Membership Without Social Citizenship? Deservingness & Redistribution As Grounds for Equality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Membership Without Social Citizenship? Deservingness & Redistribution As Grounds for Equality Membership without Social Citizenship? Deservingness & Redistribution as Grounds for Equality Irene Bloemraad, Will Kymlicka, Michèle Lamont & Leanne S. Son Hing Abstract: Western societies have experienced a broadening of inclusive membership, whether we consider legal, interpersonal, or cultural membership. Concurrently, we have witnessed increased tensions around social citizenship, notably harsher judgments or boundaries over who “deserves” public assistance. Some have argued these phenomena are linked, with expanded, more diverse membership corroding solidarity and redistribution. We maintain that such a conclusion is premature and, especially, unsatisfactory: it fails to detail the processes–at multiple levels of analysis–behind tensions over membership and social citizenship. This essay draws on normative political theory, social psychology, cultural sociology, and political studies to build a layered explanatory framework that highlights the importance of individual feelings of group identity and threat for people’s beliefs and actions; the significance of broader cultural repertoires and notions of national solidarity as a source and product of framing contests; and the diverse ways elites, power, and institutions affect notions of membership and deservingness. irene bloemraad is Profes- This essay explores processes by which a broad- sor of Sociology at the University ening of legal, social, and cultural membership in of California, Berkeley. Western societies appears to be accompanied by a will kymlicka is the Canada reduction in the social rights of citizenship, in part Research Chair in Political Phi- due to harsher judgments concerning the deserv- losophy at Queen’s University. ingness of low-income populations. As more di- michÈle lamont is Professor verse groups are extended formal national mem- of Sociology at Harvard Univer- bership, fewer individuals appear deserving of so- sity. cial rights, such as welfare redistribution. Why is leanne s. son hing is Asso- this the case? Some explain this decline in solidar- ciate Professor in the Department ity as a simple, even mechanical response to grow- of Psychology at the University ing diversity. We offer alternative approaches to un- of Guelph. derstanding these tensions and consider pathways (Complete author biographies appear for promoting inclusive membership and broad so- at the end of the essay.) cial rights. We do so by drawing on the analytical © 2019 by the American Academy of Arts & Sciences Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license doi:10.1162/DAED_a_01751 73 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/daed_a_01751 by guest on 28 September 2021 Membership tools of four distinct fields that are rare- intergroup attitudes, school textbooks, without Social ly in dialogue, proposing that positive so- popular media, and public representa- Citizenship? cial change may emerge from 1) solidar- tions of the nation). By all three measures, ity, explored by normative political the- people previously thought to be “others” orists; 2) group identity and distributive –racial, sexual, and religious minorities justice, a focus for social psychologists; and immigrants–are more likely today to 3) boundary-drawing and destigmatiza- have access to legal citizenship, to marry tion, as analyzed by cultural sociologists; someone from the majority group, and to and 4) contestation and social move- be perceived as valuable and as belonging ments, studied by political sociologists to the nation than in the 1950s. and political scientists. Sociologist T. H. In contrast, we see increased tensions Marshall famously distinguished three around social citizenship over this pe- dimensions of citizenship–civic, politi- riod. Contestation plays out in differ- cal, and social–with corresponding types ent ways. In some societies, increasing- of formal rights pertaining to legal inclu- ly harsh judgments about who deserves sion, political participation, and econom- public help distinguish the “deserving” ic redistribution (social rights), respec- poor from others. According to this logic, tively.1 He argued that modern societies one must demonstrate cultural member- are characterized by a progressive exten- ship or moral blamelessness to access re- sion of these rights to a larger number of sources, rather than receive public assis- individuals. Marshall predicted that this tance as a formal right extended to any- extension would go hand in hand with one in the national community. Other greater economic integration of all citi- societies appear to embrace welfare chau- zens, and that the decades bookending vinism: the historical beneficiaries of re- World War II would see “the subordina- distribution continue to enjoy generous tion of market price to social justice” by assistance, but newer groups, such as im- “recognizing in principle the right of the migrants, are excluded. In still other soci- citizen to a minimum standard of civi- eties, the provision of social benefits has lized living.”2 become decentralized, which accompa- Contrary to Marshall’s expectations, nies a decline in a sense of mutual obliga- we provide some evidence that the broad- tion toward low-income groups. ening of legal, interpersonal, or even cul- What processes of social change lie be- tural membership has not gone uniform- hind these tensions, and what factors may ly hand in hand with a broadening of the mitigate them? One prominent analy- distribution of welfare resources, in part sis links expanded membership but re- due to a rigidification of moral boundar- stricted social citizenship to demograph- ies based on perceptions of deservingness. ic diversity: it is posited as corrosive for On the side of broadened inclusion, we social capital, redistribution, and/or sol- consider membership in three analytical- idarity.3 We find such a conclusion pre- ly distinct ways: legal membership (as mature, given very mixed evidence.4 defined by citizenship law or formal rules Moreover, such an answer is analytically about who has access to rights); social or unsatisfactory. It does not get at the pos- interpersonal membership (referring to sible processes behind the tensions over social distance via networks of friendship membership and social citizenship, ten- and romantic relationships); and cultur- sions that we believe must be captured by al membership (who is viewed as a valu- a multilevel analysis. We begin to do this able member of society, as expressed in by combining insights about solidarity, 74 Dædalus, the Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/daed_a_01751 by guest on 28 September 2021 group identity, destigmatization, and so- national-level dynamics, tracking deserv- Bloemraad, cial movements that draw on normative ingness judgments as manifest in mem- Kymlicka, Lamont & political theory, social psychology, cul- bership in national welfare states. In this Son Hing tural sociology, and political sociology/ view, prospects for a more equal society political science. depend on national-level inclusion. In oth- In aiming to bridge levels of analysis, er accounts, boundary-drawing emerges we view these insights as complementary, from dynamic psychological processes re- each highlighting a dimension of inequal- sponsive to localized situational cues or to ity. The macrolevel concerns formal law the contingencies of particular activities, and public policy that determine mem- workplaces, social networks, and politi- bership, whether through legal rights or cal coalitions; and appeals to local cultur- bureaucratic rules governing access to ed- al scripts or, alternatively, to cultural rep- ucation, social assistance, medical care, ertoires that transcend the “nation” (such and so forth. The microlevel captures on- as human rights). Another view focuses the-ground experiences of membership instead on power and political contesta- based on interpersonal interactions and tion, with the prospects for a more equal intersubjective meaning-making. The society depending in part on the outcome mesolevel is conceptualized as scripts of such struggles. In what follows, we lay of worth, available cultural repertoires, out membership and social citizenship and practices institutionalized by orga- tensions, grapple with a set of multilevel, nizations.5 Mesolevel institutions from multidisciplinary explanatory approach- schools to workplaces establish rules, es, and consider future prospects. procedures, and norms that generate and communicate membership, and mediate One of the striking successes of the last the relationship between individuals and half-century is the struggle against ex- the state.6 Each level interacts and exer- clusionary definitions of national mem- cises reciprocal influence. bership. This is reflected in the trajecto- The literatures on which we draw share ries of both legal and sociocultural inclu- an emphasis on boundary-drawing, a pro- sion across Western democracies, which cess by which we categorize others as show a rejection of the idea that national worthy, valuable, or legitimate along di- membership is based on or limited to an mensions of morality and deservingness. ascribed ethnic background. Such symbolic boundaries, ones that dis- With respect to legal membership, the tinguish insiders and outsiders, can be ac- formal rules for acquiring citizenship or companied by reinforcing consequen- nationality have become more open.9 A tial social boundaries, as
Recommended publications
  • Animals and the Frontiers of Citizenship
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 34, No. 2 (2014), pp. 201–219 doi:10.1093/ojls/gqu001 Published Advance Access February 5, 2014 Animals and the Frontiers of Citizenship Will Kymlicka* and Sue Donaldson** Abstract —Citizenship has been at the core of struggles by historically excluded Downloaded from groups for respect and inclusion. Can citizenship be extended even further to domesticated animals? We begin this article by sketching an argument for why justice requires the extension of citizenship to domesticated animals, above and beyond compassionate care, stewardship or universal basic rights. We then consider two objections to this argument. Some animal rights theorists worry that extending citizenship to domesticated animals, while it may sound progressive, would in fact http://ojls.oxfordjournals.org/ be bad for animals, providing yet another basis for policing their behaviour to fit human needs and interests. Critics of animal rights, on the other hand, worry that the inclusion of ‘unruly’ beasts would be bad for democracy, eroding its core values and principles. We attempt to show that both objections are misplaced, and that animal citizenship would both promote justice for animals and deepen fundamental democratic dispositions and values. Keywords: citizenship, animal rights, justice, co-operation at Queen's University on June 23, 2014 1. Introduction In our recent book Zoopolis, we made the case for a distinctly ‘political theory of animal rights’.1 In this Lecture, we attempt to extend that argument, and to respond to some critics of it, by focusing specifically on the novel idea of ‘animal citizenship’. To begin, let us briefly situate our approach in the larger animal rights debate.
    [Show full text]
  • Educational Rights and the Roles of Virtues, Perfectionism, and Cultural Progress
    The Law of Education: Educational Rights and the Roles of Virtues, Perfectionism, and Cultural Progress R. GEORGE WRIGHT* I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 385 II. EDUCATION: PURPOSES, RECENT OUTCOMES, AND LEGAL MECHANISMS FOR REFORM ................................................................ 391 A. EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES AND RIGHTS LANGUAGE ...................... 391 B. SOME RECENT GROUNDS FOR CONCERN IN FULFILLING EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES ............................................................. 393 C. THE BROAD RANGE OF AVAILABLE TECHNIQUES FOR THE LEGAL REFORM OF EDUCATION ............................................................... 395 III. SOME LINKAGES BETWEEN EDUCATION AND THE BASIC VIRTUES, PERFECTIONISM, AND CULTURAL PROGRESS ..................................... 397 IV. VIRTUES AND THEIR LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM ...................................................................... 401 V. PERFECTIONISM AND ITS LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM ...................................................................... 410 VI. CULTURAL PROGRESS OVER TIME AND ITS LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM .............................................. 417 VII. CONCLUSION: EDUCATION LAW AS RIGHTS-CENTERED AND AS THE PURSUIT OF WORTHY VALUES AND GOALS: THE EXAMPLE OF HORNE V. FLORES ............................................................................................ 431 I. INTRODUCTION The law of education
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List for Comprehensive Examination in Political Theory
    READING LIST FOR COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION IN POLITICAL THEORY Department of Political Science Columbia University Requirements Majors should prepare for questions based on reading from the entire reading list. Minors should prepare for questions based on reading from the core list and any one of the satellite lists. CORE LIST Plato, The Republic Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics Books I, II, V, VIII, X; Politics Polybius, Rise of the Roman Empire, Book I paragraphs 1-10 (“Introduction”) and Book VI Cicero, The Republic Augustine, City of God, Books I, VIII (ch.s 4-11), XII, XIV, XIX, XXII (ch.s 23-24, 29-30) Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Questions 42, 66, 90-92, 94-97, 105 Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince; Discourses (as selected in Selected Political Writings, ed. David Wootton) Jean Bodin, On Sovereignty (ed. Julian Franklin) Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (as selected in Norton Critical Edition, ed. David Johnston) James Harrington, Oceana (Cambridge U. Press, ed. J.G.A. Pocock), pp. 63-70 (from Introduction), pp. 161-87; 413-19 John Locke, Second Treatise of Government; “A Letter Concerning Toleration” David Hume, “Of the Original Contract,” “The Independence of Parliament,” “That Politics May Be Reduced to A Science,” “Of the First Principle of Government,” “Of Parties in General” 1 Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws (as selected in Selected Political Writings, ed. Melvin Richter) Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Part I ("On the propriety of action"); Part II, Section II ("Of justice and beneficence"); Part IV ("On the effect of utility on the sentiment of approbation") Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Discourse on the Origins of Inequality; On The Social Contract Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (as selected in World’s Classics Edition, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • REID-DISSERTATION-2018.Pdf
    VEGANISM AND THE ETHICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY OF DISAGREEMENT: A NEO-PASCALIAN APPROACH By Adam Curran Reid, B.A., M.A. A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland, February, 2018 © Adam Curran Reid 2018 All Rights Reserved Abstract Disagreement is without a doubt one of the most universal, enduring, and oftentimes quite vexing, features of our life in common. This latter aspect, to be sure, becomes all the more evident when the particular disagreement at hand concerns differing ethical beliefs, value-judgments, or deep questions about the nature, and scope, of morally permissible action as such. One such question—also the chief subject of dispute to be taken up in this dissertation—is whether or not human beings are morally justified in killing, eating, wearing—in a word, exploiting—non-human animals for our benefit when doing so is neither required for us to survive or to flourish. Ethical vegans answer ‘no,’ insisting that non-human animals, qua sentient, conscious, experiential selves, ought to be treated with fundamental concern and respect, which, at a minimum, demands that we stop exploiting them as resources and commodities. Unsurprisingly, many disagree. While I shall have much more to say about (and in support for) ethical veganism in what follows, the guiding aim of this dissertation is firstly to explore certain key questions regarding the ethics and epistemology of disagreement(s) about veganism. In this way, my approach notably departs from that which has long prevailed (and rightly so) in conventional animal rights theory and vegan advocacy, where the emphasis, and aim, has generally been about making the first-order case for animal rights, abolition, and, therein, for veganism itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Connexion: a Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates
    Dalhousie Law Journal Volume 40 Issue 2 Article 5 10-1-2017 Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates John Enman-Beech Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.schulichlaw.dal.ca/dlj Part of the Animal Law Commons Recommended Citation John Enman-Beech, "Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates" (2017) 40:2 Dal LJ 545. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Schulich Law Scholars. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dalhousie Law Journal by an authorized editor of Schulich Law Scholars. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Enman-Beech* Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates Effective animal advocacy requires human-animal connexion. I apply a relational approach to unfold this insight into a praxis for animal advocates. Connexion grounds the affective relationships that so often motivate animal advocates. More importantly, it enables animal agency, the ability of animals to act and communicate in ways humans can experience and respond to. With connexion in mind, some weaknesses of previous reform efforts become apparent. I join these in the slogan "abolitionismas disconnexion." In so far as abolitionism draws humans and animals apart, it undermines the movement's social basis, limits its imaginative resources, and deprives animals of a deeper freedom. I evaluate political theories of animals and find that only some can frame a picture of humans and animals living together in connexion. I close by noting the limitations of the connexion lens-we cannot simply create connexions without also evaluating whether they are oppressive-and some practical policy measures that can be taken today to further the goods of connexion Pour 6tre efficace, /a defense des animaux exige une connexion entre /'homme et /'animal.
    [Show full text]
  • Doctor of Philosophy
    RICE UNIVERSITY By Drew Robert Winter A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE Doctor of Philosophy APPROVED, THESIS COMMITTEE Cymene Howe (Apr 15, 2020) Cymene Howe James Faubion James Faubion (Apr 15, 2020) James Faubion Cary Wolfe Cary Wolfe (Apr 16, 2020) Cary Wolfe HOUSTON, TEXAS April 2020 i Abstract Hyperanimals: framing livestock and climate change in Danish Imaginaries By Drew Robert Winter The IPCC and UN FAO have both suggested a global reduction in meat consumption to reduce greenhouse gas emissions. But how do nations and citizens resolve tensions between ecological stewardship and meat consumption? What is implied in eating meat and raising livestock in a country where the historical imaginary yokes national values to the pig-producing countryside? To answer these questions, this dissertation examines how climate change is affecting meat consumption and production logics in Denmark. Though the country has a reputation for progressive environmental policy, its formerly large agricultural sector continues to exert disproportionate political influence, and many citizens consider pork its most "traditional" food. In 2016, a publicly-funded advisory council issued a report suggesting that parliament pass a beef tax to reduce consumption and reflect its environmental impact. The report was the most controversial the council had ever issued, with members receiving angry phone calls and politicians arguing the council should be disbanded. The proposal put national tensions between sustainability
    [Show full text]
  • How We Tr-Eat Animals
    Umeå universitet Statsvetenskapliga institutionen HOW WE TR(EAT) ANIMALS A political analysis of the problems faced with implementing the capabilities approach Uppsats för C-seminariet i Statsvetenskap vid Umeå universitet Vårterminen 2015 Johan Westin Contents Abstract ...................................................................................................................................... 3 1. Introduction ............................................................................................................................ 4 2. Aims and purpose ................................................................................................................... 6 3. Limitations ............................................................................................................................. 6 4. Disposition ............................................................................................................................. 6 5. Theory .................................................................................................................................... 7 5.1 The capabilities approach ................................................................................................. 7 6. Method ................................................................................................................................. 11 6.1 Normative analysis ......................................................................................................... 11 6.1.1 Values and the ‘should’ questions
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Citizenship, Phenomenology, and Ontology: Some Reflections on Donaldson’S & Kymlicka’S Zoopolis
    Bangladesh Journal of Bioethics 2017; 8(1): 21-32 Original Article Animal Citizenship, Phenomenology, and Ontology: Some reflections on Donaldson’s & Kymlicka’s Zoopolis Iván Ortega Rodríguez Universidad Pontificia Comillas, Madrid, Spain Email: [email protected], [email protected] Abstract: This paper is a dialogue with Sue Donaldson’s and Will Kymlicka’s book Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights. My thesis is that, despite the authors’ reticence, considerations in first philosophy regarding humans and nonhumans are relevant to their goal of building a more comprehensive animal rights philosophy. What is more, I believe that first philosophy actually can be of help for their proposal, specifically in the form of phenomenology and phenomenological ontology. For this purpose, I first summarize the basic outline of Zoopolis’s position and indicate some questions that arise from a strictly internal consideration of its theses. And secondly, I introduce some aspects in which phenomenological research would be relevant, along with some particular and provisional analyses carried out from the standpoint of a phenomenologically-based ontology. Especially, there is a theme that stands out: the intersubjective realms between humans and nonhumans. Key Words: Animal Rights, Animal Philosophy, Phenomenology, ontology Bioethics, Ecology. Introduction: Animal philosophy received a decisive impulse with Sue Donaldson’s and Will Kymlicka’s book Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights 1 . It offered a comprehensive theory that, to a great extent, creates a new theoretical framework for thinking the moral status of nonhuman animals. In fact, it is not an understatement to say that Zoopolis is already a reference so unavoidable as Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation.
    [Show full text]
  • Nozick's Libertarian Critique of Regan
    68 BETWEEN THE SPECIES Nozick’s Libertarian Critique of Regan ABSTRACT Robert Nozick’s oft-quoted review of Tom Regan’s The Case for Animal Rights levels a range of challenges to Regan’s philosophy. Many commentators have focused on Nozick’s putative defense of speciesism, but this has led to them overlooking other aspects of the critique. In this paper, I draw attention to two. First is Nozick’s criti- cism of Regan’s political theory, which is best understood relative to Nozick’s libertarianism. Nozick’s challenge invites the possibility of a libertarian account of animal rights – which is not as oxymo- ronic as it may first sound. Second is Nozick’s criticism of Regan’s axiological theory, which is best understood relative to Nozick’s own axiological inegalitarianism. While Nozick’s axiology has distaste- ful consequences, it should not be dismissed out-of-hand. Nozick’s challenges to Regan – and Nozick’s wider animal ethics – are rich and original, warranting attention from contemporary theorists for reasons beyond mere historical interest. Josh Milburn University of York Volume 21, Issue 1 Spring 2018 http://digitalcommons.calpoly.edu/bts/ 69 Josh Milburn Tom Regan published The Case for Animal Rights (hereaf- ter, The Case) in 1983, spawning a literature of responses, cri- tiques, developments and applications. It continues to have con- siderable influence on philosophical literature in animal ethics to this day – as this special issue demonstrates. Regan belongs on a short list of the most influential and significant normative philosophers of the 21st century. Another philosopher who un- doubtedly belongs on this list is Robert Nozick, most famous as the author of the 1974 Anarchy, State, and Utopia (hereafter, ASU), in which he offers a right libertarian theory of justice.
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of a Theory of Human Rights
    AMARTYA SEN Elements of a Theory of Human Rights I. The Need for a Theory Few concepts are as frequently invoked in contemporary political dis- cussions as human rights. There is something deeply attractive in the idea that every person anywhere in the world, irrespective of citizenship or territorial legislation, has some basic rights, which others should respect. The moral appeal of human rights has been used for a variety of purposes, from resisting torture and arbitrary incarceration to demand- ing the end of hunger and of medical neglect.1 At the same time, the central idea of human rights as something that people have, and have even without any specific legislation, is seen by many as foundationally dubious and lacking in cogency. A recurrent question is, Where do these rights come from? It is not usually disputed that the invoking of human rights can be politically powerful. Rather, the worries relate to what is taken to be the “softness” (some would say “mushiness”) of the conceptual grounding of human rights. Many philosophers and legal theorists see the rhetoric of human rights as just An earlier version of this article served as my Gilbert Murray Lecture (“Why Invent Human Rights?”) given in Oxford on 14 November 2002. For helpful suggestions, I am particularly grateful to the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs, and also to Catherine Barnard, Rosanne Flynn, Sakiko Fukuda Parr, Ivan Hare, Will Kymlicka, Jo Miles, Martha Nussbaum, Onora O’Neill, Siddiq Osmani, Mary Robinson, Emma Rothschild, Thomas Scanlon, Arjun Sengupta, Frances Stewart, Rosemary Thorpe, and Rosie Vaughan. 1.See International Human Rights in Context: Law, Politics and Morals, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • CRITICAL TERMS for ANIMAL STUDIES
    CRITICAL TERMS for ANIMAL STUDIES Edited by LORI GRUEN THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS Chicago and London Contents Introduction • Lori Gruen 1 1 Abolition • Claire Jean Kim 15 2 Activism • Jeff Sebo and Peter Singer 33 3 Anthropocentrism • Fiona Probyn- Rapsey 47 4 Behavior • Alexandra Horowitz 64 5 Biopolitics • Dinesh Joseph Wadiwel 79 6 Captivity • Lori Marino 99 7 Difference • Kari Weil 112 8 Emotion • Barbara J. King 125 9 Empathy • Lori Gruen 141 10 Ethics • Alice Crary 154 11 Extinction • Thom van Dooren 169 12 Kinship • Agustín Fuentes and Natalie Porter 182 13 Law • Kristen Stilt 197 14 Life • Eduardo Kohn 210 15 Matter • James K. Stanescu 222 16 Mind • Kristin Andrews 234 17 Pain • Victoria A. Braithwaite 251 18 Personhood • Colin Dayan 267 19 Postcolonial • Maneesha Deckha 280 20 Rationality • Christine M. Korsgaard 294 21 Representation • Robert R. McKay 307 22 Rights • Will Kymlicka and Sue Donaldson 320 23 Sanctuary • Timothy Pachirat 337 24 Sentience • Gary Varner 356 25 Sociality • Cynthia Willett and Malini Suchak 370 26 Species • Harriet Ritvo 383 27 Vegan • Annie Potts and Philip Armstrong 395 28 Vulnerability • Anat Pick 410 29 Welfare • Clare Palmer and Peter Sandøe 424 Acknowledgments 439 List of Contributors 441 Index 451 INTRODUCTION Lori Gruen Animal Studies is almost always described as a new, emerging, and growing field. A short while ago some Animal Studies scholars suggested that it “has a way to go before it can clearly see itself as an academic field” (Gorman 2012). Other scholars suggest that the “discipline” is a couple of decades old (DeMello 2012).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Animal Rights, Multiculturalism and the Left Will Kymlicka and Sue
    Animal Rights, Multiculturalism and the Left1 Will Kymlicka and Sue Donaldson In shorthand summaries of the preferred causes of the progressive Left in the past 40 years, one often finds a reference to animal rights, alongside gender equality, gay rights, the disability movement, and the rights of immigrants, racial minorities and indigenous peoples. All are seen as paradigmatically progressive causes, fighting to emancipate historically subordinated and stigmatized groups, often subsumed under the label of “social justice struggles” or “citizenship struggles”. Yet the inclusion of animal rights in this list is misleading: the reality is that the animal question is virtually invisible within the Left. As Boggs notes, “Apart from its marginal leverage within the radical-ecology movement, animal rights discourse has scarcely entered into or altered the work of Left/progressive groups in the United States” (Boggs 2011: 73). Animal advocates are “orphans of the Left”,2championing a progressive cause that is shunned by other progressive movements.3 Animal rights may receive a passing ritualized mention before being promptly ignored.4 Nor is this a new phenomenon: the same pattern held for the old Left, in the 19th and early 20th centuries. As Sanbonmatsu notes, “the Left with few exceptions has historically viewed human violence towards other beings with indifference” (Sanbonmatsu 2011: 13). While this indifference is long-standing, its causes have arguably changed. Marx – who was contemptuous of animal rights movements5 – shared the Kantian/Hegelian view that the intrinsic value of humanity derives entirely from what distinguishes ‘man’ from animals, and that nature (including animals) is simply the stage on which humans enact their unique Promethean species powers for self-conscious and creative cooperative labour.
    [Show full text]