Towards an Externalist Neuroeconomics: Dual Selves, Signs, and Choice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Towards an Externalist Neuroeconomics: Dual Selves, Signs, and Choice Journal of Neuroscience, Psychology, and Economics © 2012 American Psychological Association 2012, Vol. 5, No. 1, 38–61 1937-321X/12/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0026882 Towards an Externalist Neuroeconomics: Dual Selves, Signs, and Choice Carsten Herrmann-Pillath Frankfurt School of Finance and Management Recently, reductionist models of choice have been proposed which directly reduce a modified version of economic utility theory to neuroscience. I propose an alternative conceptual framework that adopts the position of externalism, which I further narrow down to a distributed cognition framework, and eventually to a biosemiotic model of human choice. I relate this to existing modular theories on the brain, which I generalize into a dual selves model. In this model, the internal information asymmetries and deficiencies of the brain/body system drive the reliance of choices on external cognitive mechanisms as manifested in sign systems. I analyze this interaction and apply the combined biosemiotics/dual selves model to an important set of falsifiers of an integrated reductionist model of neuroeconomics, that is, addiction and other consump- tion disorders. Keywords: foundations of neuroeconomics, semiotics, dual selves, distributed cognition, con- sumption disorders I. Externalism Versus Internalism in conscious and automatic processes, and Neuroeconomics would thus result in models which differ from the standard economic model (Camerer, 2007; One of the fundamental issues in current Camerer, Loewenstein, & Prelec, 2005). The neuroeconomic research is the question of drawback of these views is that they still lack whether the analysis of the brain should fol- a coherent and consistent theoretical frame- low the standard economic model or whether work comparable to the standard economic the introduction of an alternative framework approach in terms of its simplicity, consis- is needed. Following the standard economic tency and empirical tractability. This defi- model means referring to the utility function ciency also affects the applied fields of neu- framework and identifying neural correlates. roeconomics (as recognized by Hubert, 2010; This paradigm has been established canoni- Hubert & Kenning, 2008). On the other hand, cally by Glimcher (2009, 2011). Alternative however, a paradox lurks behind the reduc- approaches would take certain insights from tionist program. Ultimately, applied (neuro)- psychology and the brain sciences as a start- economics would no longer need to refer to ing point, such as the distinction between neuroscience at all, because on the level of observable behavior the (possibly modified) standard economic tools would suffice. It is I received important advice from the JNPE referees, precisely if the reduction program can suc- which helped to improve the paper substantially. Parts of ceed that neuroeconomics will become irrel- earlier versions were presented to workshops at Durham University, Jena University and the annual Neuropsy- evant for economics because all the essential choeconomics conference 2011 and the EAEPE 2011 an- insights of neuroeconomics would be repro- nual conference at Vienna. I am indebted to Don Ross for ducible within economics without any refer- his detailed comments. The usual disclaimer applies. Fi- ence to neuronal facts. This would be the case nally, special thanks to Judith Mader who polished my English language. as long as the phenomena to be explained Correspondence concerning this article should be ad- remain on the ontological level of the units of dressed to Carsten Herrmann-Pillath, Academic Director, choice, that is, the individuals (for related East-West Centre for Business Studies and Cultural Sci- criticisms of neuroeconomics, see Bernheim, ence, Frankfurt School of Finance and Management, Son- nemannstraße 9-11, 60314 Frankfurt am Main, Germany. 2009; Gul & Pesendorfer, 2008; Harrison, E-mail: [email protected] 2008). Therefore, Glimcher’s (2011) method- 38 TOWARDS AN EXTERNALIST NEUROECONOMICS 39 ological claims deserve close attention, and reductionism and to search for an alternative are certainly a crucible for testing the relation that needs to be externalist if it aims at an between neuroscience and economics. integration between neuroscience and econom- ics. Therefore, my article aims to offer a con- The Pivot: Externalism in the ceptual framework for externalist neuroeco- Philosophy of Mind nomics (a research program inaugurated by Ross, 2005). In this article my central concern is how to design a conceptual framework for neuroco- Rendering Externalism Empirically nomics which offers an alternative to the re- Tractable: Biosemiotics ductionist approach, and because of this will demonstrate the ultimate relevance of neuro- To achieve the aim of establishing the case economics and neuroscience for economics. for externalist neuroeconomics, I rely on other In doing this, I mainly adopt a philosophical approaches to externalism in the cognitive sci- perspective, especially the philosophy of ences which focus on the role of external causal mind, in order to construct a conceptual processes establishing mental phenomena in framework which might help to organize the terms of interactions between neuronal states different theoretical propositions and hypoth- and external facts. These approaches are to be eses that come together at the neuroeconom- found in the growing literature on “distributed ics interface, although originally emerging cognition” or the “extended mind” (e.g., Clark, from different disciplines (compare Foxall, 2011; Hutchins, 1995; Hutchins, 2005; 2008). Sterelny, 2004; Ross, Spurrett, Kincaid, & Ste- One foundational issue in the philosophy of phens, 2007; for a critical view, see, e.g., Spre- mind is the distinction between externalism and vak, 2009). In this literature, the operations of internalism regarding mental phenomena (for the human mind are seen as being fundamen- surveys, see Lau & Deutsch, 2008; Schantz, tally dependent on external facts, referring not 2004; Wilson, 2004). Reductionist neuroeco- only to the obvious role of devices which lever- nomics seems ambivalent with regard to this age cognitive skills, but more fundamentally to distinction and this reveals the need for a con- the externalization of all cognitive processes in ceptual clarification. The reason for this is that the sense that cognitive performance essentially the standard economic model is externalist, involves the external world and includes both whereas its proposed neuroeconomic version is physical entities and social interaction. There- internalist. Externalism in economics is re- fore, a straightforward sketch of an externalist flected in the revealed preference approach to approach that is different from the externalism the utility function: The utility function refers of standard economics is possible. This would exclusively to observable behavior with no ref- offer a fresh view on neuroeconomics (for a erence whatsoever to internal mental states; the related argument, see Wilcox, 2008). In this concept of utility is merely a mathematical de- view, if one continued to use the term “utility” vice to describe observed actions (Ross, 2005). in explaining human choice, “utility” would not In contrast, reductionist interpretations of the correspond exclusively to a neuronal state in a utility concept refer exclusively to internal neu- neuro-reductionist approach, but to a causal ronal states. So the important difference be- conjunction between a neuronal state and an tween economics and reductionist neuroeco- external fact. nomics is that the former is externalist, the latter In order to render the philosophical approach internalist: This means that reductionist claims of externalism applicable in the context of neu- actually result in a metamorphosis of the (im- roeconomics, I propose to introduce the ap- plicit) economic position of externalism into proach of biosemiotics (which is a new way of one of internalism. As a consequence, reduc- making use of semiotics in our context; for tionist neuroeconomics entails a fundamental surveys on other uses in consumer research, see clash between two philosophical positions im- Mick, 1986; Mick, Burroughs, Hetzel, & Bran- plicit in the two disciplinary approaches. I argue nen, 2004). According to this view, all mental that this inconsistency in the philosophical phenomena are seen as interactions between foundations is a sufficient reason to discard neuronal states and signs, with signs being ex- 40 HERRMANN-PILLATH ternal physical facts. These interactions have a nomena to empirically substantiate my argu- function, which basically boils down to biolog- ment here. This also seems methodologically ical categories such as homeostasis or adapta- appropriate as the phenomenon of addiction can tion, which are relative to the environment. This be seen as one of the possible strong falsifiers of reflects the etiological approach to function, standard economic models of consumer choice, which sees functions as the result of past and seminally applied by Becker and Murphy current processes of selection in particular en- (1988) to addiction (see Ross, Sharp, vironments (for an overview of theories of func- Vuchinich, & Spurrett, 2008; West, 2006). tion, see Krohs & Kroes, 2009). Thus, the con- Biosemiotics builds on the philosophy of junction between internal neuronal states and Charles Sanders Peirce (for a selection of im- external facts has a function relative to a con- portant contributions, see Peirce, 1992, 1998, text. and
Recommended publications
  • Neuroeconomics: the Neurobiology of Decision-Making
    Neuroeconomics: The Neurobiology of Decision-Making Ifat Levy Section of Comparative Medicine Department of Neurobiology Interdepartmental Neuroscience Program Yale School of Medicine Harnessing eHealth and Behavioral Economics for HIV Prevention and Treatment April 2012 Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions Neuroeconomics NeuroscienceNeuronal MentalPsychology states “asEconomics if” models architecture Abstraction Neuroeconomics Behavioral Economics Neuroscience Psychology Economics Abstraction Neuroscience functional MRI VISUAL STIMULUS functional MRI: Blood Oxygenation Level Dependent signals Neural Changes in oxygen Change in activity consumption, blood flow concentration of and blood volume deoxyhemoglobin Change in Signal from each measured point in space at signal each point in time t = 1 t = 2 t = 3 t = 4 t = 5 t = 6 dorsal anterior posterior lateral ventral dorsal anterior medial posterior ventral Anterior The cortex Cingulate Cortex (ACC) Medial Prefrontal Cortex (MPFC) Posterior Cingulate Cortex (PCC) Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex (vMPFC) Orbitofrontal Cortex (OFC) Sub-cortical structures fMRI signal • Spatial resolution: ~3x3x3mm3 Low • Temporal resolution: ~1-2s Low • Number of voxels: ~150,000 High • Typical signal change: 0.2%-2% Low • Typical noise: more than the signal… High But… • Intact human
    [Show full text]
  • Volatility As Link Between Risk and Memory in Economics, Econometrics and Neuroeconomics: an Application for the Bolivian Inflation Rate 1938 - 2012
    Volatility as link between risk and memory in Economics, Econometrics and Neuroeconomics: an application for the Bolivian Inflation Rate 1938 - 2012 María Edith Chacón B. [email protected] Teacher and researcher CIDES – UMSA. La Paz, Bolivia. Ernesto Sheriff B. [email protected] Teacher and researcher CIDES – UMSA and UPB. La Paz, Bolivia. Experimental and Behavioral Economics: Other Neuroeconomics Econometrics: Time Series ABSTRACT This paper provides an indicator that measures memory as a stock. Memory affects economic decisions thus the memory indicator is useful to help in applied work, it was built according to the state of the art in Psychology and Neuroeconomics and it is presented as a time series; it is a recursive one and it is represented by an accumulated measure of the volatility. Many theories of risk have used volatility indicators to represent risk in the applied work. Risk valuation is associated to volatility and it is very sensitive to periods in which it is measured; it is very sensitive too to the type of data associated to volatility. In this paper we found that the memory affects risk valuations and the link between them is a special kind of volatility i.e. accumulated volatility with an endogenous initialization period and compatible with many Psychological hypotheses. The developed indicator is compatible with the econometrics of stationary series, integrated series and fractional integrated series. These contributions help to improve the study of hysteresis in applied economics, to develop more consistent links between memory and risk in Neuroeconomics and, to obtain more confident time series models in econometrics using the new indicator.
    [Show full text]
  • Economists As Worldly Philosophers
    Economists as Worldly Philosophers Robert J. Shiller and Virginia M. Shiller Yale University Hitotsubashi University, March 11, 2014 Virginia M. Shiller • Married, 1976 • Ph.D. Clinical Psychology, University of Delaware 1984 • Intern, Cambridge Hospital, Harvard Medical School, 1980-1 • Clinical Instructor, Yale Child Study Center, since 2000 • Private practice with children, adults, and families Robert Heilbroner 1919-2005 • His book The Worldly Philosophers: Lives, Times and Ideas of the Great Economic Thinkers, 1953, sold four million copies • Adam Smith, Henry George, Karl Marx, John Stewart Mill, John Maynard Keynes, Thomas Malthus Example: Adam Smith • Theory of Moral Sentiments, 1759 • The Wealth of Nations, 1776 • Did not shrink from moral judgments, e. g., frugality Example: John Maynard Keynes • Economic Consequences of the Peace • The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money, 1936 Economics as a Moral Science • The kinds of questions economists are asked to opine on are inherently moral • Moral calculus requires insights into the complexities of human behavior • A plea for behavioral economics and a broader focus for economic research Kenneth Boulding 1910-1993 • “We cannot escape the proposition that as science moves from pure knowledge toward control, that is, toward creating what it knows, what it creates becomes a problem of ethical choice, and will depend upon the common values of the societies in which the scientific culture is embedded, as well as of the scientific subculture.” Boulding on the Theory that People Maximize Utility of their Own Consumption • That there is neither malevolence nor benevolence anywhere in the system is demonstrably false. • “Anything less descriptive of the human condition could hardly be imagined.” (from American Economics Association Presidential Address, 1968).
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Cognitive Load Increases Risk Aversion 5 2.1 Introduction
    Essays in Experimental and Neuroeconomics DISSERTATION zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Dr. rer. pol. im Fach Volkswirtschaftslehre eingereicht an der Wirtschaftswissenschaftlichen Fakultät der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin von Diplom-Volkswirt Holger Gerhardt geboren am 17. Januar 1978 in Arnsberg Präsident der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin: Prof. Dr. Jan-Hendrik Olbertz Dekan der Wirtschaftswissenschaftlichen Fakultät: Prof. Oliver Günther, Ph. D. Gutachter: 1. Prof. Lutz Weinke, Ph. D. 2. Prof. Dr. Hauke R. Heekeren eingereicht am: 9. Mai 2011 Tag des Kolloquiums: 20. Juni 2011 Contents 1 Introduction 1 Bibliography . 3 2 Cognitive load increases risk aversion 5 2.1 Introduction . 5 2.2 Related literature . 7 2.2.1 Introductory remarks . 7 2.2.2 Overview of dual-system and “dual-self” approaches . 7 2.2.3 Subjective expected-utility theory as a unitary-process model of decision making under risk . 10 2.2.4 Dual-process approaches to decision making under risk . 11 2.2.5 Empirical evidence on dual processes in decision making under risk . 12 2.3 Experimental design . 17 2.3.1 Introduction: Advantages of our design over alternative designs . 17 2.3.2 Trial setup . 18 2.3.3 Additional measures of individual differences . 24 2.4 Results . 24 2.4.1 Introductory remarks . 24 2.4.2 Were the tasks adequate? . 25 2.4.3 How did subjects allocate attention to the two simultane- ous tasks? . 25 2.4.4 Preference reversal?—How often did subjects choose the riskier lottery? . 26 2.4.5 Structural regressions: the influence of additional cognitive load on subjects’ degree of relative risk aversion .
    [Show full text]
  • The Future of Economics in a Lakatos–Bourdieu Framework
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive The Future of Economics in a Lakatos–Bourdieu Framework. Heise, Arne University of Hamburg 2014 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/80024/ MPRA Paper No. 80024, posted 05 Jul 2017 05:42 UTC The Future of Economics in a Lakatos-Bourdieu framework Prof. Arne Heise University of Hamburg Dep. of Socioeconomics VMP 9 D-20146 Hamburg [email protected] Abstract The global financial crisis has clearly been a matter of great consternation for the busi- ness-as-usual faction of mainstream economics. Will the World Financial Crisis turn out to be that ‘experimentum crucis’ which triggered a scientific revolution? In this paper, we seek to assess the likelihood of a paradigm shift towards heterodox approaches and a more pluralist setting in economics emerging from the academic establishment in the U.S. – that is, from the dominant center of knowledge production in the economic disci- pline. This will be done by building the analysis on a combined Lakatosian framework of ‘battle of research programmes’ and a Bourdieuian framework of ‘power struggle’ within the academic field and highlighting the likelihood of two main proponents of the mainstream elite to become the promulgator of change? Keywords: Paradigm, heterodox economics, scientific revolution JEL codes: A 11, E 11, E 12 1 1. The Keynesian Revolution and Pragmatic Pluralism – A Fruitful Competition Between Theories or a Crisis in Economics? John Maynard Keynes concludes ‘The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money’ (1936: 383-84) with the following, now-famous words: „At the present moment people are unusually expectant of a more funda- mental diagnosis; more particularly ready to receive it; eager to try it out, if it should be even possible.
    [Show full text]
  • John Von Neumann Oskar Morgenstern
    Neuroeconomics: From The Failures of Expected Utility to the Neurobiology of Choice Paul Glimcher PhD Julius Silver Professor of Neural Science, Economics and Psychology Director, Institute of the Study of Decision Making New York University Blaise Pascal Genius: Expected Value Theory Expected Probability x Value = Value #1 0.5 100 50 #2 1.0 45 45 Pascal's Wager If God Exists If God Doesn't Exist (Prob 3 Value) + (Prob 3 Value) = Exp. Value Believe in God >0 3 `$++ 0 3 0 = ` Do not Believe >0 3 2` ++ $0 3 0 = 2` in God Problem: The Beggar’s Dilemma Daniel Bernoulli Genius: Expected Utility Theory Beggar’s Dilemma 4.3 3.8 Beggar’s Utility (utils) Beggar’s 0 7000 20,000 Rich Man’s Choice Beggar’s Wealth (florins) 6.0056 6.0 5.9969 Rich Man’s Utility (utils) Rich Man’s Problem: 0 losses wins Value ($) Bentham, Pareto, Samuelson 993,000 1,013,000 1,000,000 Jeremy Bentham Vilfredo Pareto Paul Samuelson The Calculus of Utility The Intrinsic Arbitrariness of Utility Ordinal Objective Utility John von Neumann Oskar Morgenstern Genius: Modern Expected Utility Theory 0 < a <1 a $ s = Expected 35til u Utility weight s.w. = prob Subjective 0 Utility (utils) 0 Probability Dollars ($) Critcal Advantages: • Precise • Compact • Normative (people Problem: make sense) Maurice Allais Maurice Allais People Do Not Obey EU all the time 0 < a <1 a $ s = Expected 35til u Utility weight s.w. = prob Subjective 0 Utility (utils) 0 XProbability Dollars ($) Critcal Questons: • How to Predict People? • Are People Dumb? • Why? Amos Tversky Danny Kahneman Prospect Theory Critcal Advantages: • Predictive Critcal Disadvantages: • Bulky • No Why Behavioral Traditional Social-Natural Science Boundary Economics vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Neuroeconomics
    Handbook of Experimental Economics Editors: John Kagel and Alvin Roth Neuroeconomics Colin Camerer1 (California Institute of Technology), Jonathan Cohen2 (Princeton University), Ernst Fehr3 (University of Zurich), Paul Glimcher4 (New York University), David Laibson5 (Harvard University) 1Division HSS, Caltech, [email protected]; 2Princeton Neuroscience Institute, Princeton University, [email protected]; 3University of Zurich, Department of Economics, [email protected]; 4Center for Neural Science, New York University, [email protected]; 5Department of Economics, Harvard University, [email protected]. We gratefully acknowledge research assistance from Colin Gray and Gwen Reynolds and key guidance from John Kagel, Alvin Roth, and an anonymous referee. We also acknowledge financial support from the Moore Foundation (Camerer), the National Science Foundation (Camerer), and the National Institute of Aging (Cohen; Glimcher, R01AG033406; Laibson, P01AG005842), the Swiss National Science Foundation (Fehr, CRSII3_141965/1) and the European Research Council (Fehr, 295642). Hyperlink Page Introduction Chapter 1: Neurobiological Foundations Chapter 2: Functional MRI Chapter 3: Risky Choice Chapter 4: Intertemporal choice and self-regulation Chapter 5: The neural circuitry of social preferences Chapter 6: Strategic thinking References Introduction “One may wonder whether Adam Smith, were he working today, would not be a neuroeconomi[st]” Aldo Rustichini (2005). Neuroeconomics is the study of the biological microfoundations of economic
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Neuroeconomics of Asset-Price Bubbles
    Neuroeconomics of Asset-Price Bubbles: Toward the Prediction and Prevention of Major Bubbles John L. Haracz* Goldman School of Public Policy, UC Berkeley and Department of Psychological and Brain Sciences, Indiana University [email protected] and Daniel J. Acland Goldman School of Public Policy, UC Berkeley [email protected] Goldman School of Public Policy Working Paper January 16, 2015 Abstract Asset-price bubbles challenge the explanatory and predictive power of standard economic theory, suggesting that neuroeconomic measures should be explored as potential tools for improving the predictive power of standard theory. We begin this exploration by reviewing results from functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) studies of lab asset-price bubbles and herding behavior (i.e., following others' decisions). These results are consistent with a neuroeconomics-based hypothesis of asset-price bubbles. In this view, decision making during bubble or non-bubble periods of financial- market activity is driven by, respectively, evolutionarily ancient or new neurocircuitry. Neuroimaging studies that test this or other neuroeconomics-based hypotheses of asset-price bubbles may yield a bubble-related biomarker (e.g., low trade-related lateral neocortical activity associated with traders’ herding-based decisions). Wearable functional near-infrared spectroscopy (fNIRS) technology could determine the prevalence of such a biomarker among financial-market participants, thereby enabling the real-time detection of an emerging bubble. We describe mechanisms by which this early-warning signal could be exploited in self-regulatory or government-administered policies for financial-system stabilization. In summary, neuroimaging-based financial-system regulation may be useful for distinguishing bubbles from non-bubble periods and preventing major asset-price bubbles.
    [Show full text]
  • Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain 81 © 2009, Elsevier Inc
    Neuroeconomics Decision Making and the Brain Edited by Paul W. Glimcher, PhD Center for Neuroeconomics New York University New York, NY, USA Colin F. Camerer, PhD Division of Humanities and Social Sciences California Institute of Technology Pasadena, CA, USA Ernst Fehr, PhD Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zürich Zürich, Switzerland Russell A. Poldrack, PhD Department of Psychology University of California Los Angeles Los Angeles, CA, USA AMSTERDAM • BOSTON • HEIDELBERG • LONDON NEW YORK • OXFORD • PARIS • SAN DIEGO SAN FRANCISCO • SINGAPORE • SYDNEY • TOKYO Academic Press is an imprint of Elsevier CHAPTER 7 The Evolution of Rational and Irrational Economic Behavior: Evidence and Insight from a Non-human Primate Species Laurie R. Santos and M. Keith Chen OUTLINE Introduction 81 Do Capuchins Obey Price Theory as Humans Do? 88 Neoclassical Approaches to Non-standard Behavior 82 Do Capuchins Display the Same Biases as Humans? 88 Price-Theoretic Treatments 82 Are Capuchins Reference Dependent and Axiomatic Approaches 83 Loss Averse? 88 Behavioral Economics Approaches 84 Framing and Risk: Do Capuchins Exhibit a Reflection Effect? 89 The Role of Non-human Primate Studies in Do Capuchins Exhibit an Endowment Effect? 90 Modern Economics 84 What Comparative Work Means for Traditional Primate Evolution 101 85 Economics and Neuroeconomics 90 Acknowledgements 91 Revealing Capuchin Preferences: The Token Trading Methodology 87 References 92 INTRODUCTION Second, people are endowed with effortlessly rational, error-free cognition. This assumption may entail Modern economics as it is currently practiced is an agents simply understanding their own preferences, exercise in applying three basic principles to nearly all or it may ask that they solve arbitrarily complex sig- settings.
    [Show full text]
  • Response Times and Contributions to a Real World Public Good
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Lohse, Johannes; Goeschl, Timo; Diederich , Johannes Working Paper Giving is a question of time: Response times and contributions to a real world public good Discussion Paper Series, No. 566 Provided in Cooperation with: Alfred Weber Institute, Department of Economics, University of Heidelberg Suggested Citation: Lohse, Johannes; Goeschl, Timo; Diederich , Johannes (2014) : Giving is a question of time: Response times and contributions to a real world public good, Discussion Paper Series, No. 566, University of Heidelberg, Department of Economics, Heidelberg, http://dx.doi.org/10.11588/heidok.00017046 This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/127384 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence.
    [Show full text]
  • Neuroeconomics: How Neuroscience Can Inform Economics
    mr05_Article 1 3/28/05 3:25 PM Page 9 Journal of Economic Literature Vol. XLIII (March 2005), pp. 9–64 Neuroeconomics: How Neuroscience Can Inform Economics ∗ COLIN CAMERER, GEORGE LOEWENSTEIN, and DRAZEN PRELEC Who knows what I want to do? Who knows what anyone wants to do? How can you be sure about something like that? Isn’t it all a question of brain chemistry, signals going back and forth, electrical energy in the cortex? How do you know whether something is really what you want to do or just some kind of nerve impulse in the brain. Some minor little activity takes place somewhere in this unimportant place in one of the brain hemispheres and suddenly I want to go to Montana or I don’t want to go to Montana. (White Noise, Don DeLillo) 1. Introduction such as finance, game theory, labor econom- ics, public finance, law, and macroeconomics In the last two decades, following almost a (see Colin Camerer and George Loewenstein century of separation, economics has begun 2004). Behavioral economics has mostly been to import insights from psychology. informed by a branch of psychology called “Behavioral economics” is now a prominent “behavioral decision research,” but other fixture on the intellectual landscape and has cognitive sciences are ripe for harvest. Some spawned applications to topics in economics, important insights will surely come from neu- roscience, either directly or because neuro- ∗ Camerer: California Institute of Technology. science will reshape what is believed about Loewenstein: Carnegie Mellon University. Prelec: psychology which in turn informs economics. Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
    [Show full text]
  • Neuroeconomics and the Governance of Choice in Time
    Social Studies of Science 41(4) 515–538 The shortsighted brain: © The Author(s) 2011 Reprints and permission: sagepub. Neuroeconomics and the co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/0306312710397689 governance of choice in time sss.sagepub.com Natasha Dow Schüll Program in Science, Technology & Society, MIT, Cambridge, MA, USA Caitlin Zaloom Department of Social & Cultural Analysis, NYU, New York, NY, USA Abstract The young field of neuroeconomics converges around behavioral deviations from the model of the human being as Homo economicus, a rational actor who calculates his choices to maximize his individual satisfaction. In a historical moment characterized by economic, health, and environmental crises, policymakers have become increasingly concerned about a particular deviation for which neuroeconomics offers a biological explanation: Why do humans value the present at the expense of the future? There is contentious debate within the field over how to model this tendency at the neural level. Should the brain be conceptualized as a unified decision-making apparatus, or as the site of conflict between an impetuous limbic system at perpetual odds with its deliberate and provident overseer in the prefrontal cortex? Scientific debates over choice-making in the brain, we argue, are also debates over how to define the constraints on human reason with which regulative strategies must contend. Drawing on ethnographic and archival research, we explore how the brain and its treatment of the future become the contested terrain for distinct visions of governmental intervention into problems of human choice-making. Keywords economics, epistemology, governance, liberalism, neuroeconomics, neuroscience, policy, rationality An undergraduate in jeans and a ponytail doffs her winter parka and climbs onto the bed of an fMRI [functional magnetic resonance imaging] machine.
    [Show full text]