Neuroeconomics: the Neurobiology of Decision-Making

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Neuroeconomics: the Neurobiology of Decision-Making Neuroeconomics: The Neurobiology of Decision-Making Ifat Levy Section of Comparative Medicine Department of Neurobiology Interdepartmental Neuroscience Program Yale School of Medicine Harnessing eHealth and Behavioral Economics for HIV Prevention and Treatment April 2012 Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions Neuroeconomics NeuroscienceNeuronal MentalPsychology states “asEconomics if” models architecture Abstraction Neuroeconomics Behavioral Economics Neuroscience Psychology Economics Abstraction Neuroscience functional MRI VISUAL STIMULUS functional MRI: Blood Oxygenation Level Dependent signals Neural Changes in oxygen Change in activity consumption, blood flow concentration of and blood volume deoxyhemoglobin Change in Signal from each measured point in space at signal each point in time t = 1 t = 2 t = 3 t = 4 t = 5 t = 6 dorsal anterior posterior lateral ventral dorsal anterior medial posterior ventral Anterior The cortex Cingulate Cortex (ACC) Medial Prefrontal Cortex (MPFC) Posterior Cingulate Cortex (PCC) Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex (vMPFC) Orbitofrontal Cortex (OFC) Sub-cortical structures fMRI signal • Spatial resolution: ~3x3x3mm3 Low • Temporal resolution: ~1-2s Low • Number of voxels: ~150,000 High • Typical signal change: 0.2%-2% Low • Typical noise: more than the signal… High But… • Intact human brain • Behaving human • Whole brain • Non-invasive Neuroeconomics Cognitive Neuroscience Behavioral Economics Neuroscience Psychology Economics Abstraction New challenge: how do you make sense of such huge amounts of data?? Neuroeconomics Mechanistic constraints of the human brain Cognitive Behavioral Neuroscience Economics Economic models as normative theory Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions certainty risk ambiguity 100% 50% unknown partial full full relief remission remission Choose one: A B Risky OR Ambiguous Most people choose A, implying that B has fewer red than blue chips: red < blue A B Risky OR Ambiguous Most people choose A, implying that B has fewer blue than red chips: blue < red The Ellsberg paradox: a bag cannot have fewer red chips and fewer blue chips at the same time Non-certain outcomes • Risk – probabilities of different outcomes are known • Ambiguity – probabilities of different outcomes are not known • Partial ambiguity – partial information known probability risk aversion high probability low low probability high reward reward $40 unknown probability ambiguity aversion known probability unknown probability low reward high reward $110$0 $0$110 Value of risk and ambiguity Risk and ambiguity affect the subjective value of an option in very different ways Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions Research Question neural representation of value multiple systems single system reward reward punishment punishment immediate delayed cognitive cognitive delayed immediate emotional . emotional . Research Question neural representation of value multiple systems single system ambiguity vs. risk ambiguity & risk x,y,0.5,5 Experimental design Experimental design Amount Probability Ambiguity level OR: - Winning color - $5 Parametric design Real bags One trial played for real money Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p (chose (chose risky) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p (chose (chose risky) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p (chose (chose risky) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p (chose (chose risky) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p (chose (chose risky) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p = 0.50 p (chose (chose risky) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p = 0.50 p (chose (chose risky) p p = 0.38 Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p = 0.50 p (chose (chose risky) p p = 0.38 p = 0.25 Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain-risk trials p = 0.75 p = 0.50 p (chose (chose risky) p p = 0.38 p = 0.25 p = 0.13 Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain ambiguity trials A = 0.25 p (chose (chose ambiguous) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain ambiguity trials A = 0.25 p (chose (chose ambiguous) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain ambiguity trials A = 0.25 A = 0.50 p (chose (chose ambiguous) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Gain ambiguity trials A = 0.25 A = 0.50 A = 0.75 p (chose (chose ambiguous) p Amount [$] $5 subject 1 Behavioral model MaxMin, Gilboa and Schmeidler 1989 subjective value ambiguity level − β A α ( p ) · V risk 2 preference amount probability ambiguity aversion stochastic choice model S1: gains S2: gains α = 0.55, β = 0.89 α = 0.58, β = -0.03 p = 0.75 p = 0.50 p = 0.38 p = 0.25 p = 0.13 A = 0.25 A = 0.50 p (chose p (chose lottery) A = 0.75 Amount [$] Amount [$] S1: gains S1: losses α = 0.55, β = 0.89 α = 0.58, β = -0.04 p = 0.75 p = 0.50 p = 0.38 p = 0.25 p = 0.13 A = 0.25 A = 0.50 p (chose p (chose lottery) A = 0.75 Amount [$] Amount [$] Gains Losses Ambiguity aversion Ambiguity Risk aversion Risk aversion Risk aversion Ambiguity aversion Losses Gains Gains A ( p − β )⋅V α 2 under risk subjectivevalue under ambiguity … … time Subjective value under ambiguity ACC / MPFC R L caudate posterior amygdala cingulate 19 subjects, random effect analysis P<0.002 P<0.0001 Subjective value under risk ACC / MPFC R L caudate posterior amygdala cingulate 19 subjects, random effect analysis P<0.01 P<0.001 Unique areas for SV under ambiguity? PCC amygdala No… %signal change %signal change risk ambiguity risk ambiguity Research Question neural representation of value multiple systems single system ambiguity vs. risk ambiguity & risk x,y,0.5,5 Uncertainty Summary 1 • High variability in risk and ambiguity attitudes across individuals • Areas in MPFC and striatum represent subjective value under both risk and ambiguity Can attitudes towards risk and ambiguity explain phenomena like risk-taking in adolescents and overeating in obese individuals? Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions Adolescents take risks • 200% increase in morbidity and mortality rates in adolescence compared to childhood (Dahl, 2004) • Adolescents are physically healthier and stronger than both children and adults (Dey et al., 2004) • Increase mostly attributed to risky behaviors: car accidents, alcohol and substance abuse, violence, eating disorders, unsafe sex (Reyna and Farley, 2006) • Not due to flawed reasoning capabilities, poor decision- making skills or failure to understand the consequences of their actions (Reyna and Farley, 2006) Subjects Age \ Female Male Total Gender 12-17 17 16 33 21-25 18 16 34 30-50 17 15 32 65-90 18 17 35 Total: 70 64 134 In collaboration with Paul Glimcher Adolescents vs. adults Uncertainty Summary 2 • Adolescents are more risk averse, but less ambiguity averse than adults • Young organisms need to learn about their world Do people treat risk and ambiguity similarly in different domains? In collaboration with Terri Fried Overview • Introduction to neuroeconomics • Decision under uncertainty – Brain and behavior – Adolescent behavior – Medical decisions “You were involved in a car accident and as a result suffered traumatic brain injury. You were immediately rushed to the nearest hospital and were informed by the doctor that without immediate treatment you will not survive.” Gains and losses in medical decisions Gains: cognitive improvement No effect Slight improvement Moderate improvement Major improvement Recovery Worst outcome Best outcome Major improvement = Mild cognitive disability: mild memory impairment resulting in forgetting some appointments, forgetting people’s names, needing a list to do food shopping No effect Slight improvement or recovery Major improvement Slight improvement or No effect Gains and losses in medical decisions Losses: headache as an adverse effect Critical headache Severe headache Moderate headache Mild headache Recovery Worst outcome Best outcome Moderate headache: improves but does not resolve with acetaminophen (Tylenol); requires you to lie down occasionally to relieve pain; occurs a couple of times a week. moderate headache Mild headache or recovery Severe headache Mild headache or recovery Decision under risk 1 Positive outcomes 1 Negative outcomes 0.9 0.9 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.5 0.5 0.4 0.4 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.2 Proportionof choices lottery 0.1 0.1 0 0 0.13 0.25 0.38 0.5 0.75 0.13 0.25 0.38 0.5 0.75 Outcome probability Outcome probability Money Medical N = 29 Decision under ambiguity 1 Money 1 Medical 0.9 0.9 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.5 0.5 0.4 0.4 0.3 0.3 Proportionof choices lottery 0.2 0.2 0.1 0.1 0 0 gain loss improvement adverse effect Ambiguity level: 0 0.25 0.50 0.75 N = 29 Uncertainty Summary 3 • Ambiguity aversion was observed both under gains and under losses when making medical decisions Summary • Economic models can be used to make sense of neural data • High variability across subjects in attitudes towards risk and ambiguity • Adolescents are more risk averse and less ambiguity averse than adults • Ambiguity aversion in medical decision- making for both positive and negative outcomes Acknowledgements Lab Collaborators Sarah Abdallah Paul Glimcher, NYU Jennifer Fanning Aldo Rustichini,
Recommended publications
  • Volatility As Link Between Risk and Memory in Economics, Econometrics and Neuroeconomics: an Application for the Bolivian Inflation Rate 1938 - 2012
    Volatility as link between risk and memory in Economics, Econometrics and Neuroeconomics: an application for the Bolivian Inflation Rate 1938 - 2012 María Edith Chacón B. [email protected] Teacher and researcher CIDES – UMSA. La Paz, Bolivia. Ernesto Sheriff B. [email protected] Teacher and researcher CIDES – UMSA and UPB. La Paz, Bolivia. Experimental and Behavioral Economics: Other Neuroeconomics Econometrics: Time Series ABSTRACT This paper provides an indicator that measures memory as a stock. Memory affects economic decisions thus the memory indicator is useful to help in applied work, it was built according to the state of the art in Psychology and Neuroeconomics and it is presented as a time series; it is a recursive one and it is represented by an accumulated measure of the volatility. Many theories of risk have used volatility indicators to represent risk in the applied work. Risk valuation is associated to volatility and it is very sensitive to periods in which it is measured; it is very sensitive too to the type of data associated to volatility. In this paper we found that the memory affects risk valuations and the link between them is a special kind of volatility i.e. accumulated volatility with an endogenous initialization period and compatible with many Psychological hypotheses. The developed indicator is compatible with the econometrics of stationary series, integrated series and fractional integrated series. These contributions help to improve the study of hysteresis in applied economics, to develop more consistent links between memory and risk in Neuroeconomics and, to obtain more confident time series models in econometrics using the new indicator.
    [Show full text]
  • History-Dependent Risk Attitude
    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Journal of Economic Theory 157 (2015) 445–477 www.elsevier.com/locate/jet History-dependent risk attitude ∗ David Dillenberger a, , Kareen Rozen b,1 a Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania, 160 McNeil Building, 3718 Locust Walk, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6297, United States b Department of Economics and the Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics, Yale University, 30 Hillhouse Avenue, New Haven, CT 06511, United States Received 21 June 2014; final version received 17 January 2015; accepted 24 January 2015 Available online 29 January 2015 Abstract We propose a model of history-dependent risk attitude, allowing a decision maker’s risk attitude to be affected by his history of disappointments and elations. The decision maker recursively evaluates compound risks, classifying realizations as disappointing or elating using a threshold rule. We establish equivalence between the model and two cognitive biases: risk attitudes are reinforced by experiences (one is more risk averse after disappointment than after elation) and there is a primacy effect (early outcomes have the greatest impact on risk attitude). In a dynamic asset pricing problem, the model yields volatile, path-dependent prices. © 2015 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. JEL classification: D03; D81; D91 Keywords: History-dependent risk attitude; Reinforcement effect; Primacy effect; Dynamic reference dependence * Corresponding author. E-mail addresses: [email protected] (D. Dillenberger), [email protected] (K. Rozen). 1 Rozen thanks the NSF for generous financial support through grant SES-0919955, and the economics departments of Columbia and NYU for their hospitality. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jet.2015.01.020 0022-0531/© 2015 Elsevier Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • Economists As Worldly Philosophers
    Economists as Worldly Philosophers Robert J. Shiller and Virginia M. Shiller Yale University Hitotsubashi University, March 11, 2014 Virginia M. Shiller • Married, 1976 • Ph.D. Clinical Psychology, University of Delaware 1984 • Intern, Cambridge Hospital, Harvard Medical School, 1980-1 • Clinical Instructor, Yale Child Study Center, since 2000 • Private practice with children, adults, and families Robert Heilbroner 1919-2005 • His book The Worldly Philosophers: Lives, Times and Ideas of the Great Economic Thinkers, 1953, sold four million copies • Adam Smith, Henry George, Karl Marx, John Stewart Mill, John Maynard Keynes, Thomas Malthus Example: Adam Smith • Theory of Moral Sentiments, 1759 • The Wealth of Nations, 1776 • Did not shrink from moral judgments, e. g., frugality Example: John Maynard Keynes • Economic Consequences of the Peace • The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money, 1936 Economics as a Moral Science • The kinds of questions economists are asked to opine on are inherently moral • Moral calculus requires insights into the complexities of human behavior • A plea for behavioral economics and a broader focus for economic research Kenneth Boulding 1910-1993 • “We cannot escape the proposition that as science moves from pure knowledge toward control, that is, toward creating what it knows, what it creates becomes a problem of ethical choice, and will depend upon the common values of the societies in which the scientific culture is embedded, as well as of the scientific subculture.” Boulding on the Theory that People Maximize Utility of their Own Consumption • That there is neither malevolence nor benevolence anywhere in the system is demonstrably false. • “Anything less descriptive of the human condition could hardly be imagined.” (from American Economics Association Presidential Address, 1968).
    [Show full text]
  • A Measure of Risk Tolerance Based on Economic Theory
    A Measure Of Risk Tolerance Based On Economic Theory Sherman D. Hanna1, Michael S. Gutter 2 and Jessie X. Fan3 Self-reported risk tolerance is a measurement of an individual's willingness to accept risk, making it a valuable tool for financial planners and researchers alike. Prior subjective risk tolerance measures have lacked a rigorous connection to economic theory. This study presents an improved measurement of subjective risk tolerance based on economic theory and discusses its link to relative risk aversion. Results from a web-based survey are presented and compared with results from previous studies using other risk tolerance measurements. The new measure allows for a wider possible range of risk tolerance to be obtained, with important implications for short-term investing. Key words: Risk tolerance, Risk aversion, Economic model Malkiel (1996, p. 401) suggested that the risk an to describe some preliminary patterns of risk tolerance investor should be willing to take or tolerate is related to based on the measure. The results suggest that there is the househ old situation, lifecycle stage, and subjective a wide variation of risk tolerance in people, but no factors. Risk tolerance is commonly used by financial systematic patterns related to gender or age have been planners, and is discussed in financial planning found. textbooks. For instance, Mittra (1995, p. 396) discussed the idea that risk tolerance measurement is usually not Literature Review precise. Most tests use a subjective measure of both There are at least four methods of measuring risk emotional and financial ability of an investor to tolerance: askin g about investment choices, asking a withstand losses.
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Cognitive Load Increases Risk Aversion 5 2.1 Introduction
    Essays in Experimental and Neuroeconomics DISSERTATION zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Dr. rer. pol. im Fach Volkswirtschaftslehre eingereicht an der Wirtschaftswissenschaftlichen Fakultät der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin von Diplom-Volkswirt Holger Gerhardt geboren am 17. Januar 1978 in Arnsberg Präsident der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin: Prof. Dr. Jan-Hendrik Olbertz Dekan der Wirtschaftswissenschaftlichen Fakultät: Prof. Oliver Günther, Ph. D. Gutachter: 1. Prof. Lutz Weinke, Ph. D. 2. Prof. Dr. Hauke R. Heekeren eingereicht am: 9. Mai 2011 Tag des Kolloquiums: 20. Juni 2011 Contents 1 Introduction 1 Bibliography . 3 2 Cognitive load increases risk aversion 5 2.1 Introduction . 5 2.2 Related literature . 7 2.2.1 Introductory remarks . 7 2.2.2 Overview of dual-system and “dual-self” approaches . 7 2.2.3 Subjective expected-utility theory as a unitary-process model of decision making under risk . 10 2.2.4 Dual-process approaches to decision making under risk . 11 2.2.5 Empirical evidence on dual processes in decision making under risk . 12 2.3 Experimental design . 17 2.3.1 Introduction: Advantages of our design over alternative designs . 17 2.3.2 Trial setup . 18 2.3.3 Additional measures of individual differences . 24 2.4 Results . 24 2.4.1 Introductory remarks . 24 2.4.2 Were the tasks adequate? . 25 2.4.3 How did subjects allocate attention to the two simultane- ous tasks? . 25 2.4.4 Preference reversal?—How often did subjects choose the riskier lottery? . 26 2.4.5 Structural regressions: the influence of additional cognitive load on subjects’ degree of relative risk aversion .
    [Show full text]
  • Utility with Decreasing Risk Aversion
    144 UTILITY WITH DECREASING RISK AVERSION GARY G. VENTER Abstract Utility theory is discussed as a basis for premium calculation. Desirable features of utility functions are enumerated, including decreasing absolute risk aversion. Examples are given of functions meeting this requirement. Calculating premiums for simplified risk situations is advanced as a step towards selecting a specific utility function. An example of a more typical portfolio pricing problem is included. “The large rattling dice exhilarate me as torrents borne on a precipice flowing in a desert. To the winning player they are tipped with honey, slaying hirri in return by taking away the gambler’s all. Giving serious attention to my advice, play not with dice: pursue agriculture: delight in wealth so acquired.” KAVASHA Rig Veda X.3:5 Avoidance of risk situations has been regarded as prudent throughout history, but individuals with a preference for risk are also known. For many decision makers, the value of different potential levels of wealth is apparently not strictly proportional to the wealth level itself. A mathematical device to treat this is the utility function, which assigns a value to each wealth level. Thus, a 50-50 chance at double or nothing on your wealth level may or may not be felt equivalent to maintaining your present level; however, a 50-50 chance at nothing or the value of wealth that would double your utility (if such a value existed) would be equivalent to maintaining the present level, assuming that the utility of zero wealth is zero. This is more or less by definition, as the utility function is set up to make such comparisons possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Loss Aversion in Decisions Under Risk and the Value of a Symmetric Simplification of Prospect Theory
    1 Loss Aversion in Decisions under Risk and the Value of a Symmetric Simplification of Prospect Theory By Eyal Ert and Ido Erev Max Wertheimer Minerva Center for Cognitive Studies, Technion, Israel Abstract Three studies are presented that examine alternative interpretations of the loss aversion assertion (Kahneman and Tversky (1979)). The first two studies reject a "strong" interpretation: In violations of this interpretation the choice rate of the risky option was higher given prospects with mixed payoffs (gain and losses) than given prospects with nonnegative payoffs. The third study rejects a "moderate" interpretation of loss aversion: It shows that the elimination of the loss aversion assumption from prospect theory increases the theory's predictive value. The results demonstrate the value of a simplified version of prospect theory that assumes a symmetric value function (with diminishing sensitivity relative to the reference point), a symmetric probability weighting function (that implies a certainty/possibility effect) and a stochastic response rule. Keywords: Stochastic models, Cumulative prospect theory, Predictive value. JEL Classification: C91, D01. 2 1. INTRODUCTION The loss aversion assertion, one of the assumptions that underlie prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky (1979)), implies that losses loom larger than gains. That is, the absolute subjective value of a specific loss is larger than the absolute subjective value of an equivalent gain. This assertion was shown to provide an elegantexplanation to a wide set of important behavioral phenomena. Famous examples are the endowment effect (Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler (1990)), the status quo bias (Samuelson and Zeckhauser (1988)), and the equity premium puzzle (Benartzi and Thaler (1995)).
    [Show full text]
  • The Future of Economics in a Lakatos–Bourdieu Framework
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive The Future of Economics in a Lakatos–Bourdieu Framework. Heise, Arne University of Hamburg 2014 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/80024/ MPRA Paper No. 80024, posted 05 Jul 2017 05:42 UTC The Future of Economics in a Lakatos-Bourdieu framework Prof. Arne Heise University of Hamburg Dep. of Socioeconomics VMP 9 D-20146 Hamburg [email protected] Abstract The global financial crisis has clearly been a matter of great consternation for the busi- ness-as-usual faction of mainstream economics. Will the World Financial Crisis turn out to be that ‘experimentum crucis’ which triggered a scientific revolution? In this paper, we seek to assess the likelihood of a paradigm shift towards heterodox approaches and a more pluralist setting in economics emerging from the academic establishment in the U.S. – that is, from the dominant center of knowledge production in the economic disci- pline. This will be done by building the analysis on a combined Lakatosian framework of ‘battle of research programmes’ and a Bourdieuian framework of ‘power struggle’ within the academic field and highlighting the likelihood of two main proponents of the mainstream elite to become the promulgator of change? Keywords: Paradigm, heterodox economics, scientific revolution JEL codes: A 11, E 11, E 12 1 1. The Keynesian Revolution and Pragmatic Pluralism – A Fruitful Competition Between Theories or a Crisis in Economics? John Maynard Keynes concludes ‘The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money’ (1936: 383-84) with the following, now-famous words: „At the present moment people are unusually expectant of a more funda- mental diagnosis; more particularly ready to receive it; eager to try it out, if it should be even possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Risk Aversion and Emotions
    bs_bs_banner Pacific Economic Review, 19: 3 (2014) pp. 296–312 doi: 10.1111/1468-0106.12067 RISK AVERSION AND EMOTIONS YEN NGUYEN Tilburg University CHARLES N. NOUSSAIR* Tilburg University Abstract. We consider the relationship between emotions and decision-making under risk. Specifi- cally, we examine the emotional correlates of risk-averse decisions. In our experiment, individuals’ facial expressions are monitored with face reading software, as they are presented with risky lotteries. We then correlate these facial expressions with subsequent decisions in risky choice tasks. We find that a more positive emotional state is positively correlated with greater risk taking. The strength of a number of emotions, including fear, happiness, anger and surprise, is positively correlated with risk aversion. JEL Classification Code: C9 1. INTRODUCTION The mechanisms that underpin choice under risk have been a primary focus of research in economics, psychology and neuroscience. The traditional approach in economics has been to postulate the existence of a utility function, possessing the expected utility property, that represents an individual’s preferences, and to note that concavity implies a preference for relatively safe lotteries, while convexity corresponds to a preference for relatively risky lotteries. Neuroscien- tists have documented the physiological correlates of risky decision-making. Psychologists and behavioural economists stress the role of emotions such as happiness or fear in guiding individuals’ choices in risky situations (see e.g. Forgas, 1995; Loewenstein and Lerner, 2003; Coget et al., 2011). The focus of the work reported here is to better understand the connection between emotions, which are ultimately psychological terms describing profiles of physiological responses, and the level of risk aversion exhibited in financial decision-making tasks.
    [Show full text]
  • John Von Neumann Oskar Morgenstern
    Neuroeconomics: From The Failures of Expected Utility to the Neurobiology of Choice Paul Glimcher PhD Julius Silver Professor of Neural Science, Economics and Psychology Director, Institute of the Study of Decision Making New York University Blaise Pascal Genius: Expected Value Theory Expected Probability x Value = Value #1 0.5 100 50 #2 1.0 45 45 Pascal's Wager If God Exists If God Doesn't Exist (Prob 3 Value) + (Prob 3 Value) = Exp. Value Believe in God >0 3 `$++ 0 3 0 = ` Do not Believe >0 3 2` ++ $0 3 0 = 2` in God Problem: The Beggar’s Dilemma Daniel Bernoulli Genius: Expected Utility Theory Beggar’s Dilemma 4.3 3.8 Beggar’s Utility (utils) Beggar’s 0 7000 20,000 Rich Man’s Choice Beggar’s Wealth (florins) 6.0056 6.0 5.9969 Rich Man’s Utility (utils) Rich Man’s Problem: 0 losses wins Value ($) Bentham, Pareto, Samuelson 993,000 1,013,000 1,000,000 Jeremy Bentham Vilfredo Pareto Paul Samuelson The Calculus of Utility The Intrinsic Arbitrariness of Utility Ordinal Objective Utility John von Neumann Oskar Morgenstern Genius: Modern Expected Utility Theory 0 < a <1 a $ s = Expected 35til u Utility weight s.w. = prob Subjective 0 Utility (utils) 0 Probability Dollars ($) Critcal Advantages: • Precise • Compact • Normative (people Problem: make sense) Maurice Allais Maurice Allais People Do Not Obey EU all the time 0 < a <1 a $ s = Expected 35til u Utility weight s.w. = prob Subjective 0 Utility (utils) 0 XProbability Dollars ($) Critcal Questons: • How to Predict People? • Are People Dumb? • Why? Amos Tversky Danny Kahneman Prospect Theory Critcal Advantages: • Predictive Critcal Disadvantages: • Bulky • No Why Behavioral Traditional Social-Natural Science Boundary Economics vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Monetary Policy, Redistribution, and Risk Premia∗
    Monetary Policy, Redistribution, and Risk Premia∗ Rohan Kekrey Moritz Lenelz September 2019 Abstract We study the transmission of monetary policy through risk premia in a heteroge- neous agent New Keynesian environment. Heterogeneity in agents' marginal propensity to take risk (MPR) summarizes differences in risk aversion, constraints, rules of thumb, background risk, and beliefs relevant for portfolio choice on the margin. An unexpected reduction in the nominal interest rate redistributes to agents with high MPRs, lower- ing risk premia and amplifying the stimulus to the real economy through investment. Quantitatively, this mechanism rationalizes the empirical finding that the stock market response to monetary policy shocks is driven by news about future excess returns. JEL codes: E44, E63, G12 ∗We thank Adrien Auclert, Markus Brunnermeier, Emmanuel Farhi, Zhiguo He, Anil Kashyap, Gita Gopinath, Francois Gourio, Veronica Guerrieri, Erik Hurst, Nobu Kiyotaki, Stefan Nagel, Brent Neiman, Monika Piazzesi, Martin Schneider, Alp Simsek, Ludwig Straub, Gianluca Violante, Ivan Werning, Tom Winberry, and Moto Yogo for discussions. yUniversity of Chicago Booth School of Business. Email: [email protected]. zPrinceton University. Email: [email protected]. 1 Introduction In the data, expansionary monetary policy lowers risk premia. This finding has been es- tablished for the equity premium in stock markets, the term premium on longer maturity nominal bonds, and the external finance premium on risky corporate debt.1 The basic New Keynesian framework as described by Woodford (2003) and Gali (2008) does not capture this aspect of monetary policy transmission. As noted by Kaplan and Violante (2018), this is equally true for an emerging body of heterogeneous agent New Keynesian models whose focus on heterogeneous marginal propensities to consume has substantially enriched the im- plications for aggregate consumption but less so for asset prices and therefore investment.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Neuroeconomic Analysis, by Paul W. Glimcher Clément Levallois
    Book Review: Foundations of Neuroeconomic Analysis, by Paul W. Glimcher Clément Levallois To cite this version: Clément Levallois. Book Review: Foundations of Neuroeconomic Analysis, by Paul W. Glimcher. Journal of Economic Methodology, Taylor & Francis (Routledge), 2012. hal-01892831 HAL Id: hal-01892831 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01892831 Submitted on 10 Oct 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Foundations of Neuroeconomic Analysis, by Paul W. Glimcher, New York: Oxford University Press, 2010, 467 + xix pp., $69.95 (hardback), ISBN 978-0-19-974425-1. Forthcoming in the Journal of Economic Methodology “Subjective values are real numbers ranging from 0 to 1,000. They take action potentials [bioelectrical pulses in neurons] as their natural units.” (p. 398): this exemplifies how far Paul Glimcher, a professor at NYU, wants you to follow him in his new book, Foundations of Neuroeconomic Analysis. Can he be possibly serious? Searching for the physiological substrate of subjective value is like re-opening a very cold case – almost a taboo, for several reasons. During most of the twentieth century, it was an undisputable premise that the investigation of cultural and social behaviour was the exclusive province of the social sciences and the humanities.
    [Show full text]