gasché, editor Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia Das Allgemeine Brouillon Novalis Translated, Edited, and with an Introduction by David W. Wood State University of New York Press Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2007 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, address State University of New York Press, 194 Washington Avenue, Suite 305, Albany, NY 12210-2384 Production by Judith Block Marketing by Michael Campochiaro Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Novalis, 1772–1801. [Allgemeine Brouillon. English] Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia : Das Allgemeine Brouillon / Novalis ; translated, edited, and with an introduction by David W. Wood. p. cm. — (SUNY series, intersections: philosophy and critical theory) Includes bibliographical references and index. Translation of: Das Allgemeine Brouillon : Materialien zur Enzyklopäedistik 1798/99. ISBN-13: 978-0-7914-6973-6
    [Show full text]
  • The Nature of Metaphysical Knowledge
    THE INTERNATIONAL SOCIETY FOR METAPHYSICS STUDIES IN METAPHYSICS, VOLUME IV THE NATURE OF METAPHYSICAL KNOWLEDGE Edited by GEORGE F. McLEAN HUGO MEYNELL UNIVERSITY PRESS OF AMERICA INTERNATIONAL SOCIETY FOR METAPHYSICS TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction PART I. APPROACHES AND METHODS 1. Metaphysics as a Discipline: Its Requirements by Ivor Leclerc 3-22 2. Metaphysics and the Architectonic of Systems by Reiner Wiehl 23-50 3. Truth, Justification and Method in Metaphysics and Theology by Richard Martin 51-68 4. Some Principles of Procedure in Metaphysics by Charles Hartshorne 69-75 Comment: James W. Felt 77-81 5. Metaphysical Knowledge as Hypothesis by Richard L. Barber 83-92 Comment: Errol E. Harris 93-96 PART II. IMPLICATIONS AND TASKS OF METAPHYSICS FOR SCIENCE, ETHICS AND HISTORY 6. Metaphysics and Science by Andre Mercier 99-103 7. Metaphysics and Science: Affinities and Discrepancies by Evandro Agazzi 105-121 8. Some Tasks for Metaphysicians by Mario Bunge 123-128 9. The Problem of Metaphysical Presupposition in and of Science by Kurt Hubner 129-134 10. Cosmology and the Philosopher by Ernan McMullen 135-148 11. Metaphysics and the Foundations of Ethical and Social Values by Johannes Lotz 149-161 12. Metaphysics and History by T.A. Roberts 163-176 INDEX 177-180 INTRODUCTION The preceding volumes in this series--devoted respectively to Person and Nature, Person and Society and Person and God1--progressively delineated the basic issues of human and, indeed, of all existence. They took work on these issues beyond the horizon of the physical and social sciences, as well as beyond such philosophical methods as those of pragmatism and positivism.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Babel: How Science Was Done Before and After Global English
    Scientific Babel Scientific Babel How Science Was Done Before and After Global English Michael D. Gordin The University of Chicago Press Chicago and London Michael D. Gordin is the Rosengarten Professor of Modern and Contemporary History at Princeton University and the author of The Pseudoscience Wars, also published by the University of Chicago Press. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637 The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London © 2015 by Michael D. Gordin. All rights reserved. Published 2015. Printed in the United States of America 24 23 22 21 20 19 18 17 16 15 1 2 3 4 5 ISBN- 13: 978- 0- 226- 00029- 9 (cloth) ISBN- 13: 978- 0- 226- 00032- 9 (e- book) DOI: 10.7208/chicago/9780226000329.001.0001 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Gordin, Michael D., author. Scientific Babel : how science was done before and after global English / Michael D. Gordin. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-226-00029-9 (cloth : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-0-226-00032-9 (e-book) 1. Communication in science. 2. English language— Technical English. I. Title. Q223.G67 2015 501'.4—dc23 2014032723 ♾ This paper meets the requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39.48–1992 (Permanence of Paper). To my language teachers Contents Introduction: Talking Science 1 Chapter 1: The Perfect Past That Almost Was 23 Chapter 2: The Table and the Word 51 Chapter 3: Hydrogen Oxygenovich 79 Chapter 4: Speaking Utopian 105 Chapter 5: The Wizards of Ido 131 Chapter 6: The Linguistic Shadow of the Great War 159 Chapter 7: Unspeakable 187 Chapter 8: The Dostoevsky Machine 213 Chapter 9: All the Russian That’s Fit to Print 241 Chapter 10: The Fe Curtain 267 Chapter 11: Anglophonia 293 Conclusion: Babel Beyond 317 Acknowledgments 327 List of Archives 331 Notes 333 Index 403 Introduction Talking Science Les savants des autres nations à qui nous avons donné l’exemple, ont cru avec raison qu’il écriraient encore mieux dans leur langue que dans la nôtre.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | E-Mail: [email protected] Mathesis Universalis: the Search for a Universal Scienc
    12/7/2021 Mathesis Universalis: the Search for a Universal Science Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Mathesis Universalis: the Search for a Universal Science INTRODUCTION "Preliminary remark: It is never quite clear what (the modern concept of mathesis universalis as such exactly signifies, let alone how it may be defined. The expression itself (1) is a composite of the Greek μάθησεως latinized by transcription to mathesis, and the Latin universalis. The latinized mathesis, generally meaning, according to the dictionaries, learning / knowledge / science (= disciplina or scientia), (2) more specifically designates mathematic (= scientia mathematica), though it can even mean astrology. Hence the first and general sense of mathesis universalis signifies no more than universal science (disciplina universalis or scientia universalis). However – and this will be very important – since this "science" has a rather mathematical ring to it, we should on second thoughts take it to be an equivalent of s cientia mathematica universalis (3) (or generalis or communis: due to the underlying Greek terminology, there is no difference between universal, general, or common in antiquity – things will have changed by Leibniz' time at the latest, of course). This more specific meaning, i.e., universal (or general or common) mathematical science or universal mathematic, is essential, and more or less the bottom line for most occurrences of the expression, though it still remains very vague. However, the emphasis of this paper lies, with regard to the concept of mathesis universalis not so much on the historical details as on the more general systematical outlines. Therefore it should suffice to begin our work with an understanding of mathesis universalis that implies not much more than universal (or general or common) mathematical science, which of course still allows for a range of diverse meanings.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Philosophy and Philosophical Science Hourya Benis Sinaceur
    Scientific Philosophy and Philosophical Science Hourya Benis Sinaceur To cite this version: Hourya Benis Sinaceur. Scientific Philosophy and Philosophical Science. Tahiri Hassan. The Philosophers and Mathematics. Festschrift for Roshdi Rashed, pp.25-66, 2018, 978-3-319-93733-5. 10.1007/978-3-319-93733-5. halshs-01935233 HAL Id: halshs-01935233 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01935233 Submitted on 26 Nov 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Hourya Benis Sinaceur Directrice de recherche émérite Institut d’Histoire et Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques (IHPST) Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne – CNRS – ENS Ulm International Colloquium The Philosophers and Mathematics Lisbon, October 2014 Scientific Philosophy and Philosophical Science (2016-12-21) Abstract Philosophical systems have developed for centuries, but only in the nineteenth century did the notion of scientific philosophy emerge. This notion presented two dimensions in the early twentieth century. One dimension arose from scientists’ concern with conceptual foundations for their disciplines, while another arose from philosophers’ appetite for more rigorous philosophy. In the current paper, I will focus on David Hilbert’s construct of “critical mathematics” and Edmund Husserl’ and Jules Vuillemin’s systematic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant the Critique of Pure Reason
    Immanuel Kant The Critique of Pure Reason Translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn Table of Contents ● PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781 ● PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 ● INTRODUCTION. ● I. Of the difference between Pure and Empirical Knowledge ● II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State, is in Possession of Certain Cognitions “a priori”. ● III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which shall Determine the Possibility, Principles, and Extent of Human Knowledge “a priori” ● IV. Of the Difference Between Analytical and Synthetical Judgements. ● V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements “a priori” are contained as Principles. ● VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason. ● VII. Idea and Division of a Particular Science, under the Name of a Critique of Pure Reason. ● I. TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF ELEMENTS. ● FIRST PART. TRANSCENDENTAL AESTHETIC. ❍ SS 1. Introductory. ❍ SECTION I. Of Space. ■ SS 2. Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception. ■ SS 3. Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Space. ■ SS 4. Conclusions from the foregoing Conceptions. ❍ SECTION II. Of Time. ■ SS 5 Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception. ■ SS 6 Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Time. ■ SS 7 Conclusions from the above Conceptions. ■ SS 8 Elucidation. ■ SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic. ■ SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic. ● SECOND PART. TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC. ❍ INTRODUCTION. Idea of a Transcendental Logic. ■ I. Of Logic in General. ■ II. Of Transcendental Logic. ■ III. Of the Division of General Logic into Analytic and Dialectic. ■ IV. Of the Division of Transcendental Logic into Transcendental Analytic and Dialectic. ❍ Transcendental Logic. FIRST DIVISION. ❍ TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC. ❍ SS 1. ❍ BOOK I. Analytic of Conceptions.
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Biology
    Universal Biology by Carlos Mariscal Department of Philosophy Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Robert N. Brandon, Co-Supervisor ___________________________ Alexander Rosenberg, Co-Supervisor ___________________________ Tyler Curtain ___________________________ Daniel W. McShea ___________________________ Karen Neander ___________________________ V. Louise Roth Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Duke University 2014 ABSTRACT Universal Biology by Carlos Mariscal Department of Philosophy Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Robert N. Brandon, Co-Supervisor ___________________________ Alexander Rosenberg, Co-Supervisor ___________________________ Tyler Curtain ___________________________ Daniel W. McShea ___________________________ Karen Neander ___________________________ V. Louise Roth An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Duke University 2014 Universal Biology by Carlos Mariscal is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/deed.en_US. 2014 Abstract Our only example of life is our own– which forms a single lineage. We know little about
    [Show full text]
  • On the Permanence of Metaphysics
    On the permanence of metaphysics K ATIA SANTOS §1. Introduction S OF 1960, A REDISCOVERY OF METAPHYSICS in the analytic tradition has begun, with a large number of works dedicated to the discussion of its A problems being published in England and the United States1. It is interesting to observe, however, that they all point to an investigation taken in the same direction, namely what is understood as a systematic study of the fundamental structure of reality. Edward J. Lowe, for example, in The possibility of metaphysics: substance, identity and time, writes: «Traditionally, metaphysics has been thought of as the systematic study of the most fundamental structure of reality — and, indeed, that is the view of it which I should like to support» (2001, p. 2). The same conception is defended by several other contemporary exponents, who have made a concentrated effort to identify metaphysics with ontology, thus reducing its scope to the investigation of the foundations of natural science. From our point of view, the fundamental theses of the analytic conception about nature and the possibility of metaphysics are untenable. They are, in fact, anti–metaphysical. Their origins lie in the great detractors of metaphysics of the last century, among which the most fierce was the Vienna Circle. The attacks, exacerbated and ferocious, in which it was claimed that metaphysical propositions and issues were meaningless, being considered pseudo– proposition without meaning, are well known2. There was a project to eliminate metaphysics, which nodal point was that it would accept as significant terms that have no reference in experience, such as «absolute», «thing–in–itself», «unconditioned».
    [Show full text]