Pragmatism and Existential Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Pragmatism and Existential Philosophy Pragmatism and Existential Philosophy Hans Lipps Translation by Jason Hills Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy - Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française, Vol XVIII, No 1 (2008-2010) pp. 106-118. Vol XVIII, No 1 (2008-2010) ISSN 1936-6280 (print) ISSN 2155-1162 (online) DOI 10.5195/jffp.2010.174 http://www.jffp.org This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. This journal is published by the University Library System of the University of Pittsburgh as part of its D-Scribe Digital Publishing Program, and is co-sponsored by the University of Pittsburgh Press Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy | Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française Vol XVIII, No 1 (2008-2010) | jffp.org | DOI 10.5195/jffp.2010.174 Hans Lipps | 107 Pragmatism and Existential Philosophy Hans Lipps Translation by Jason Hills1 I Existential philosophy determines the current situation of philosophy in Germany; it consummates the most complete separation with prior philosophy. Despite the diversity of its systems and points of view of previous philosophies, we recognize today the homogeneity of its aims and the persistence of its problems. It was guided by a tendency taken a priori as natural that no longer suffices for the tendencies and aspirations that, in the thought of our time, urgently desire to surface. The fact that it is made up entirely of doctrines and systems appears to render it problematic. Perhaps no previous era “knew” those systems as well as ours, but the very fact that this philosophy can be transformed into pure and simple knowledge renders it suspect. We have learned not to trust what can be shown within the limits of reason, what can be contained within it, and what can be placed at the disposal of everyone and under the general shape of philosophy,2 without requiring any exertion or existential risk [risque d’existence].3 We recognize today the non-obligatory character of these systems and doctrines. The influence of Nietzsche and Kierkegaard is symptomatic of the current situation.4 Both were taken as outsiders in their days, because their thought differed so much from others. Here there are more doctrines and positions than one could ever prove or whose raison d’être could be discussed. It is an entirely new general attitude. It is not a thought content with solutions for freeing itself, as it were, from itself. Both Nietzsche and Kierkegaard attacked the “systems” in which everything seemed to them to be oversimplified and reduced to the trivial. They show how those systems move us away from the gravity of the problem that surfaced in the self, the reality of existence. The uncertain, tense, indefinite, fragmentary character of our temporal existence stands in contradiction with the totalizing nature that informs those doctrines. Both discovered how “inhuman” it is to begin Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy | Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française Vol XVIII, No 1 (2008-2010) | jffp.org | DOI 10.5195/jffp.2010.174 108 | Pragmatism and Existential Philosophy from a “pure” subject of knowledge. For Nietzsche the will to create a system reveals a lack of honesty. Here the question of knowing what philosophy “is” is posed anew. It frees itself from its union with science that goes back to Descartes. Knowledge, for Nietzsche and Kierkegaard, is “interpretation.” It is an understanding that enlightens, a discovery that reveals those very depths of our existence which are originally hidden. Existential philosophy is not a doctrine; it can only be learned through experience. For, this new movement of thought opens the space through which reflection must travel, all the while knowing that it will not have a basis. We would only like to determine the direction of the path of this thought. Kierkegaard said, “The philosopher of the system, as a man, resembles someone who builds a castle, yet who lives in the shed beside it. This fantastic being does not live in what he thinks, yet the thought of a man must be the house in which he lives.” One can easily notice a certain affinity between the motifs of such a thought and those of pragmatism. When pragmatism, without allowing itself to be influenced by any point of view, undertakes an analysis of the practice of knowledge, what does it find there, if not the insignificance and the platitudes of such disputes as those of scholastic philosophy? Pragmatism, also, combats a philosophy that, in ignorance of its originary character, wanted to establish itself as science, but as a supreme science, as a science that has never been up to date and that has always remained behind; whereas positive science, within the limits in which it makes sense, arrived at some results. Pragmatism combats systematic philosophy in the same manner. In this combat, it neither discusses nor explains itself to the adversary to determine to what extent a point of view is right. Both [pragmatism and existential philosophy] separate themselves clearly from the beginning from their adversary, and without allowing the least discussion with them. The comparison between the two directions is all the more convincing since neither of them underwent the influence of the other. We will make a comparison between these two philosophies, so that in treating one, we will tackle the other; this will allow us to show the difference that appears in their overall structure, between these ways of philosophizing, by taking as the common denominator the progression of the ideas of each towards the notion of truth. Let us say it one more time: pragmatism and existential philosophy look to regain a connection to reality. Pragmatism resorts to practical experience that it contrasts with the outrageousness of the traditional conception of truth; existential philosophy, in its desire for intellectual honesty, makes its appeal to the earnestness of the individual. We will thus try to specify the domain of pragmatism and of existential philosophy. This domain is revealed by a specific spiritual attitude in each case. This spiritual attitude is either bound to certain requirements that pragmatism posits as Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy | Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française Vol XVIII, No 1 (1008-2010) | jffp.org | DOI 10.5195/jffp.2010.174 Hans Lipps | 109 being equivalent to the truth, or, in connection to existential philosophy, to the specific inquiry of the “real”5 truth that it proposes. II Criticism is however too easy a task for pragmatism. One must try hard to penetrate the great intentions of James and Dewey to recognize the nearness of pragmatism to the works of the young Nietzsche, for example, who speaks in his second “Untimely Meditation” of the “lazy in the garden of knowledge.” Dewey denounces the “prejudice that wants that what is6 exists only as being known by the mind in some manner,” as if the structure of what is4 could consist only in the concept. Our primordial connection with things is not, for Dewey, knowledge. It is rather transaction [commerce] with things that is first given. One has them and experiences them, for example, in manipulating them, in wanting them, and in objecting to them as objects. They show themselves to me through their resistance. I notice the weather outside as it exerts an influence on my mood. We have experience of things solely through their continuity with practice. I do not need knowledge about a number written as a decimal; I must solely “know” of it, have at my disposal a know-how on the subject, possess the manner to write it, etc., in order to know how to count with it. But, knowledge in the proper sense of the word would signify that one retains something insofar as one understands or imagines it. Here a “lasting” possession was considered true. At first we act in connection with things, and we are right or not insofar as we know of them; error is a mistake. The way that I experience a thing is reflected in the manner and direction of my transaction with it. What is4 does not first have a structure conceived by the mind, as the object of knowledge that is always “represented” in whatever manner. Does not the word “comprehend” indicate the direction of “prehending,” taking in hand, that is to say, understanding a thing to the point of knowing how to handle it? We never experience things in some isolated fashion as “objects,” but always in the context of situations. The closest reality had always been subtracted. But, in this case, what does “knowledge” mean? One speaks of the “object” of knowledge. The thing to be known appears in the form of an encounter; it is thus an object only in a “temporary” way. Knowledge has an “episodic” character (Dewey). Knowledge always responds to a question: one examines, one watches up close, one contemplates intensively. The driving force of this heightened activity is always the difficulty in which one finds oneself that is due to the interruption of “knowing”: one no longer knows how to handle things. Knowledge depends upon the reconstruction of this. Knowing is thus always surrounded by a horizon that is not on the same plane as knowledge, but that holds the knowing subject, leading one farther and guiding secretly. It is not by chance that one desires to know. There is no “pure,” disinterested knowledge. One expects something from it, notably to be able to use things again. Each thing known relates to a Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy | Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française Vol XVIII, No 1 (2008-2010) | jffp.org | DOI 10.5195/jffp.2010.174 110 | Pragmatism and Existential Philosophy particular natural situation.
Recommended publications
  • Adolf Reinach: an Intellectual Biography1
    Adolf Reinach: An Intellectual Biography1 Karl Schumann and Barry Smith From: K. Mulligan, ed., Speech Act and Sachverhalt: Reinach and the Foundations of Realist Phenomenology, Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: Nijhoff, 1987, 1–27. §1 PROLOGUE As early as 1741 a Jekel Reinach is mentioned in the Memory Book of the Jewish community in Mainz, and by the end of the century the Reinachs were already one of the most notable and well-to-do Jewish families in the city.2 The Record of Names of 1808 lists Salomon (formerly Seligmann) Reinach, Jacques (Mayer Herz) Reinach, Marx (Mayer Herz) Reinach, and Bernard Jacques (Beer Jacob) Reinach.3 The descendants of Jacques Reinach spread from Mainz to Frankfurt and from there to Paris. His grandson Adolf von Reinach (1814-1879), Belgian consul in Frankfurt, was created an Italian Baron in 1866, and founded 1 The few existing published biographies of Reinach are, if not unreliable (Oesterreicher 1952), then at best very succinct (Avé-Lallemant 1975, 172-74, Crosby 1983, XI-X). In compiling the present essay we have used in particular Reinach’s letters to Husserl (Husserl Archives) and to Conrad and Daubert (Bavarian State Library, Munich). We draw further on Avé-Lallemant’s Catalogue of the Münchener Phänomenologennachlässe, on Schuhmann’s Husserl-Chronik (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1977), and on the pertinent Vorlesungsverzeichnisse of the University of Göttingen. We have also profited from the “Historical Introduction” to Brettler 1974, 1-15. References not given in full here are to be found in the Reinach bibliography on pp. 299-332 below. We would like to thank the Bavarian State Library, the Husserl Archives, Louvain, and Oberarchivrat Schütz of the Stadtarchiv Mainz for providing copies of relevant materials.
    [Show full text]
  • Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences
    Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences Volume 8 Series Editors Ruth Edith Hagengruber, Department of Humanities, Center for the History of Women Philosophers, Paderborn University, Paderborn, Germany Mary Ellen Waithe, Professor Emerita, Department of Philosophy and Comparative Religion, Cleveland State University, Cleveland, OH, USA Gianni Paganini, Department of Humanities, University of Piedmont, Vercelli, Italy As the historical records prove, women have long been creating original contributions to philosophy. We have valuable writings from female philosophers from Antiquity and the Middle Ages, and a continuous tradition from the Renaissance to today. The history of women philosophers thus stretches back as far as the history of philosophy itself. The presence as well as the absence of women philosophers throughout the course of history parallels the history of philosophy as a whole. Edith Stein, Hannah Arendt and Simone de Beauvoir, the most famous represen- tatives of this tradition in the twentieth century, did not appear form nowhere. They stand, so to speak, on the shoulders of the female titans who came before them. The series Women Philosophers and Scientists published by Springer will be of interest not only to the international philosophy community, but also for scholars in history of science and mathematics, the history of ideas, and in women’s studies. More information about this series at https://www.springer.com/series/15896 Ronny Miron Hedwig Conrad-Martius The Phenomenological Gateway to Reality Ronny Miron Interdisciplinary Studies Bar-Ilan University Ramat Gan, Israel ISSN 2523-8760 ISSN 2523-8779 (electronic) Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences ISBN 978-3-030-68782-3 ISBN 978-3-030-68783-0 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-68783-0 © The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2021 This work is subject to copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • Masterarbeit / Master's Thesis
    MASTERARBEIT / MASTER’S THESIS Titel der Masterarbeit / Title of the Master‘s Thesis An Exposition of Edith Stein’s Inquiry into the Meaning of Being verfasst von / submitted by Dr. Jose Conrado Estafia, PhL, MA, MA, SThB, AB angestrebter akademischer Grad / in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts (MA) Wien, 2018 / Vienna 2018 Studienkennzahl lt. Studienblatt / A 066 795 degree programme code as it appears on the student record sheet: Studienrichtung lt. Studienblatt / Masterstudium Theologische Spezialisierungen / degree programme as it appears on Advanced Theological Studies the student record sheet: Betreut von / Supervisor: Uni.-Prof. MMMag. DDr. Kurt Appel TABLE OF CONTENTS Foreword 2 Introduction 4 Chapter One: From Phenomenology to Christian Philosophy: A Short Look at Edith Stein’s Journey 12 1. Her Way to Phenomenology 13 2. Her Way to the Catholic Faith 24 3. Her Way to Christian Philosophy 29 Chapter Two: Inquiry into the Meaning of Being 34 1. The Doctrine of Act and Potency 35 2. The Fact of Our Own Being 39 3. Temporality as a Progress of Actuality 42 4. The Experience of Capability 43 5. Being Human as Transitory 47 6. The Pure Ego 49 7. Received Being as Dependent of Eternal Being 55 Summary, Conclusion, and Recommendations 62 Bibliography 68 Abstract (English) 79 (Deutsch) 79 Curriculum Vitae 81 FOREWORD A Carmelite nun once suggested that I should be writing a thesis on Edith Stein for my licentiate and master’s degree in philosophy. That was the first time I heard of Edith Stein. I followed her suggestion, only to find out how few were the sources on this Catholic woman philosopher in Manila, both in the Dominican-run University of Santo Tomas (UST) and in the Jesuit-run Ateneo de Manila University.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, XI-1 | 2019 Pragmatism in the Third Reich 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy XI-1 | 2019 European Pragmatism Pragmatism in the Third Reich Heidegger and the Baumgarten Case Hans-Joachim Dahms Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1524 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.1524 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Hans-Joachim Dahms, « Pragmatism in the Third Reich », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], XI-1 | 2019, Online since 19 July 2019, connection on 21 July 2019. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1524 ; DOI : 10.4000/ejpap.1524 This text was automatically generated on 21 July 2019. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Pragmatism in the Third Reich 1 Pragmatism in the Third Reich Heidegger and the Baumgarten Case Hans-Joachim Dahms AUTHOR'S NOTE I published some years ago an article covering briefly the current subject: Dahms (1987/1998: 299-303). In the meantime new literature appeared on the theme, especially Vogt 2002 and Hausmann 2003. Whereas Hausmann tackled the task from the viewpoint of American Studies in Germany, though adding a number of new sources, Vogts writes as a historian of philosophy without considering any archival files concerning the Baumgarten case. I will not only comment on these works, but also add some new sources from the Göttingen university archive and its library. I thank Prof. Robert P. Ericksen (Gig Harbour, Wa., USA) for valuable help in improving my English draft.
    [Show full text]
  • DOCUMENTIONS EDITH STEIN MATERIALS in the Archives of the State University of New York at Buffalo
    Teresianum 55 (2004/1) 195-222 DOCUMENTIONS EDITH STEIN MATERIALS In the Archives of the State University of New York at Buffalo S t e v e n P a y n e O C D In the summer of 1998, at the suggestion of Sr. Josephine Koeppel, OCD, I visited the archives of the State University of New York (SUNY) at Buffalo, searching for any materiale related to Edith Stein1. University Archivist Christopher Densmore and I identified four previously unpublished lettere from Stein to Marvin Farber, which were then brought to the attention of the Archivum Carmelitanum Edith Stein in Cologne, Germany and subsequently appeared in the new edition of Stein's Selbstbildnis in Briefen2. Elsewhere over the past five years I have published a few brief excerpts from these letters and other accompanying 1 Sr. Josephine Koeppel, OCD, is a Discalced Carmelite nun of the community of Elysburg, PA, and the English language translator of sev­ eral volumes of the works of Edith Stein for ICS Publications. She has provided the English translation of the four Stein letters (actually two letters and two postcards) found in the SUNY-Buffalo Archives, as well as the passage from Husserl quoted by Fritz Kaufmann in his letter of 9-11 September 1945, below. The present article is dedicated to the memory of my brother John Payne, who died shortly before my visit to the archives. 2 A new expanded edition of Edith Steins collected letters can be found in volumes 2 to 4 of Verlag Herder s "Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe” series; see Edith Stein, Selbstbildnis in Briefen, I-III (Herder: Freiburg, 2000-2001).
    [Show full text]
  • Hermeneutics and the Humanities.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 01-05-12 / 14:17 | Pag
    Hermeneutics Hermeneutik und and the Humanities Geisteswissenscha en DIALOGUES WITH | IM DIALOG MIT - LUP Hermeneutics and the Humanities.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 01-05-12 / 14:17 | Pag. 1 Hermeneutics and the Humanities Hermeneutik und die Geisteswissenschaften Hermeneutics and the Humanities.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 01-05-12 / 14:17 | Pag. 2 Hermeneutik und die Geisteswissenschaften im dialog mit hans-georg gadamer Hermeneutics and the Humanities.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 01-05-12 / 14:17 | Pag. 3 Hermeneutics and the Humanities dialogues with hans-georg gadamer Edited by Madeleine Kasten, Herman Paul, Rico Sneller Leiden University Press Hermeneutics and the Humanities.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 01-05-12 / 14:17 | Pag. 4 Cover design and lay-out: Sander Pinkse Boekproductie, Amsterdam ISBN 978 90 8728 154 0 e-ISBN 978 94 0060 072 0 (pdf) e-ISBN 978 94 0060 073 7 (ePub) NUR 730 © M.J.A. Kasten, H.J. Paul, H.W. Sneller/Leiden University Press 2012 All rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reser - ved above, no part of this book may be reproduced, stored in or intro- duced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise) without the written permission of both the copyright owner and the author of the book. Hermeneutics and the Humanities.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 01-05-12 / 14:17 | Pag. 5 Table of contents Acknowledgments 7 Introduction 9 Herman Paul 1 Das Verstehen verstehen:
    [Show full text]
  • Peter Emberley Contemporary Perspective Will Morrisey Will Morrisey Hans-Georg Gadamer
    A JOURNAL OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY May & Sept. 1986 Volume 14 Numbers 2 & 3 155 Joseph Cropsey The Dramatic End of Plato's Socrates 177 Charles Griswold, Jr. Philosophy, Education, and Courage in Plato's Laches 195 Thomas J. Lewis Refutative Rhetoric as True Rhetoric in the Gorgias 211 Thomas F. Curley III How to Read the Consolation of Philosophy 265 Joseph Masciulli The Armed Founder versus the Catonic Hero: Machiavelli and Rousseau on Popular Leadership 281 William Mathie Reason and Rhetoric in Hobbes's Leviathan 299 Peter Emberley Rousseau versus the Savoyard Vicar: the Profession of Faith Considered 331 Mackubin Thomas Owens, Jr. Alexander Hamilton on Natural Rights and Prudence 353 Peter Simpson Autonomous Morality and the Idea of the Noble Review Essays 371 Ernest L. Fortin Faith and Reason in Contemporary Perspective Apropos of a Recent Book 389 Joseph J. Carpino On Eco's The Name of the Rose 415 Nino Langiulli Affirmative Action, Liberalism, and Teleology: on Nicholas Capaldi's Out of Order 431 Robert R. Sullivan The Most Recent Thinking of Jurgen Habermas Book Reviews 441 Will Morrisey Jerusalem versus Athens by Paul Eidelberg 448 How Does the Constitution Secure Rights? edited by Robert A. Goldwin & William A. Schambra Short Notices 455 Will Morrisey Freedom ofExpression by Francis Canavan 456 Joan Stambaugh Philosophical Apprenticeships by Hans-Georg Gadamer interpretation Volume 14 JL numbers 2 & 3 Editor-in-Chief Hilail Gildin Editors Seth G. Benardete Charles E. Butterworth Hilail Gildin Robert Horwitz Howard B.White (d.1974) Consulting Editors Joseph Cropsey John Hallowell Wilhelm Hennis Erich Hula Harry V.
    [Show full text]
  • Generic Concept of Meaning and Hermeneutical Logic by Hans Lipps
    ARCHIWUM HISTORII FILOZOFII I MYŚLI SPOŁECZNEJ • ARCHIVE OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY AND SOCIAL THOUGHT VOL. 64/2019 • ISSN 0066–6874 DOI: 10.37240/AHFiMS.2019.64.8 Krzysztof Sołoducha Generic Concept of Meaning and Hermeneutical Logic by Hans Lipps The task of logic is to discover the laws of truth Gottlob Frege ABSTRACT: The linguistic turn in philosophy of the 19th and 20th century added to the classical question about the constitution of being, the question of language and its role in this process. It also posed a new metaphilosophical question concerning the very status of philosophy and the results of its deliberations, facing the discovery that the linguistic nature of knowledge is its basic exoteric property. In Hans Lipps’ philosophy there is a characteristic and symptomatic connection between the conclusions drawn from the linguistic revolution in philosophy, and anthropological, biological and pragmatic threads. The task of this paper, referring to Lipps’ considerations, will be to indicate the programme and consequences of such an approach to the theory of language. According to Lipps the judgement is not an exemplification of the state of things. It is the states of things, their properties and their relations that are the product of self-explanatory existence which builds their meanings, thanks to the power of language manifesting itself in the “Konzeption” – the teleological power of language. KEYWORDS: hermeneutical logic • hermeneutical philosophy • Göttinger Group of Logic • phenomenology Introduction. Regressive philosophy and theory he background for our deliberations is going to be a statement on the Tstate of philosophy and humanities at the beginning of 21st century, which is not very encouraging.
    [Show full text]
  • Gadamer Dialogue
    IDEAS • BOOKS • SOCIETY • READINGS © Philobiblon. Transylvanian Journal of Multidisciplinary Research in Humanities HERMENEUTICAL CIRCLE IN UNDERSTANDING ON AN ORIGINAL LINK BETWEEN HERMENEUTICS AND LOGIC IN THE HEIDEGGER – GADAMER DIALOGUE * ZSUZSANNA MARIANN LENGYEL Abstract The hermeneutical circle is one of the most fundamental but up to now contentious doctrines with a long tradition in the history of hermeneutics. In what follows, the purpose of my contribution is to reconsider the Heidegger–Gadamer dialogue on the circle (Zirkel, Zirkelhaftigkeit), with an emphasis on how they shed new light on the whole issue. Keywords circle, prejudices, humanism, hermeneutics, logic, rhetoric, Gadamer, Heidegger Introduction In the case of Heidegger and Gadamer, the issue of the hermeneutical circle (in other words: the whole idea of the circular structure of interpretation) is about the close interrelation between understanding and prejudices, i.e. about the idea that the entire process of understanding includes certain preliminary expectations. I will argue that their dialogue on the circle led to the discovery of an original link between hermeneutics and logic. (I) First of all, I shall make a brief presentation of the conceptual background rooted in Antiquity of the circle whose criticism led to the two different hermeneutic accounts of circle. (II–III) Then I shall try * doi: 10.26424/philobib.2018.23.1.05 Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest, [email protected]. My paper was supported by the research project No. PD 121045 of the National Research, Development and Innovation Office (NKFI-OTKA). I have used the text of my lecture held at the Annual Conference of International Society for Hermeneutics and Science (ISHS), organized by the University of Vienna, the Medical University of Vienna, the Corvinus University and the Eötvös Loránd University, Baden (Austria), August 22–24, 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Edith Stein: 1891 – 1942 Breslau – Birkenau
    Edith Stein: 1891 – 1942 Breslau – Birkenau Breslau was the capital of the Prussian province of Silesia, Germany. (present-day Wrocław, Poland) Birkenau was one of the three camps at Auschwitz, Poland. her spiritual journey and her legacy “I am a Prussian citizen and a Jewess.” (1916 Curriculum-vitae) I am “... a child of the Jewish people ... also ... a child of the Catholic Church ...” (1933 letter to Pope Pius XI) “I am a Catholic.” (1942 to a transit camp offi cer) Edith Stein at 35 years old. Photo taken during the 1926 summer vacation in Breslau for a student teacher at St Magdalena’s College, a Dominican girls’ school and teachers’ college in Speyer, where Edith taught for eight years. [Neyer, Edith Stein: Her Life in Photos and Documents, (ICS, 1999), page 39.] Edith’s family Family Portrait 1893: Edith was the youngest of eleven children - seven surviving to adulthood. Back Row L-R: Paul, Elfriede (Frieda), Siegfried, Else, Arno. Front Row L-R: Rosa, Auguste, Edith, Erna. Siegfried had already died when this photo was taken Auguste Stein: Edith’s but the family had his passport photo inserted into the mother. The fourth of picture, to complete the family portrait. fi fteen Courant children. Family Photo 1911: Edith (front row, with light- coloured coat) on an outing with family and friends. Sisters: Erna left, Edith right. [for more on the family history see 20 months difference in age. https://www.wikitree.com/wiki/Courant-10] Edith’s friends Göttingen phenomenologists in 1912: L-R: Johannes Hering, Friedrich Neumann, Adolf Reinach, Hans Lipps, Hans-Theodor Conrad, Max Scheler, Alexandre Koyré, Siegfried Hamburger, Hedwig (Hattie) Martius, Rudolf Clemens, Gustav Edmund Husserl: ‘the master’ Hübener, Alfred Von Sybel.
    [Show full text]
  • Løgstrup's Criticism of Kierkegaard
    Løgstrup’s Criticism of Kierkegaard - Epistemological and Anthropological Dimensions Gunnar M. Karlsen lthough the differences between Kierkegaard and Grundtvig both Al in style and content are undeniable, there are also some impor­ tant similarities. First, they both criticize romantic philosophy for mediating Christian faith and denying the importance of the unique historical event on which that faith is dependent.1 Second, both in Grundtvig and Kierkegaard there is a hermeneu­ tic of Christian faith which states the full development of human exis­ tence as a necessary condition for attaining faith. Finally, both Kierke­ gaard and Grundtvig are extremely difficult to interpret in a consi­ stent way. It could be said that while Kierkegaard meant the difficulti­ es to be there, the problem in the case of Grundtvig is that his views on fundamental issues several times underwent dramatic changes, and therefore it is hard to state the fundamental and genuine Grundt- vigian doctrine. However, the purpose of this article is not to undertake a com­ parison between Kierkegaard and Grundtvig, but to describe and dis­ cuss the criticism of Kierkegaard by the theologian and philosopher Knud E. Løgstrup (1905-1981). Starting in the Tidehverv movement he gradually developed into an ardent critic of both existentialist theolo­ gy and Kierkegaard. It would, however, be misleading to take this cri­ ticism as a starting-point. His main project is not anti-Kierkegaardia- nism, but a reinterpretation of the Judaeo-Christian doctrine of crea­ tion, developed as an ongoing dialogue with, and criticism of, the transcendental idealistic element in post-Kantian continental philoso­ phy (especially in neo-Kantianism and Heidegger).
    [Show full text]
  • “Holding Oneself Open in a Conversation” – Gadamer's
    “Holding Oneself Open in a Conversation” – Gadamer’s Philosophical Hermeneutics and the Ethics of Dialogue Scherto Gill Philosophical hermeneutic ‘understands itself not as an absolute position but as a way of experience. It insists that there is no higher principle than holding oneself open in a conversation’ –Hans Georg Gadamer This paper’s aim is to explore Gadamer’s philosophical hermeneutics in order to draw out implications for the ethics of dialogue. Through examining key interconnected components in Gadamer’s theory, I highlight the openness to the other and otherness as a key normative ideal for dialogic understanding and their influence on the core practical ethos that underpins dialogue encounter, including the ethics of alterity, self-cultivation, equality, reciprocity, and solidarity. We further consider hermeneutical application or praxis by way of a guide insofar as to how one might act in the world through dialogue construed through these ethical dimensions. Keywords: philosophical hermeneutics, Gadamer, dialogue, encounter, otherness, ethics, praxis. Introduction Gadamer argues that dialogue is fundamental to understanding and to our way of being-in-the-world (Heidegger 1962). Since a human’s embeddedness and finitude demand self-transformation, the hermeneutical problem is not only universal but also existential. One of the central threads in Gadamer’s philosophical hermeneutics is the place of the other in dialogic interpretation and in the process of understanding. From this emerges the intersubjective nature of transcendent human conditions. Dialogue takes place whilst individuals seek to understand within the interplay of the perspectives present in an encounter, which are constituted in historical consciousness, traditions, cultural contexts, and so forth.
    [Show full text]