Advancing Critical Criminology Through Anthropology” Western Criminology Review 12(2):55-77

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Advancing Critical Criminology Through Anthropology” Western Criminology Review 12(2):55-77 Brisman/ Western Criminology Review 12(2), 55-77 (2011) Online citation: Brisman, Avi. 2011. “Advancing Critical Criminology through Anthropology” Western Criminology Review 12(2):55-77. (http://wcr.sonoma.edu/v12n2/Brisman.pdf). Advancing Critical Criminology through Anthropology Avi Brisman Emory University Abstract: Since its genesis, critical criminology has been committed to a critique of domination and to developing and exploring broader conceptions of “crime” to include “harms” that are not necessarily proscribed by law. Without diminishing the contributions of early or current critical criminologists, this article suggests that critical criminology can further its goals by looking to anthropology. Such a recommendation is not without risk. Early “criminal anthropology” regarded criminality as inherited and contended that individuals could be “born criminal” (e.g., Fletcher 1891). Subsequent anthropological investigations of crime were and have continued to be sporadic, and the discipline’s approach to crime has not been particularly unified. (Anthropology has often considered crime within broader explorations of law, for example, or through related, albeit different, examinations of sorcery and witchcraft.) Despite these limitations or shortcomings, this article presents three ways in which anthropology can speak to, and engage with, critical criminology’s “insistence that criminological inquiry move beyond the boundaries imposed by legalistic definitions of crime” and its critique of domination (Michalowksi 1996:11): 1) anthropology can help reveal processes of domination that are pervasive; 2) anthropology can remind us that what constitutes “crime” is culturally specific and temporal; and 3) anthropology can help provide paradigms for better living—allowing critical criminologists to be not just critical, not just prescriptive, but aspirational. A wide range of ethnographic accounts is considered. Keywords: anthropology; culture; domination; harm; power; resistance INTRODUCTION anthropological attention (cf. Parnell and Kane 2003; Schneider and Schneider 2008). As a subject, “crime” has not generated significant This phenomenon may be due, in part, to sociology’s interest in the field of cultural anthropology.1 While one near hegemony over all matters crime-related (before criminology became its own discipline or sub-discipline, could point to an anthology here or a review essay there, 3 one would be hard-pressed to support the contention that depending on one’s perspective). But cultural anthro- anthropology has approached crime in a coherent, unified, pology’s lack of attention to crime may also be attributed, or sustained way—or that it has even generated substantial, at least in part, to the regrettable subfield of criminal ongoing debates about crime.2 Most often, crime appears anthropology (also known as anthropological crim- in the context of some other inquiry, such as disorder inology), which Fletcher (1891:204), in his famous address (Comaroff and Comaroff 2004, 2006), violence (e.g., to the Anthropological Society of Washington, defined as Betzig et al. 1988; Knauft et al. 1991), witchcraft and “the study of the being who, in consequence of physical sorcery (Favret-Saada 1980; Geschiere 1997), primitive conformation, hereditary taint, or surroundings of vice, law (Driberg 1928), the nature of the relationship between poverty, and ill example, yields to temptation and begins a law and conflict (Collier 1975), or labor, employment, career of crime.” Although such efforts to “biologize law- social stratification, and the effects of deindustrialization breaking” (Rafter 2007:808) were later discredited and (e.g., Bourgois 1996; Phillips 1999; Sullivan 1989), rather abandoned because of concerns for their racist and than on its own and as the primary subject of eugenicist policy implications (Cullen and Agnew 55 Advancing Critical Criminology 2006:22; see also Brennan et al. 1995:65; Raine 2002:43), anthropology extends beyond society and social structures the experience may have left anthropology reluctant to — because anthropology considers elements of culture, venture into the world of crime.4 such as beliefs, ideas, symbols, and other internal Such unwillingness is unfortunate for a number of dimensions of group living (Donovan 2008:xviii) — very basic reasons: 1) anthropology shares sociology’s and anthropology can provide further avenues for criminology’s forefathers (e.g., Durkheim, Marx, Weber) understanding how “crime” is, has been, or might be and canonical figures (e.g., Foucault) — individuals who defined, prevented, and controlled, as well as its meaning contemplated issues of conflict and cooperation, power for offenders, victims, cultural groups, and society, more and punishment, which lie at the heart of or are integral to generally. As such, anthropology should be more heavily understandings of crime;5 2) while all cultures possess invested in issues of, and matters pertaining to, crime and proscribed behaviors, “crime” is still culturally-specific criminology, or can, at the very least, and as this article and peoples differ (over time) over what behavior is to be suggests, contribute to criminologist’s study of crime. condemned and condoned (see, e.g., Betzig et al. 1988; Despite anthropology’s inattention to crime as a Brisman 2006; Cullen and Agnew 2006:266-67; Daly and singular subject matter — or, at least, anthropology’s Wilson 1997:53; Ellis and Walsh 1997:230; Fletcher sporadic interest in crime — there is much that 1891:204; Herrnstein 1995:40), rendering crime ideal for criminology as a whole could gain from a consideration of longitudinal and comparative anthropological study; and 3) anthropological approaches, insights, and perspectives on relatively few ethnographies of crime exist — “thick” crime. For example, Collier (1975:125) provides anthro- accounts (in the Geertzian sense) of the experience of pological support for both labeling theory and Quinney’s committing crimes or participating in a subculture of (1969, 1974) Marxist criminology. There may still be crime, of being a victim, of residing in a community that fruitful linkages between criminology and biological and fears crime, or of migrating to a particular community evolutionary anthropology (see, e.g., Brisman 2010c). To because of its low crime rate. offer a third example: anthropologists, because of the time This last point merits some clarification. I do not spent in the field, and the scope of their inquiries, can mean to suggest that researchers have not employed consider the distinctions and relationships between ethnographic field methods in their study of crime. Many “norms” and “institutions,” “legal formalities” and “legal fine ethnographies of crime have improved and shaped our realities,” and “rules” and “behaviors” (Donovan 2008:14, understanding of the convergence of cultural and criminal 18, 23-24) — all of which could have bearing on processes in various societies (e.g., Adler 1985; Becker criminological studies and explorations. In this article, I 1963; Ferrell 1993; Ferrell and Hamm 1998; Humphreys consider ways that anthropology can help or advance 1975). But only a small percentage have been written by critical criminology — or reasons why critical anthropologists or with an anthropological perspective criminologists might look to some of the work of (e.g., Malinowski 1959; Merry 1981). While ethnography anthropologists. More specifically, I identify three ways in does not and should not reside solely under the dominion which anthropology can speak to, and engage with, critical of anthropology (see Kratz 2007), given anthropology’s criminology’s “insistence that criminological inquiry move strength with this methodology and the fact that the study beyond the boundaries imposed by legalistic definitions of of crime has been increasingly dominated by “shallow crime” and its critique of domination — for “un- survey research” and “abstract statistical analysis” (Ferrell apologetically” embracing “a commitment to confronting 1999:402),6 there is a tremendous need for more racism, sexism, working class oppression and US neo- anthropologically-oriented studies of crime (see generally colonialism” (Michalowksi 1996:11, 12): Betzig et al. 1988; Burawoy et al. 1991; Hagedorn 1990; Polsky 1969; Van Maanen 1995; and Sampson and Groves 1. Anthropology can help reveal processes of 1989). domination that are pervasive. Furthermore, while sociology is often focused on 2. Anthropology can remind us that what constitutes social structures (and while criminology tends to focus “crime” is culturally specific and temporal (a either on how individual characteristics influence actors’ point alluded to above). propensity for aggression, violence, and crime based on 3. Anthropology can help provide paradigms for biological or social psychological antecedents, or on better living—allowing critical criminologists to individuals in relation to their larger social environments, be not just critical, not just prescriptive, but such as schools, neighborhoods, and nation states aspirational. (Griffiths, Yule, and Gartner 2011), anthropology appreciates these structures, characteristics, and These categories or types of intersections between environments, but realizes that much of what makes anthropology and critical criminology are but the tip of the humans “human” lies in cultural ideation (Donovan iceberg. The discussion that follows offers representative 2008:xiv). In other words, because anthropology casts a examples
Recommended publications
  • Racism and Bad Faith
    AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF Gregory Alan Jones for the degree ofMaster ofArts in Interdisciplinary Studies in Philosophy, Philosophy and History presented on May 5, 2000. Title: Racism and Bad Faith. Redacted for privacy Abstract approved: Leilani A. Roberts Human beings are condemned to freedom, according to Jean-Paul Sartre's Being and Nothingness. Every individual creates his or her own identity according to choice. Because we choose ourselves, each individual is also completely responsible for his or her actions. This responsibility causes anguish that leads human beings to avoid their freedom in bad faith. Bad faith is an attempt to deceive ourselves that we are less free than we really are. The primary condition of the racist is bad faith. In both awarelblatant and aware/covert racism, the racist in bad faith convinces himself that white people are, according to nature, superior to black people. The racist believes that stereotypes ofblack inferiority are facts. This is the justification for the oppression ofblack people. In a racist society, the bad faith belief ofwhite superiority is institutionalized as a societal norm. Sartre is wrong to believe that all human beings possess absolute freedom to choose. The racist who denies that black people face limited freedom is blaming the victim, and victim blaming is the worst form ofracist bad faith. Taking responsibility for our actions and leading an authentic life is an alternative to the bad faith ofracism. Racism and Bad Faith by Gregory Alan Jones A THESIS submitted to Oregon State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Interdisciplinary Studies Presented May 5, 2000 Commencement June 2000 Redacted for privacy Redacted for privacy Redacted for privacy Redacted for privacy Redacted for privacy Redacted for privacy Acknowledgment This thesis has been a long time in coming and could not have been completed without the help ofmany wonderful people.
    [Show full text]
  • Seriously Playful and Playfully Serious: the Helpfulness of Humorous Parody Michael Richard Lucas Clemson University
    Clemson University TigerPrints All Dissertations Dissertations 5-2015 Seriously Playful and Playfully Serious: The Helpfulness of Humorous Parody Michael Richard Lucas Clemson University Follow this and additional works at: https://tigerprints.clemson.edu/all_dissertations Recommended Citation Lucas, Michael Richard, "Seriously Playful and Playfully Serious: The eH lpfulness of Humorous Parody" (2015). All Dissertations. 1486. https://tigerprints.clemson.edu/all_dissertations/1486 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Dissertations at TigerPrints. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TigerPrints. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SERIOUSLY PLAYFUL AND PLAYFULLY SERIOUS: THE HELPFULNESS OF HUMOROUS PARODY A Dissertation Presented to the Graduate School of Clemson University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy Rhetorics, Communication, and Information Design by Michael Richard Lucas May 2014 Accepted by: Victor J. Vitanza, Committee Chair Stephaine Barczewski Cynthia Haynes Beth Lauritis i ABSTRACT In the following work I create and define the parameters for a specific form of humorous parody. I highlight specific problematic narrative figures that circulate the public sphere and reinforce our serious narrative expectations. However, I demonstrate how critical public pedagogies are able to disrupt these problematic narrative expectations. Humorous parodic narratives are especially equipped to help us in such situations when they work as a critical public/classroom pedagogy, a form of critical rhetoric, and a form of mass narrative therapy. These findings are supported by a rhetorical analysis of these parodic narratives, as I expand upon their ability to provide a practical model for how to create/analyze narratives both inside/outside of the classroom.
    [Show full text]
  • The Note-Books of Samuel Butler
    The Note−Books of Samuel Butler Samuel Butler The Note−Books of Samuel Butler Table of Contents The Note−Books of Samuel Butler..........................................................................................................................1 Samuel Butler.................................................................................................................................................2 THE NOTE−BOOKS OF SAMUEL BUTLER...................................................................................................16 PREFACE....................................................................................................................................................17 BIOGRAPHICAL STATEMENT...............................................................................................................20 I—LORD, WHAT IS MAN?.......................................................................................................................24 Man........................................................................................................................................................25 Life........................................................................................................................................................26 The World..............................................................................................................................................27 The Individual and the World................................................................................................................28
    [Show full text]
  • The Suspension of Seriousness
    CHAPTER ONE Matters of Life and Death And López Wilson, astigmatic revolutionist come to spy upon his enemy’s terrain, to piss on that frivolous earth and be eyewit- ness to the dying of capitalism while at the same time enjoying its death-orgies. —Carlos Fuentes, La región más transparente (1958) Introduction wentieth-century Mexican philosophy properly considered boasts Tof a number of great thinkers worthy of inclusion in any and all philosophical narratives. The better known of these, Leopoldo Zea, José Vasconcelos, Antonio Caso, Samuel Ramos, and, to a great extent, Octavio Paz, have received their fair share of attention in the United States over the last fifty years, partly due to a concerted effort by a few philosophy professors in the US academy who find it necessary to dis- combobulate the Eurocentric philosophical canon with outsiders. For reasons which I hope to make clear in what follows, Jorge Portilla is not one of these outsiders to which attention has been paid—even in his homeland, where he is more likely to be recognized, not as one of Mex- ico’s most penetrating and attuned minds, but rather by his replicant, López Wilson, a caricature of intelligence and hedonism immortalized by Carlos Fuentes in his first novel. This oversight is unfortunate, since Portilla is by far more outside than the rest; in fact, the rest find approval precisely because they do not stray too far afield, keeping to themes and methodologies in tune with the Western cannon. One major reason for 1 2 The Suspension of Seriousness the lack of attention paid to Portilla has to do with his output, restricted as it is to a handful of essays and the posthumously published text of his major work, Fenomenología del relajo.
    [Show full text]
  • Scaling Seriousness: an Evaluation of Magnitude and Category Scaling Techniques George S
    Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology Volume 66 | Issue 2 Article 8 1975 Scaling Seriousness: An Evaluation of Magnitude and Category Scaling Techniques George S. Bridges Nancy S. Lisagor Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/jclc Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Criminology Commons, and the Criminology and Criminal Justice Commons Recommended Citation George S. Bridges, Nancy S. Lisagor, Scaling Seriousness: An Evaluation of Magnitude and Category Scaling Techniques, 66 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 215 (1975) This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology by an authorized editor of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. TMI JoURNAL OFCRImINAL LW & CRIMINOLOGY Vol. 66, No. 2 Copyright g 1975 by Northwestern University School of Law Printed in U.S.A. SCALING SERIOUSNESS: AN EVALUATION OF MAGNITUDE AND CATEGORY SCALING TECHNIQUES GEORGE S. BRIDGES* AND NANCY S. LISAGOR** Unidimensional attitude scaling in social re- by delinquency should be measured by scaling search encompasses a variety of measurement attitudes. It was argued: techniques. A relevant issue in the application The criteria for determining degrees of s- of any of these, however, is the extent to riousness must ultimately be determined by which different procedures yield similar re- someone's or some group's subjective interpre- sults. For example, one might expect that since tation. If weights were assigned by a few crim- magnitude and category scales represent two inologists engaged in the task of construct- distinct and different types, of scaling, each ing a mathematical model, we should regard would generate different sets of results.
    [Show full text]
  • What Makes a Crime Serious? Testing Warr's Model of Offence
    Ceza Hukuku ve Kriminoloji Dergisi-Journal of Penal Law and Criminology 2020; 8(1):1-31 ISSN: 2148-6646 / E-ISSN: 2602-3911 http://jplc.istanbul.edu.tr Research Article DOI: 10.26650/JPLC2020-0006 What Makes a Crime Serious? Testing Warr’s Model of Offence Seriousness Bir Suçu Ağır Yapan Nedir? Warr’un Suç Ağırlığı Modelinin Bir Testi Galma AKDENİZ1 1Dr. Öğr. Üyesi, İstanbul Bilgi Üniversitesi, Hukuk Fakültesi, İstanbul, Türkiye ORCID: G.A. 0000-0002-7255-8260 ABSTRACT Warr (1989) proposed that the perceptions of seriousness of different criminal offences are a function of perceptions of harmfulness caused by a crime (consequences of the crime), and perceived wrongfulness of a crime (normative evaluations regarding the crime). The study reported in this paper tested this model and examined the perceptions of seriousness of different offences in a sample of university students in Turkey. It was found that the degree of consensus regarding offence seriousness was much higher for offences judged as more serious. It was further found, when using wrongfulness and harmfulness assessments, that offences clustered into three larger groups: offences that present threat/risk of physical harm/death, property offences, and “minor” offences. Further, Warr’s model was tested on both the offence and the individual level of analysis. The findings suggest that the model indeed holds, however relative strength of harmfulness and wrongfulness, as predictors of crime seriousness, are different in Turkey, compared to findings from the USA and Westernest European countries. On an individual level, it was found that harmfulness was a stronger predictor than wrongfulness in a much larger number of offences, and that on the level of the offence, harmfulness was as strong a predictor of seriousness as wrongfulness.
    [Show full text]
  • The Phenomenological Ontologies of Kierkegaard and Sartre: an Existential Theory of Addiction
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1994 Love and Addiction: The Phenomenological Ontologies of Kierkegaard and Sartre: An Existential Theory of Addiction Ross Channing Reed Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Reed, Ross Channing, "Love and Addiction: The Phenomenological Ontologies of Kierkegaard and Sartre: An Existential Theory of Addiction" (1994). Dissertations. 3461. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/3461 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1994 Ross Channing Reed LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO "LOVE" AND ADDICTION: THE PHENOMENOLOGICAL ONTOLOGIES OF KIERKEGAARD AND SARTRE AN EXISTENTIAL THEORY OF ADDICTION A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY ROSS CHANNING REED CHICAGO, ILLINOIS MAY 1994 Copyright by Ross Channing Reed, 1994 All rights reserved. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to thank the following people and institutions for their support, encouragement, and prayer during the many years that led up to the production of this dissertation, as well as its actual writing: Texas A&M University Library, Millersville University Library, Franklin and Marshall College Library, Dr. John Ellsworth Winter, John Albert Cavin III, Christopher John Broniak, Richard J. Westley, John D.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ancient Roots of Humor Theory
    Merrimack College Merrimack ScholarWorks Communication and Media Faculty Publications Communication and Media 2012 The Ancient Roots of Humor Theory Lisa Glebatis Perks Merrimack College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.merrimack.edu/com_facpub Part of the Speech and Rhetorical Studies Commons Repository Citation Perks, L. (2012). The Ancient Roots of Humor Theory. Humor, 25(2), 119-132. Available at: https://scholarworks.merrimack.edu/com_facpub/8 This Article - Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Communication and Media at Merrimack ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Communication and Media Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Merrimack ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The ancient roots of humor theory LISA GLEBATIS PERKS Abstract Many modern humor scholars have oversimplified their summaries of Plato, Aristotle, Cicero and Quintilian's views on humor, focusing on the philoso- phers' cautionary warnings about the rhetorical efficacy and ethics of humor Although the philosophers did write much on the offensive nature of jests, which can be considered illustrative of superiority theory, I describe elements of the incongruity and relief theories of humor motivation in their work. There is evidence to suggest that all four philosophers found humor to be a fitting and effective response to certain exigencies. It is more accurate to summarize their views thus: Humor has the potential to be a powerful tool of persuasion, but like any potent weapon (discursive or non-discursive) it should be used with caution. Keywords: Aristotle; Cicero; motivation theories; Plato; Quintilian. 1.
    [Show full text]
  • HUMOUR IS a LAUGHING MATTER: the Existential Humour of Saki, Life of Brian and the Hitchhiker’S Guide to the Galaxy
    HUMOUR IS A LAUGHING MATTER: The Existential Humour of Saki, Life of Brian and The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy Dissertação apresentada à Universidade Católica Portuguesa para obtenção do grau de mestre em Estudos de Cultura Por Hugo Simões Faculdade de Ciências Sociais e Humanas Outubro 2017 HUMOUR IS A LAUGHING MATTER The Existential Humour of Saki, Life of Brian and The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy Dissertação apresentada à Universidade Católica Portuguesa para obtenção do grau de mestre em Estudos de Cultura Por Hugo Simões Faculdade de Ciências Sociais e Humanas Sob orientação da Professora Doutora Alexandra Lopes Outubro 2017 Abstract Humour is a complex, multifaceted phenomenon, the nature of which has eluded authors from Classical Antiquity to contemporary modernity. This dissertation explores some of the most important writings on humour to date, in an attempt to provide a well-rounded, critical approach to its most relevant characteristics, such as its relation to play, incongruity, relief, and superiority. These characteristics, and in particular the fact that humour seems to be deeply embedded in the tragic existential aspects of the human condition, then form the theoretical backbone of the subsequent analysis of three short stories by Saki, Monty Python’s Life of Brian and The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy by Douglas Adams, mostly through a practice of close reading. Each of these works, it is argued, reveal a particular outlook on the human condition through the exploration of its inherent incongruities – both on a social and individual level. They are also shown to, in the face of tragedy, encourage the adoption of a detached perspective that derives enjoyment from these incongruities, in what ultimately seems to be a life-affirming practice that seeks solace in the bleakest aspects of our existence.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Theory on the Experience and Ethics of Humor
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Dissertations (1934 -) Projects Humor, Power and Culture: A New Theory on the Experience and Ethics of Humor Jennifer Marra Marquette University Follow this and additional works at: https://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Marra, Jennifer, "Humor, Power and Culture: A New Theory on the Experience and Ethics of Humor" (2019). Dissertations (1934 -). 1015. https://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/1015 HUMOR, POWER, AND CULTURE: A NEW THEORY ON THE EXPERIENCE AND ETHICS OF HUMOR by Jennifer Marra A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin May 2019 ABSTRACT HUMOR, POWER, AND CULTURE: A NEW THEORY ON THE EXPERIENCE AND ETHICS OF CULTURE Jennifer Marra Marquette University, 2019 The aim of this dissertation is to offer a new theory of humor that takes seriously both the universality and power of humor in culture. In the first chapter, I summarize historical and contemporary theories, and show how each either 1) fails to give any definition of humor, 2) fails as a theory of humor, and/or 3) underappreciates, dismisses, or does not consider the power of humor in experience. The second chapter explains the failures of prior theories by understanding the problem in terms of Ernst Cassirer’s philosophy of symbolic forms. These forms of culture are perspectives through which we express and understand our world, and each presents its own unique perspectives through which we can understand ourselves and the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Seriousness of Offenses: an Evaluation by Offenders and Nonoffenders, the Robert M
    Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology Volume 66 | Issue 2 Article 5 1975 Seriousness of Offenses: An Evaluation by Offenders and Nonoffenders, The Robert M. Figlio Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/jclc Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Criminology Commons, and the Criminology and Criminal Justice Commons Recommended Citation Robert M. Figlio, Seriousness of Offenses: An Evaluation by Offenders and Nonoffenders, The, 66 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 189 (1975) This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology by an authorized editor of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. THE TounNAL OFCRIMINAL LAW & CRImINoLoGy Vol. 66, No. 2 Copyright C 1975 by Northwestern University School of Law Printed in U.S.A. THE SERIOUSNESS OF OFFENSES: AN EVALUATION BY OFFENDERS AND NONOFFENDERS ROBERT M. FIGLIO * The research reported here concerns the de- Building on the work of S. S. Stevens in termination of the subjective severities of var- the field of psychophysical scaling, Sellin and ious kinds of criminal offenses as judged by Wolfgang developed a subjective measuring convicted offenders and by nonoffenders. The stick for assessing the severity of various de- study aims -to determine if convicted offenders linquent acts based on the judgments of juve- rate the seriousness of offenses in the same nile court judges, police officers and college manner as do middle-class nonoffenders with students.3 They were able to scale the gamut of regard to (1) offense ranking, (2) absolute delinquent behavior involving components of and relative weight given to each offense and, injury, theft and/or damage down to the rather (3) degree of consensus about the seriousness insignificant forms of deviant activity resulting of each offense.
    [Show full text]
  • What Makes a Crime Serious? Testing Warr's Model of Offence Seriousness
    Ceza Hukuku ve Kriminoloji Dergisi-Journal of Penal Law and Criminology 2020; 8(1):1-31 ISSN: 2148-6646 / E-ISSN: 2602-3911 http://jplc.istanbul.edu.tr Araştırma Makalesi / Research Article DOI: 10.26650/JPLC2020-0006 What Makes a Crime Serious? Testing Warr’s Model of Offence Seriousness Bir Suçu Ağır Yapan Nedir? Warr’un Suç Ağırlığı Modelinin bir Testi Galma AKDENİZ1 1Dr. Öğr. Üyesi, İstanbul Bilgi Üniversitesi, Hukuk Fakültesi, İstanbul, Türkiye ORCID: G.A. 0000-0002-7255-8260 ABSTRACT Warr (1989) proposed that the perceptions of seriousness of different criminal offences are a function of perceptions of harmfulness caused by a crime (consequences of the crime), and perceived wrongfulness of a crime (normative evaluations regarding the crime). The study reported in this paper tested this model and examined the perceptions of seriousness of different offences in a sample of university students in Turkey. It was found that the degree of consensus regarding offence seriousness was much higher for offences judged as more serious. It was further found, when using wrongfulness and harmfulness assessments, that offences clustered into three larger groups: offences that present threat/risk of physical harm/death, property offences, and “minor” offences. Further, Warr’s model was tested on both the offence and the individual level of analysis. The findings suggest that the model indeed holds, however relative strength of harmfulness and wrongfulness, as predictors of crime seriousness, are different in Turkey, compared to findings from the USA and Westernest European countries. On an individual level, it was found that harmfulness was a stronger predictor than wrongfulness in a much larger number of offences, and that on the level of the offence, harmfulness was as strong a predictor of seriousness as wrongfulness.
    [Show full text]