Emerson, Rödl, and the Life of Nature

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Emerson, Rödl, and the Life of Nature EMERSON'S IDEALIST POETICS: EMERSON, RÖDL, AND THE LIFE OF NATURE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of English by Robert Darren Hutchinson B.A., Furman University, 1989 Ph.D. Vanderbilt University, 1996 May 2020 Table of Contents Abstract ......................................................................................................................... iii Chapter 1. Introduction ................................................................................................ 1 A. The Problem of Emerson’s Poetics ......................................................... 1 B. Emerson’s Ghosts ................................................................................... 9 C. The Writing of Spontaneity .................................................................. 19 D. Overview ............................................................................................... 30 Chapter 2. The Idealism of Sebastian Rödl ................................................................ 33 A. Introduction to Rödl’s Approach .......................................................... 33 B. Preliminary Methodological Issues ..................................................... 41 C. Practical Self-Consciousness ................................................................ 50 D. Theoretical Self-Consciousness............................................................ 73 E. Materialism and Intersubjectivity ....................................................... 88 Chapter 3. Emerson’s Idealist Poetics ...................................................................... 108 A. The Opening of Nature ....................................................................... 108 B. The Problem of Our History ............................................................... 123 C. On Emerson’s Idealism ...................................................................... 137 D. Solitude .............................................................................................. 150 E. The Perpetual Presence of the Sublime ............................................ 156 F. The Transparent Eyeball ................................................................... 170 Bibliography ............................................................................................................... 204 Vita ............................................................................................................................. 208 ii Abstract In this dissertation, I articulate a hermeneutics for reading Ralph Waldo Emerson’s seminal text Nature through drawing on the insights of the contemporary philosopher Sebastian Rödl. Particularly, the performative, literary characteristics of Rödl’s quite conceptual work resonate with the poetic strategies that Emerson employs in Nature. In the section on the work of Rödl, I make the performative aspects of his philosophy explicit through a close reading of the way self-consciousness happens in his texts through the language he employs. Rödl refers to his elucidation of self-consciousness as idealism. In the section on Emerson, I show how Emerson’s project of engaging and transforming the individual soul also rests upon a performative idealism that occurs within his writing. Thus, I demonstrate how Emerson transforms the idealism that he inherited from such thinkers as Coleridge and Kant into a poetics of transcendence. The aims of this work point in the directions of heightening the value of Emerson’s texts beyond their historical importance, showing the significance of idealism for both literature and philosophy, and establishing a communication between literature and philosophy along the lines of the poetics of idealism. iii Chapter 1. Introduction A. The Problem of Emerson’s Poetics Emerson’s Nature is not really about nature. Nature’s chapter headings, after its introduction and self-named first chapter, enumerate "Commodity,” “Beauty,” “Language,” “Discipline,” “Idealism,” “Spirit,” and “Prospects” as its specific concerns: we might have expected “Rocks,” “Water,” “Plants,” “Animals,” “Weather,” “Planets,” and “The Cosmos.” The things and concepts Emerson names are essential to human mind and culture, not nature, at least in the traditional sense of this term. If, however, we remember that Nature is a work steeped in the tradition of German idealism, then its focus on the primacy of human consciousness and essential human concepts hardly seems surprising. In his lecture “The Transcendentalist,” Emerson explains this reorientation of the idealist’s approach to describing the world by contrasting it to the approach of the materialist: In the order of thought, the materialist takes his departure from the external world, and esteems a man as one product of that. The idealist takes his departure from his consciousness, and reckons the world an appearance. Mind is the only reality, of which men and all other natures are better or worse reflectors. Nature, literature, history, are only subjective phenomena. .His thought, — that is the Universe. (TCRWE I, 203) Here, Emerson provides us with an elementary dialectical elucidation of his approach in Nature. Whereas the materialist views herself and the world from a third-person perspective, the idealist begins with the first-person perspective (whether singular or plural) and orders all appearances in terms of its outward directed arrow. To use my pair of my examples from above, to understand “Rocks,” 1 the idealist would ask how we first encounter rocks as relevant appearances (for instance, the relevance of flint for starting fires), rather than assessing them in light of their neutral material being. “Water,” as well, always appears for me first in its value for slaking thirst and the beauty and sublimity offered by its scintillations and vast expanses, etc., and if I want to study its chemical properties as H2O, I only do so through the discipline of a science that allows me to discern an elegant molecular geometry. In this lecture, though it is nowhere nearly as poetically reflective as the great passages from Nature, Emerson is extremely subtle and consistent. In the next sentence following the passage above, Emerson implicitly indicates that we should not consider even “Transcendentalism” as a subject of neutral intellectual interest but should rather encounter it through its relevance for us: “From this transfer of the world into the consciousness, this beholding of all things in the mind, follow easily his whole ethics. It is simpler to be self-dependent.” Transcendentalism is not merely an account of the mind’s relation to the world but rather an account of this for the subject in her pursuit of autonomy. In a parallel move later in the essay, he acknowledges that “the Idealism of the present day acquired the name of Transcendental, from the use of that term by Immanuel Kant, of Konigsberg” and gives a brief philosophical genealogy of the term, only to transfigure it in the next paragraph once again: Although, as we have said, there is no pure Transcendentalist, yet the tendency to respect the intuitions, and to give them, at least in our creed, all authority over our experience, has deeply colored the conversation and poetry of the present day; and the history of genius 2 and of religion in these times, though impure, and as yet not incarnated in any powerful individual, will be the history of this tendency. (TCRWE I, 207) No one is a “pure” transcendentalist, since sensory affection and the call of material interests are always present, sometimes pressing in such a demanding way that individuals forget themselves and pretend to think of a world without them in it, but here, Emerson follows the articulation of transcendentalism from a theory into a calling, an orientation seeking an incarnation on her way to being poetized within a history of genius, transfigured beyond the body, a spirit waiting for others to inspire. If we place Emerson along such a path, we will witness him change from Emerson the man into Emerson the idea, an idea that travels from him to us on the way to our inheritance of it within the creative projection of our ideal selves. The main argument of this essay is that Emerson’s Nature composes its own sophisticated idealist poetics. The idealism within these poetics is not merely inherited from metaphysical idealists such as Berkeley or German idealists such as Kant and Fichte, although Emerson was variously influenced by their thought. Rather, the brilliance of Emerson’s idealist poetics consists in its blending the project of the self-consciousness of the subject together with a poetic language of self-figuration (figuration as artistic creation and as representation, a sounding of the “unsounded centre,” finding its voice, founding its call). Part of the work in making my argument will involve showing how Emerson deploys these blended configurations in his work. This will require me to take a micrological approach, one focusing on dense or subtle junctures in Emerson’s language at the expense of 3 discussing broad themes or contexts, although I do not consider this to be a close reading in the new critical sense. Sometimes, disclosing the operations within these configurations will involve going beyond Emerson into historical comparisons with other works, such as philosophical texts or poems. Sometimes, this will require
Recommended publications
  • The Personalized A-Theory of Time and Perspective
    The Personalized A-Theory of Time and Perspective Vincent Conitzer∗ Abstract A-theorists and B-theorists debate whether the “Now” is metaphysically distinguished from other time slices. Analogously, one may ask whether the “I” is metaphysically distin- guished from other perspectives. Few philosophers would answer the second question in the affirmative. An exception is Caspar Hare, who has devoted two papers and a book to arguing for such a positive answer. In this paper, I argue that those who answer the first question in the affirmative – A-theorists – should also answer the second question in the affirmative. This is because key arguments in favor of the A-theory are more effective as arguments in favor of the resulting combined position, and key arguments against the A-theory are ineffective against the combined position. Keywords: metaphysics, philosophy of time, philosophy of self. ∗Departments of Computer Science, Economics, and Philosophy, Duke University, Box 90129, Durham, NC 27708, USA; Email: [email protected] 1 1 Introduction In a series of unconventional but lucid works, Caspar Hare has laid out and defended a theory of egocentric presentism (or, in his more recent work, perspectival realism), in which a distinguished individual’s experiences are present in a way that the experiences of others are not (Hare, 2007, 2009, 2010). Closely related ideas appear in the writings of others. One example is Valberg (2007)’s notion of the “personal horizon,” especially considering his discussion of “the truth in solipsism” and his insistence that “my” horizon is really “the” (preeminent) horizon. Merlo (2016)’s “subjectivist view of the mental” is arguably even more closely related; he argues that “one’s own mental states are metaphysically privileged vis-a-vis` the mental states of others” and discusses in detail the relationship of his view to Hare’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Space and Time - Shahn Majid
    FUNDAMENTALS OF PHYSICS - Philosophy of Space And Time - Shahn Majid PHILOSOPHY OF SPACE AND TIME Shahn Majid Queen Mary, University of London, London, UK. Keywords: Born-reciprocity, relativity, quantum theory, momentum space, spacetime continuum, Planck scale, quantum gravity, quantum spacetime, quantum group, noncommutative geometry, relative realism, nature of time Contents 1. Introduction 2. Prehistory of Space and Time 3. Spacetime Continuum 4. Failure of the Spacetime Continuum 5. Quantum Geometry 6. Quantum Spacetime and Experiment 7. Time, Matter and Dark Energy 8. Philosophical Perspective 9. Conclusions Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch Summary It is easy to think that our notions of space and time have barely changed since the ancient Greeks. With the proviso of certain relativistic effects, we more or less take them for granted as the backdrop in which all other Sciences take place. But is this correct? We will see in this chapter that since the 1950s it has been clear that the assumption of a spacetime continuum is actually unjustified and could well be wrong. Only in the 1980s, however, were serious alternatives developed by mathematicians and since then a growing confluence of philosophical ideology, mathematical innovation and the possibility of experimental test has led to the emergence of a new science of space and time. UNESCO-EOLSS In principle thereSAMPLE are as many approaches toCHAPTERS spacetime as there are to the unsolved problem of a unified theory of quantum gravity. However, we will explain how a coherent new science has emerged in spite of that, based on the idea of „quantum spacetime‟ as a common framework.
    [Show full text]
  • A Manifestation of All Life : Intersections of Virtue Ethics, Philosophy of Emotion, and Philosophy of Literature
    University of Louisville ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository Electronic Theses and Dissertations 12-2010 A manifestation of all life : intersections of virtue ethics, philosophy of emotion, and philosophy of literature. Derek Lee Penwell 1965- University of Louisville Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.library.louisville.edu/etd Recommended Citation Penwell, Derek Lee 1965-, "A manifestation of all life : intersections of virtue ethics, philosophy of emotion, and philosophy of literature." (2010). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 1113. https://doi.org/10.18297/etd/1113 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. This title appears here courtesy of the author, who has retained all other copyrights. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A MANIFESTATION OF ALL LIFE: INTERSECTIONS OF VIRTUE ETHICS, PHILOSOPHY OF EMOTION, AND PHILOSOPHY OF LITERATURE By Derek Lee Penwell B.R.E., Great Lakes Christian College, 1987 M.A.R., Emmanuel School of Religion, 1990 M.Div., Lexington Theological Seminary D.Min., Lexington Theological Seminary A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Louisville in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Self-Consciousness, Embodiment, and the Narrativizing Self
    N o t e s 1 Self-Consciousness, Embodiment, and the Narrativizing Self 1 . Fitzgerald critiques contemporary metaphysics and argues for physiological psychology as a basis for future metaphysics. 2 . Other key meditations on this methodological issue include James 1884, Dewey 1886, Bain 1893, and Ladd 1913. 3 . Rick Rylance offers an excellent account of associationism in Victorian Psychology and British Culture, 1850–1880. 4 . I n Popular Fiction and Brain Science in the Late Nineteenth Century, Ann Stiles describes the biological determinism of late-nineteenth-century neurology, particularly in relation to cerebral localization. Stiles explores how selected Gothic romances reacted to this determinism. 5 . By 1903, Ladd felt that psycho-physical parallelism had been dominant “a decade or two ago” (374). He emphasized the complexity of the stream of con- sciousness, and emphasizes a “real dynamical connexion” between “observed changes, produced by other things upon the thing-like body, [and] . changes in self-conscious states” (376). 6 . Others wondered in the pages of MIND , “Is Bergson’s Philosophy Monistic?” (Radhakrishnan 332). 7 . Chapter 3 of this study features and extended discussion of Joyce’s engagement with Bergson. See pages 79–80. 8 . Behaviorism, which became the dominant theoretical approach in American psychology, rejected introspection (and the problem of perspectives) altogether. As a methodology, behaviorism has infamous limitations while also providing some useful insight. 9 . The standard analogue of this is from chemistry: when you combine carbon atoms in a certain way, you get coal; in another, diamond; in still another, graphite. In this view, the properties of coal, diamond, and graphite could not be predicted by the properties of the atom.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Introduction to Philosophy of Psychedelics (Oxford University
    Introduction to Philosophy of Psychedelics (Oxford University Press, 2021) Chris Letheby Please quote from published version. 1 Introduction The unacceptability of psychedelic therapy… stems in part at least from this fundamental empirical fact: Through the psychedelic experience persons tend to accept beliefs which are at variance with the usual conception of the “scientific world view.” Willis Harman, ‘The Issue of the Consciousness Expanding Drugs’. Something very strange is happening in psychiatry. Clinicians and researchers are becoming increasingly interested in a “new” experimental treatment, with some suggesting it might herald a “new paradigm” in the treatment of disorders such as anxiety, depression, and addiction (Nichols et al. 2017, Schenberg 2018). If promising initial results are borne out, this new treatment may significantly outperform existing pharmacological and psychological therapies in terms of rapidity and efficacy. And yet this treatment has a number of properties that, from the standpoint of mainstream philosophy and science, can only be described as extremely weird. First, although it is a drug treatment, there is no daily dosing regimen of the kind familiar from existing antidepressant and antipsychotic medications. Patients receive one, or very few, doses of the drug—albeit with considerable interpersonal support and preparation—and then, in successful cases, their symptoms dramatically decrease for many months; no re-dosing required. Second, although it is in some sense a drug treatment, it’s far from clear that the drug itself is the direct cause of clinical improvement. Rather, it seems that the drug is merely a catalyst for a brief but intense conscious experience, and it is this experience that causes therapeutic effects.
    [Show full text]
  • Selfhood and the Metaphysics of Altruism
    Selfhood and the Metaphysics of Altruism A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI¢I AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY MAY 2017 By Kevin Perry Maroufkhani Dissertation Committee: Arindam Chakrabarti, Chairperson Ron Bontekoe George Tsai Peter Hershock Sai Bhatawadekar ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am indebted to my family, particularly, Rosanne Perry, Dariush Maroufkhani, and Roya Dennis for their moral support and stubborn belief that I could accomplish this project despite all the obstacles I created for myself. I would like to acknowledge my chair, Dr. Arindam Chakrabarti, for the breadth and vivacity of his philosophical imagination, which has continued to challenge me, and nudge me out of complacency and inevitable philosophical naps. His analytical rigor, teaching-presence, and facility in world philosophy is a testament to what is possible in the field of global philosophical discourse. I am grateful for the many hours of selfless instruction he provided, and the fertile ideas cultivated in his classrooms. I would like to acknowledge Dr. Ron Bontekoe, who has always challenged me in the true spirit of a philosophical friend. Dr. Bontekoe has been a careful and caring academic advisor, and, in the courses I’ve taken with him, has never let me off the hook. He does not mince words, and because of the background depth he has provided in hermeneutics, biology, and theoretical ethics, he has greatly benefited this project. I would like to acknowledge Dr. Peter Hershock, who continually reminds me that a hermeneutical lens can make or break the credibility, rigor and sensitivity of cross-cultural conversation.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Philosophy of the Self the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy
    Ancient Philosophy of the Self The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 64 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, Princeton University RICHARD SORABJI, University of London Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Thomas-Institut, Universität zu Köln ROGER ARIEW, University of South Florida E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University of Waterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University PAUL HOFFMAN, University of California, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, Northwestern University, Evanston ALAIN DE LIBERA, Université de Genève JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Università degli Studi di genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN WOOD, Stanford University For other titles published in this series, go to www.springer.com/series/6608 Pauliina Remes • Juha Sihvola Editors Ancient Philosophy of the Self Editors Pauliina Remes Juha Sihvola Uppsala University Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies Sweden University of Helsinki and Finland University of Helsinki Finland ISBN 978-1-4020-8595-6 e-ISBN 978-1-4020-8596-3 Library of Congress Control Number: 2008928521 © 2008 Springer Science + Business Media B.V. No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work.
    [Show full text]
  • Systems Philosophy and Cybernetics
    Systems Philosophy and Cybernetics Nagib Callaos Founding President of the International Institute of Informatics and Systemics (IIIS) Abstract1 The general purpose of this article is to outline the intellectual importance and the pragmatic value of Cybernetics Philosophy. With this orientation, we will try to show the plausibility that Cybernetics, in its essence, is not new but, on the contrary, it seems consubstantial with human nature and, plausibly with Nature itself. Based on this plausibility, we will try to reason why it is intellectually important and pragmatically valuable, to foster reflections oriented to a Philosophy of Cybernetics. Consequently, we will suggest that applying systems philosophy, to be applied to Cybernetic systems, as a species. Additionally, it would be required to identify the differentia specifica of cybernetic systems and, hence, add other predicates to the notion of Cybernetics. This does not mean that we will be suggesting the use of the Aristotelian Definition and adding another definition to the overwhelming number of definitions that already exist. What we are suggesting is to use the Aristotelian notion of ‘definition’, in a more comprehensive context, i.e., not to define but to describe the notion or the idea of Cybernetics. In this context, we suggest the support of ‘Control Philosophy’ as a source to identify the differentia specifica of “cybernetics” in the context of the genus “general system”. This suggestion will emerge as we provide details regarding the con-essential nature of cybernetics to human beings and potential with Nature and its Evolution. Based on the details, we will provide regarding the above paragraph, we will suggest cybernetic relationships that tacitly, implicitly, or explicitly exist between the most important notions; which we will provide as related to the general- purpose briefly described above.
    [Show full text]
  • On Autonomy and Self-Binding Charlie Coil University of Arkansas, Fayetteville
    University of Arkansas, Fayetteville ScholarWorks@UARK Theses and Dissertations 8-2018 Abandoning the Dream of Omnipotence: On Autonomy and Self-Binding Charlie Coil University of Arkansas, Fayetteville Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd Part of the Applied Behavior Analysis Commons, Behavioral Economics Commons, and the Comparative Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Coil, Charlie, "Abandoning the Dream of Omnipotence: On Autonomy and Self-Binding" (2018). Theses and Dissertations. 2893. http://scholarworks.uark.edu/etd/2893 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UARK. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UARK. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Abandoning the Dream of Omnipotence: On Autonomy and Self-Binding A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Charles Coil, Jr. University of Arkansas Master of Arts in Philosophy, 2009 August 2018 University of Arkansas This dissertation is approved for recommendation to the Graduate Council. ______________________________ Eric Funkhouser, PhD Dissertation Director ______________________________ ______________________________ Jacob Adler, PhD Tom Senor, PhD Committee Member Committee Member Abstract I offer a prolegomenon to the philosophical study of a uniquely human activity—the self- binding act. This philosophical interest directly connects with the Enlightenment project of centralizing personal autonomy and individual freedom as primary values of personhood. Self- binding represents an easily referenced action that introduces a possible clash between autonomy and freedom on the one hand seen as in conflict with other ancient basic human values like self- control and avoiding akrasia.
    [Show full text]
  • Ego-Splitting and the Transcendental Subject. Kant's Original Insight And
    Ego-Splitting and the Transcendental Subject. Kant’s Original Insight and Husserl’s Reappraisal Marco Cavallaro Abstract In this paper, I contend that there are at least two essential traits that com- monly define being an I: self-identity and self-consciousness. I argue that they bear quite an odd relation to each other in the sense that self-consciousness seems to jeopardize self-identity. My main concern is to elucidate this issue within the range of the transcendental philosophies of Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. In the first section, I shall briefly consider Kant’s own rendition of the problem of the Ego- splitting. My reading of the Kantian texts reveals that Kant himself was aware of this phenomenon but eventually deems it an unexplainable fact. The second part of the paper tackles the same problematic from the standpoint of Husserlian phenom- enology. What Husserl’s extensive analyses on this topic bring to light is that the phenomenon of the Ego-splitting constitutes the bedrock not only of his thought but also of every philosophy that works within the framework of transcendental thinking. Keywords Kant, Immanuel · Husserl, Edmund · Ego-splitting · Transcendental philosophy · Subjectivity · Self-consciousness 1 Introduction There are two essential traits that, taken together, provide us with a general defini- tion of being an I: self-identity and self-consciousness.1 The first is straightforwardly a necessary condition. Any object whatsoever must be identical with itself to be thinkable or, more generally speaking, experienceable. Even a squared circle must be identical with itself if I state its nonexistence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science of Self, Mind and Body
    Open Journal of Philosophy 2012. Vol.2, No.3, 171-178 Published Online August 2012 in SciRes (http://www.SciRP.org/journal/ojpp) http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2012.23026 The Science of Self, Mind and Body Sung Jang Chung Morristown-Hamblen Healthcare System, Morristown, USA Email: [email protected] Received April 30th, 2012; revised May 29th, 2012; accepted June 12th, 2012 A relationship among self, mind and body in humans is still not clearly known in philosophy and science because of lack of human data that would enable to objectively explain it. Teachings related to their rela- tionship in religions have been given to humanity in general in terms of subjective words. Consequently, philosophers and scientists have been investigating to find objective proofs related to their relationship. The author proposed a theory in his book (2009) that there are in a human individual two selves, one, the inner self (the true self) and one, the physical self (the false self) that coexist in one individual person. McGonigal (2012) published her book in which she described two minds or two selves in one human in- dividual, naming them “I WILL” and “I WANT” self on the basis of extensive studies on adult subjects. More recent researches in neuroscience using functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) discovered that the prefrontal cortex of the human brain performs self-control, emotion regulation and guiding be- haviors with morality, future goals and rules. The author compared characteristic aspects of the inner and physical selves of Chung with the “I WILL” and “I WANT” selves of McGonigal.
    [Show full text]
  • Situating the Elusive Self of Advaita Veda¯Nta
    8 Situating the Elusive Self 1 of Advaita Veda¯nta CHAKRAVARTHI RAM-PRASAD I. Introduction: Advaita and the Question of What is Denied When Self is Denied In this essay, I will explore some ambiguities concerning what it is to affirm or deny the self, through the view of the Hindu school of Advaita Veda¯nta on the nature of the ‘I’ and its relationship to the reflexivity of conscious- ness. In particular, I will seek to situate this elusive self between my understanding of Dan Zahavi’s notion of the minimal self (Zahavi 2005; 2009; and this volume) and one reading of the significance of Thomas Metzinger’s brief but provocative comparisons of his denial of self with Advaita and Buddhism (Metzinger 2003: 549–50; 566). As Zahavi (like others in this volume) observes in Section 4 of his essay, the boundaries between self and no-self theories depend on what the self is taken to be. Exposition of Buddhist denials of self in this volume range from Siderits’ uncompromising reductionism all the way to Albahari’s defence of a unitary and perspectival witness consciousness, which Zahavi points out appears to preserve many of the defining characteristics of theories of self. So it is clear that in the classical Indian traditions, within Buddhism itself, what it means to deny self is a highly disputed matter. So it is with the Hindu school of Advaita. As both Fasching’s paper and mine show, the Advaitic assertion of self is not a straightforward matter, for other senses of self are denied by them that look intuitively necessary for a theory of self.
    [Show full text]