The Normativity of Moral Contractualism: a Hegelian Solution

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Normativity of Moral Contractualism: a Hegelian Solution The Normativity of Moral Contractualism: A Hegelian Solution A thesis submitted to the University of Manchester for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) in the faculty of Humanities 2019 Fred H Horton Social of Social Sciences Contents Section Page Abstract 5 Declaration 6 Copyright Statement 7 Dedication 9 Acknowledgements 10 Introduction 11 Chapter 1: An Instrumentalist’s Answer to the Question of Normativity 19 1.1 Introduction 19 1.2 Rational Choice Theory 21 1.3 A Disposition to Comply 31 1.4 What Sort of Motivation? 37 1.5 Conclusion 43 Chapter 2: Scanlonian Contractualism 45 2.1 Introduction 45 2.2 Scanlon’s Contractualism: An Overview 46 2.3 Scanlon’s Constructivism 53 2.4 Relativism and Convergence 60 2.5 Conclusion 70 Chapter 3: The Normativity of Deliberative Contractualism 71 3 3.1 Introduction 71 3.2 Deliberative Contractualism 72 3.3 The Question of Normativity 76 3.4 Some Concerns for Southwood’s Account 79 3.5 Conclusion 89 Chapter 4: Relational Formalism and German Idealism 91 4.1 Recap: The Shortcomings of Actually 91 Existing Contractualism 4.2 A Second Person Solution? 95 4.3 Thompson’s Alternative 101 4.4 Fichtean Themes in Contractualist Ethics 107 4.5 Conclusion 116 Chapter 5: A Hegelian Solution? 118 5.1 Introduction 118 5.2 Hegel’s Dialectic of Recognition 122 5.3 The Hegelian Thought Applied to Contractualism 134 5.4 Objections 140 5.5 Conclusion 154 Conclusion 156 Bibliography 158 Word Count: 60,569 4 Abstract The University of Manchester Fred H Horton The Normativity of Moral Contractualism: A Hegelian Solution June 2019 Moral contractualism is a branch of normative ethics that holds that our moral obligations to each other are determined by the principles that we would agree to in certain hypothetical, idealised circumstances. This thesis takes an in-depth look at this approach, in particular an aspect of it denoted the ‘question of normativity’. The question of normativity is concerned with how the conditions of the circumstances of the agreement come to constitute moral reasons for real world agents. It argues that existing contractualist approaches to the question of normativity fail to provide a satisfactory answer to the question of normativity, because the accounts of practical reason relied on to do so either fail to explain the binding of our moral requirements, or do so only at the expense of undermining contractualism’s ambitions to provide an account of morality’s foundations. It then attempts to provide a positive solution to the question of the form of normativity in the form of an account of agency inspired by the thought of G. W. F. Hegel. The claim is that an approach to agency inspired by what I call the ‘Hegelian Thought’ provides us with the tools for a plausible account of practical reason; one that makes sense of the interpersonal nature of this practical reason and is not hostage to a defeasible commitment to a substantive value. 5 Declaration No portion of the work referred to in the thesis has been submitted in support of an application for another degree or qualification of this or any other university or other institute of learning; 6 Copyright Statement i. The author of this thesis (including any appendices and/or schedules to this thesis) owns certain copyright or related rights in it (the “Copyright”) and s/he has given The University of Manchester certain rights to use such Copyright, including for administrative purposes. ii. Copies of this thesis, either in full or in extracts and whether in hard or electronic copy, may be made only in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (as amended) and regulations issued under it or, where appropriate, in accordance Presentation of Theses Policy with licensing agreements which the University has from time to time. This page must form part of any such copies made. iii. The ownership of certain Copyright, patents, designs, trademarks and other intellectual property (the “Intellectual Property”) and any reproductions of copyright works in the thesis, for example graphs and tables (“Reproductions”), which may be described in this thesis, may not be owned by the author and may be owned by third parties. Such Intellectual Property and Reproductions cannot and must not be made available for use without the prior 7 written permission of the owner(s) of the relevant Intellectual Property and/or Reproductions. iv. Further information on the conditions under which disclosure, publication and commercialisation of this thesis, the Copyright and any Intellectual Property and/or Reproductions described in it may take place is available in the University IP Policy (see http://documents.manchester.ac.uk/DocuInfo.aspx?DocID=2442 0), in any relevant Thesis restriction declarations deposited in the University Library, The University Library’s regulations (see http://www.library.manchester.ac.uk/about/regulations/) and in The University’s policy on Presentation of Theses 8 Dedication To my Dad 9 Acknowledgements This work was funded through the University of Manchester’s Philosophy Studentship. For valuable support and discussion, I would like to thank my main supervisor, John O’Neill. And various stages throughout this project John has been joined by Steve de Wijze, Richard Child, Thomas Smith and Stephen Ingram. All have provided very helpful comments and encouragement about my work. Special thanks should also go to Joel Smith and Alan Hamlin for reading on commenting on drafts of the early parts of this thesis. I have also benefitted immensely from the comments and questions of those who attended the MANCEPT seminar and the Manchester Philosophy Research seminar (twice). The Philosophy and Politics communities at Manchester have been a further source of support and ideas. Lastly I would like to thanks my family, especially my mother, father, grandmother, Anne, Klaudia, and Tim for their support and encouragement. 10 Introduction Moral contractualism is, roughly, the idea that what makes an action permissible or impermissible is whether or not a principle that licensed it would be accepted or rejected by hypothetical agents in idealized circumstances. Various versions of this moral theory have been advanced, and the differences between them are largely explained by the assumptions made about the details of these circumstances and the nature of the agents in question. While these assumptions will have an impact on the principles that are licensed, this is not the focus of this thesis. Rather, the focus here is on what I am calling ‘question of normativity’: how do the specific conditions of the hypothetical agreement constitute moral reasons for real-world agents? Each account of contractualism relies on a particular conception of practical reason to answer this question. That is, they each have an account of the kinds of considerations that provide an agent with a reason to perform action ϕ. The conception of practical reason relied on must explain why the hypothetical agents would reach an agreement, the nature of that agreement, and how that agreement comes to provide (strong, binding) reasons for real-world agents. The contention of the first part of this thesis is that the conceptions of practical reason adopted by the different contractualist approaches are, in distinct ways, inadequate to the task of explaining the relationship between what constitutes a reason in the hypothetical circumstances and what constitutes a reason in the real-world. That is, they fail to answer the question of normativity. The second part of the thesis attempts to provide a positive solution to the question of the form of normativity in the form of an account of agency inspired by the thought of G. W. F. Hegel. The claim is that an approach to agency inspired by what I call the ‘Hegelian Thought’ provides us with the tools for a plausible account of practical reason; one that makes sense of the interpersonal nature of this practical reason and is not hostage to a defeasible commitment to a substantive value. Before outlining the plan of this thesis, I will say a bit about moral contractualism more generally and explain some terminology in a bit more detail. 11 * Contractualism has a long historical pedigree, and while the basic idea behind the thought experiment that characterises it is relatively stable, the details and purpose of it vary. It has been used as a means of grounding political authority,1 to determine the nature of the political institutions that we should strive for,2and as the basis for determining the obligations we have, as individuals, to each other.3 The basic idea that these various approaches share is that we ought to be governed by what we would agree to in certain hypothetical idealised circumstances. Rousseau wondered what we would will if we had the general interests of the wider community at heart. Rawls considered what kind of political arrangements we would want if we had no idea what our position or status would be in the community. These latter approaches have much to offer, but they are not the focus here. This thesis is concerned exclusively with moral contractualism; that is, the code that would be agreed to in order to regulate individual conduct. A successful contractualist account will explain what we ought to do in terms of what would be agreed in these hypothetical circumstances presumed. So the reason I should return the money I borrowed when I said I would is because if a group of agents were determining the code we ought to live by it is highly likely that a principle of repaying debts agreed to on time would be endorsed.4 But any moral contractualism that provides answers to such question must also explain why the requirements that are derived through this process are binding on the agents they apply to.
Recommended publications
  • Page 55 'SAVING the GREATEST NUMBER' THOM BROOKS Imagine
    “05brooks” i i 2004/3/16 page 55 i i Logique & Analyse 177–178 (2002), 55–59 `SAVING THE GREATEST NUMBER' THOM BROOKS Imagine there are three boats equidistant from one another. You are alone in the first boat. The other two boats are sinking fast: one boat has one person (A), the other has two persons (B&C). There is only enough time to allow saving either A or B&C before their boats sink, drowning whoever is onboard.1 `As far as common-sense morality is concerned, one's duty as rescuer, under the circumstances, is a straightforward matter: one ought to save the greatest number' (Kumar 2001: 165). In this example, one reason in favour of saving B&C and not A is the Kamm-Scanlon argument, a contractualist framework without any commit- ment to aggregating various outcome values nor a combination of individual claims for rescue.2 If the claims of A, B, and C are accorded equal and positive weight, Michael Otsuka contends that the Kamm-Scanlon argument `considers C's claim in combination with B's claim so that they together tip the balance in favor of saving B and C' and not A (2000: 290–91; cf Scan- lon 1998: 232–33). C's presence in B's boat makes the difference between saving A or B&C. For Otsuka, the assertion that `C has a claim to be saved by virtue of an appeal to the difference that B and C make when considered together or in combination rather than one by one' amounts to an `appeal to the claim of a group of individuals' (2000: 292).
    [Show full text]
  • Religion, Ethics, and Poetics in a Tamil Literary Tradition
    Tacit Tirukku#a#: Religion, Ethics, and Poetics in a Tamil Literary Tradition The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Smith, Jason William. 2020. Tacit Tirukku#a#: Religion, Ethics, and Poetics in a Tamil Literary Tradition. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard Divinity School. Citable link https://nrs.harvard.edu/URN-3:HUL.INSTREPOS:37364524 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use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
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond the Principles of Bioethics: Facing the Consequences of Fundamental Moral Disagreement
    DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1677-2954.2012v11n1p13 BEYOND THE PRINCIPLES OF BIOETHICS: FACING THE CONSEQUENCES OF FUNDAMENTAL MORAL DISAGREEMENT H. TRISTRAM ENGELHARDT (Rice Universtiy / USA) ABSTRACT Given intractable secular moral pluralism, the force and significance of the four principles (autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and justice) of Tom Beauchamp and James Childress must be critically re-considered. This essay examines the history of the articulation of these four principles of bioethics, showing why initially there was an illusion of a common morality that led many to hold that the principles could give guidance across cultures. But there is no one sense of the content or the theoretical justification of these principles. In addition, a wide range of secular moral and bioethical choices has been demoralized into lifestyle choices; the force of the secular moral point of view has also been deflated, thus compounding moral pluralism. It is the political generation of the principles that provides a common morality in the sense of an established morality. The principles are best understood as embedded not in a common morality, sensu stricto, but in that morality that is established at law and public policy in a particular polity. Although moral pluralism is substantive and intractable at the level of moral content, in a particular polity a particular morality and a particular bioethics can be established, regarding which health care ethics consultants can be experts. Public morality and bioethics are at their roots a political reality. Keywords: Bioethics. Pluralism. Moral disagreement. Ethical particularism. RESUMO Dado o pluralismo moral secular intratável, a força e o significado dos quatro princípios (autonomia, beneficência, não maleficência e justiça) de Tom Beauchamp e James Childress precisam ser reconsiderados criticamente.
    [Show full text]
  • Grotius and Kant on Original Community of Goods and Property
    grotiana 38 (2017) 106-128 GROTIAN A brill.com/grot Grotius and Kant on Original Community of Goods and Property Sylvie Loriaux Département de science politique, Université Laval, Quebec [email protected] Abstract This paper is interested in the critical potential of the idea of original common possession of the Earth. On the basis of a comparative analysis of Hugo Grotius and Immanuel Kant, it shows how different the meaning of this idea can be within a theory of property or territory. The first part is devoted to Grotius’s account of why and how the institution of property was progressively introduced. It highlights the importance this account attaches to the intention of the first distributors for a good understand- ing of property laws, and in particular, for an understanding of their non-application in situations of extreme necessity. The second part takes the opposite path and shows that although Kant rejects the very existence of a right of necessity, the idea that one might be liberated from a law is not completely absent from, and even plays a crucial role in, his account of property. Clarification of this role ultimately leads us back to the idea of original possession in common of the Earth. Keywords Hugo Grotius – Immanuel Kant – original community of goods – necessity – permissive law – property rights * The author would like to thank the journal’s anonymous referees and editor for their very helpful comments and suggestions on earlier drafts of this article. She would also like to thank the participants in the Workshop on Grotius’s Place in the History of Moral and Politi- cal Thought (Leuven, 2017) and in the Workshop on Private Property and Territorial Rights (Bayreuth, 2017) for illuminating discussions.
    [Show full text]
  • Charles Taylor and George Grant on the Problem of Instrumentalism: Expressivism and Justice As Alternative Ontologies
    CHARLES TAYLOR AND GEORGE GRANT ON THE PROBLEM OF INSTRUMENTALISM: EXPRESSIVISM AND JUSTICE AS ALTERNATIVE ONTOLOGIES Carlos Colorado Bachelor of Arts, Simon Fraser University, 2001 THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS Under Special Arrangements in the Faculty of Arts O Carlos Colorado 2004 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY August 2004 All rights reserved. This work may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without permission of the author. APPROVAL Name: Carlos Colorado Degree: Master of Arts Charles Taylor and George Grant on the Problem of Title of Thesis: Instrumentalism: Expressivism and Justice as Alternative Ontologies Examining Committee: Chair: Dr. Jonathan C. Driver Dean of Graduate Studies Dr. Ian Angus Senior Supervisor Professor Department of Humanities Dr. David Laycock Supervisor Professor Department of Political Science Dr. Samuel LaSelva External Examiner Professor Department of Political Science University of British Columbia Date Approved: &b! 208~ Partial Copyright Licence The author, whose copyright is declared on the title page of this work, has granted to Simon Fraser University the right to lend this thesis, project or extended essay to users of the Simon Fraser University Library, and to make partial or single copies only for such users or in response to a request from the library of any other university, or other educational institution, on its own behalf or for one of its users. The author has further agreed that permission for multiple copying of this work for scholarly purposes may be granted by either the author or the Dean of Graduate Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Abilityand Volitionalincapacity
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers DISCUSSION NOTE ABILITY AND VOLITIONAL INCAPACITY BY NICHOLAS SOUTHWOOD AND PABLO GILABERT JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE | SEPTEMBER 2016 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT © NICHOLAS SOUTHWOOD AND PABLO GILABERT 2016 JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY | DISCUSSION NOTE ABILITY AND VOLITIONAL INCAPACITY Nicholas Southwood and Pablo Gilabert Ability and Volitional Incapacity Nicholas Southwood and Pablo Gilabert HE SO-CALLED “CONDITIONAL ANALYSIS of ability” (henceforth “CA”) holds that: T (CA) An agent A is able to perform an act φ iff and because A would (or would be sufficiently likely to) φ if A were to have or form some relevant volitional attitude or response v with regard to φing (see Moore 1912; Estlund 2011).1 (CA) faces a familiar kind of counterexample. Here is a famous instance of the counterexample due to Keith Lehrer: Suppose that I am offered a bowl of candy and in the bowl are small round red sugar balls. I do not choose to take one of the red sugar balls because I have a pathological aversion to such candy. (Perhaps they remind me of drops of blood …) It is logically consistent to suppose that if I had chosen to take the red sugar ball, I would have taken one, but not so choosing, I am utterly unable to touch one (Lehrer 1968: 32). Here is another famous instance of the counterexample due to Susan Wolf: [Suppose] a person attacked on a dark street would have screamed if she had chosen … [but is] too paralyzed by fear to consider, much less choose, to scream (Wolf 1990: 99).
    [Show full text]
  • Contractualism
    Contractualism Jussi Suikkanen Final author copy; To be published in Michael Hemmingsen (ed.): Ethical Theory in Global Perspective (SUNY Press). Introduction There is a long historical tradition of trying to understand morality in terms of a contract. The core idea in this tradition is that what is right and wrong is in some way grounded in either what we have agreed to do or in what we could be expected to agree to in some hypothetical circumstances. This contractualist way of thinking goes back to at least Ancient Greece (Plato, The Republic, 358e–359b), but it really became the prominent way of thinking especially about our political obligations during the Early Modern period through the social contract theories of Thomas Hobbes (1996 [1651]), John Locke (2002 [1689]), and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1997 [1762]). Contractualism is not, however, merely a historical tradition, but rather it continues to be a popular approach. In political philosophy, many debates concerning justice still tend to take John Rawls’s (1971) contractualism as their starting point. Similarly, in moral philosophy, different ways of developing the basic contractualist insights are at the centre of several key theoretical debates (Gauthier 1986, Scanlon 1998, Southwood 2010, and Parfit 2011). That so many people have approached morality through the idea of a contract for over two millennia suggests that the contractualist framework must be getting something right. Yet, as we will see below, the devil will be in the details. 1 For the sake of simplicity, this chapter focuses on just one contemporary formulation of contractualism – the version outlined by T.M.
    [Show full text]
  • PABLO GILABERT Curriculum Vitae (March 2017) Department of Philosophy, Concordia University ❖ 1455 De Maisonneuve West ❖ Montreal, Quebec, Canada H3G 1M8 Tel
    PABLO GILABERT Curriculum Vitae (March 2017) Department of Philosophy, Concordia University ❖ 1455 de Maisonneuve West ❖ Montreal, Quebec, Canada H3G 1M8 Tel. (514) 848 2424 ext. 2520 ❖ Email: [email protected] ❖ Web: http://www.concordia.ca/faculty/pablo-gilabert.html __________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ ACADEMIC POSITIONS Concordia University. Philosophy Department. Assistant Professor (2003). Associate Professor (since 2008). University of Montreal. Centre de Recherche en Ethique. Visiting Research Fellow (2018). Princeton University. Center for Human Values. Laurance S. Rockefeller Visiting Faculty Fellow (2011-12). Australian National University. Philosophy Program. Visiting Fellow (2008). Research Associate (2014). Universidad Torcuato di Tella, Buenos Aires. Law School. Visiting Scholar (2009). Oxford University. University College. HLA Hart Visiting Fellow (2007). EDUCATION New School for Social Research. Philosophy Department (minor field in Political Science), New York (1998-2003). M.A. (2000). Ph.D. with Honors (2003). Johann Wolfgang Goethe-Universität (University of Frankfurt). Philosophy Department. Doctoral studies and research as a DAAD fellow (2001-2). University of Buenos Aires. Philosophy Department. Licenciatura with Honors (1992-1997). PUBLICATIONS Book From Global Poverty to Global Equality. A Philosophical Exploration (Oxford University Press, 2012). Articles - “Dignity at Work.” Philosophical Foundations of Labour Law, ed. H. Collins, G. Lester, V. Mantouvalou (Oxford: Oxford University Press): forthcoming. - “Justice and Feasibility: A Dynamic Approach.” Political Utopias: Contemporary Debates, ed. M. Weber and K. Vallier (Oxford: Oxford University Press): forthcoming. - “Facts, Norms, and Dignity.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy: forthcoming. - “The Human Right to Democracy and the Pursuit of Global Justice.” The Oxford Handbook of Global Justice, ed. T. Brooks (Oxford: Oxford University Press): forthcoming.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics: a Study of Dietrich BonhoeEr's Ethics in Relation to Virtue Ethics
    Durham E-Theses The virtue of Bonhoeer's ethics: a study of Dietrich Bonhoeer's Ethics in relation to virtue ethics MOBERLY, JENNIFER,LYNNE How to cite: MOBERLY, JENNIFER,LYNNE (2009) The virtue of Bonhoeer's ethics: a study of Dietrich Bonhoeer's Ethics in relation to virtue ethics, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/89/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 The Virtue of Bonhoeffer’s Ethics A Study of Dietrich Bonhoeffer’s Ethics in Relation to Virtue Ethics Jennifer Moberly Thesis submitted for PhD Durham University December 2009 Abstract Jennifer Moberly, „The Virtue of Bonhoeffer‟s Ethics: A Study of Dietrich Bonhoeffer‟s Ethics in Relation to Virtue Ethics‟ (thesis submitted for PhD, December 2009) This study first explores prima facie reasons for rejecting the possibility of seeing a close relationship between Bonhoeffer‟s Ethics and virtue ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 MATTHEW LINDAUER Curriculum Vitae Department of Philosophy
    MATTHEW LINDAUER Curriculum Vitae Department of Philosophy [email protected] Brooklyn College www.matthewlindauer.com 2900 Bedford Avenue +1 718-702-3637 Brooklyn, NY 11210 Academic Employment Brooklyn College, City University of New York, Department of Philosophy Assistant Professor 2018-Present Australian National University, School of Philosophy Research Fellow 2017-Present Research and Teaching Postdoctoral Fellow 2015-2017 Education Ph.D., 2008-2015, Philosophy, Yale University B.A., 2001-2005, magna cum laude, Honors in Philosophy, New York University Areas of Specialization: Political Philosophy, Ethics, Moral Psychology Areas of Competence: Epistemology, History of Modern Philosophy, Logic Publications Peer-Reviewed Articles “In Defense of a Category-Based System for Unification Admissions.” Journal of Moral Philosophy, forthcoming. “Immigration Policy and Identification Across Borders.” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, Vol. 12, No. 3, 2017, 280-303. (w/ C. Barry) “Moral Judgment and the Duties of Innocent Beneficiaries of Injustice.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology, Vol. 8, No. 3, 2017, 671-686. (w/ C. Barry and G. Øverland) “Doing, Allowing, and Enabling Harm: An Empirical Investigation." In Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Vol. 1, eds. T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe, and S. Nichols, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, 62-90. 1 Matthew Lindauer CV Invited Articles “Unification Admissions and Skilled Worker Migration.” In Fair Work: Ethics, Social Policy, and Globalization, ed. K.P. Schaff, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, forthcoming. “Kantian Themes in Ethics and International Relations.” In The Routledge Handbook of Ethics and International Relations, eds. B. Steele and E. Heinze, New York: Routledge Press, forthcoming. “The Focus on Health Capability and Role of States in Ruger’s Global Health Justice Framework.” The American Journal of Bioethics, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Forthcoming in Philosophy Compass the Feasibility Issue1
    This is the peer reviewed version of the following article:Southwood, N. The feasibility issue. Philosophy Compass. 2018; 13:e12509. https:// doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12509, which has been published in final form at https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12509. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. https://authorservices.wiley.com/author- resources/Journal-Authors/licensing-open-access/open-access/self-archiving.html (Publisher journal website as of 1/4/2019) Forthcoming in Philosophy Compass The feasibility issue1 Nicholas Southwood (ANU) We expend considerable time and energy wondering, reasoning, conjecturing, and disagreeing, about what is feasible and infeasible. A Google search for the word “feasible” yields almost 100 million hits. And, of course, this doesn’t account for our private conversations, or what happens inside our heads, or when we deploy the concept of feasibility by using different words: “possible” and “impossible;” “viable” and “non‐viable;” “achievable” and “unachievable;” “practicable” and “impracticable;” what we “can” and “can’t” do; and so on. The prevalence of feasibility is hardly surprising. It is commonly taken for granted that questions of feasibility are highly relevant to our thinking about normative questions.2 This is perhaps especially true of our normative thinking about politics. Thus, we typically assume that in thinking about whether states should introduce a basic income, or open their borders, or start a war, it matters what courses of action, policies, and institutional arrangements are feasible and infeasible. But what is it that matters exactly and how? These are difficult and important questions.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics Content
    Ethics Content I Introduction to Ethics Unit-1 Nature and Scope of Ethics Unit-2 Importance and Challenges of Ethics Unit-3 Ethics in the History of Indian Philosophy Unit-4 Ethics in the History of Western Philosophy II Ethical Foundations Unit-1 Human Values Unit-2 Human Virtues Unit-3 Human Rights Unit-4 Human Duties III Applied Ethics Unit-1 International Ethics Unit-2 Bioethics Unit-3 Environmental Ethics Unit-4 Media Ethics IV Current Ethical Debates Unit-1 Natural Moral Law Unit-2 Deontology and Moral Responsibility Unit-3 Discourse Ethics Unit-4 Social Institutions UNIT 1 NATURE AND SCOPE OF ETHICS Nature and Scope of Ethics Contents 1.0 Objectives 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Moral Intuitionism 1.3 Human Person in Search of Himself/Herself 1.4 Love and the Moral Precepts 1.5 The Dynamics of Morality 1.6 The Constant and the Variable in Morality 1.7 Let Us Sum Up 1.8 Key Words 1.9 Further Readings and References 1.0 OBJECTIVES This unit aims at introducing the students to the philosophical need for Ethics starting from a brief discussion of Moral law and how the human person in his or her process of growth intuits the ethical principles. Discussions pertaining to the dynamics of morality is undertaken to show how on the one hand new situations call for new responses from moral point of view and on the other hand certain fundamentals of ethics remain the same in so far as there is something of a common human nature adequately understood.
    [Show full text]