<<

& Volume 11, Article 9, 2018 https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.11.9

This is an early access version of

Lassiter, Daniel. 2018. Complex sentential operators refute unrestricted Sim- plification of Disjunctive Antecedents. Semantics and Pragmatics 11(9). https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.11.9.

This version will be replaced with the final typeset version in due course. Note that page numbers will change, so cite with caution.

©2018 Daniel Lassiter This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/). early access

Complex sentential operators refute unrestricted Simplification of Disjunctive Antecedents*

Daniel Lassiter Stanford University

Abstract There is a longstanding debate about the status of the principle Simpli- fication of Disjunctive Antecedents (SDA), according to which a counterfactual with a syntactically disjunctive antecedent [(φ ∨ ψ) > χ] entails a conjunction of counterfactuals [(φ > χ) ∧ (ψ > χ)]. This principle is highly intuitive for most examples that have been considered, but it has also been claimed to be subject to empirical counter-examples. However, there are promising pragmatic explanations for the currently known counter-examples, which have led several authors to argue in recent work that SDA is unrestrictedly valid after all. This short piece introduces new data involving sentential operators that impose both upper and lower bounds on confidence, frequency, etc., such as likely but not certain, there is an exactly n% probability, and usually but not always. These examples show clearly that SDA is not valid tout court. While SDA-supporting interpretations do exist and require an explanation, every theory of counterfactuals also requires an explanation of examples that can only be read in a way that does not support SDA.

Keywords: counterfactuals, conditionals, disjunction, pragmatics

1 Simplification of Disjunctive Antecedents: Detractors and defenders

Lewis’s (1973) semantics for counterfactuals does not validate the principle that Nute(1975) labels ‘Simplification of Disjunctive Antecedents’ (SDA). Using > to represent the counterfactual connective, I will define SDA as the claim that counterfactuals with the form of (1a) entail (1b).1 (1) a. (φ ∨ ψ) > χ b. (φ > χ) ∧ (ψ > χ) Nute(1975) and Fine(1975) object to Lewis’ semantics that SDA is intuitively valid in examples like (2) (slightly modified from Nute).

* Many thanks to Josh Dever and three anonymous reviewers for extremely helpful comments that helped me to improve and streamline this squib. 1 Note that the principle is sometimes given a stronger formulation according to which (1a) is equivalent to (1b). I will only be concerned with the weaker version, which is enough to generate the problems I will discuss. early access 2 2017. Santorio 2006, Rooij van 2003, Bennett 1984, em ob ruln entailment. troubling a be to seems (5b) harmless, is (5a) While hte oueasnl-o obymdlzditrrtto.Iwl o otruhtevrosoptions various the through go not will I interpretation. doubly-modalized or singly- a use to whether Op eatc,teeifrne ol o otruhfrsnecswt ooetoeao fthe if operator overt no with sentences for through go not would inferences these semantics, (1991b) gv the give Inwagen van & McKay valid. not is SDA that argue 1977) ( Inwagen van a. (3) (2) netitdy n testa ont sr hudb aeu oesr htterfvrdter is 2. theory section favored in their SDA introduced that validate data ensure that the to theory of careful restrictor sense be the make should of to Users variants able not. are do as there that such that others note choices, and simply semantic unrestrictedly, will and but syntactic space, of this in number concerned, a are on operators depend complex Where and theory. equally complex restrictor apply are the then a predictions of would using variants SDA the or these of source among validity ordering choice the empty the around an to dialectic requiring classical by The example, operator. for silent — do different they which in epistemic theory of restrictor force the has operator silent of semantics the of details the on LF but the with sentence a whether con- (possibly ask for a to syntax restricts question restrictor conditional the a a reframe choose of we antecedent if the operator affected where silent) much 1991a), Kratzer not 1975, are (Lewis paper ditionals this in discussed issues 1980, The Nute example, for see, valid: unrestrictedly not is Axis. SDA the that with evidence fought as have cited would it form Axis the the with with Examples fought had Spain If a. (5) (4) (4): in counter-example apparent Ellis 1975, Nute example, for see, present: the Warmbr to the 1977, topic from al. the authors et on many work by way. of endorsed the straightforward days explicitly any of been early in explanation has predict and clear not much-discussed a does is provide theory SDA would Lewis’ (3). (1) which in (2), of conditionals of the validity bizarreness of the conjunction bizarre, the is (2) (3b) from Since infer to reasonable is it Plainly, [ φ MKy& McKay and (1976) Loewer above, noted discussion early the on up Following ][ χ Axis. fSanhdfuh ihteAi rteAle twudhv ogtwt the with fought have would it Allies the or Axis the with fought had Spain If cold crop. grow bumper to a were have sun would the we summer, or of summer end this the weather before good have to were we If I pi a ogtwt h lisi ol aefuh ihteAxis. the with fought have would it Allies the with fought had Spain If b. b. ] and ftesnwr ogo odbfr h n fsme,w ol aea have would we summer, of end the before cold crop. grow bumper to were sun bumper the a have If would we summer, this weather crop. good have to were we If Op Op [ ψ ][ n hr sn cutrata connective’ ‘counterfactual no is there and χ ] hte hsifrnecmsotde o eedo h ytxdirectly, syntax the on depend not does out comes inference this Whether . 2017. Willer 2014, Starr 2012, Fine 1981, od ¯ ( φ ∨ ψ ) Op > φ Kratzer’s in example, For modeled. is restriction how and must where , oee,oecudesl eieavrato the of variant a devise easily could one However, . 2 φ and Op ψ r noptbe r frequently are incompatible, are [ φ e se per ∨ ψ ][ nta ae ejs edto need just we case, that In . χ ] nal etne ihLFs with sentences entails 2 ailLassiter Daniel early access is not relevantly possible. Suppose also, 3 is not relevantly possible — that is, that (6) is false. Spain fights with the Allies ¯ od , 1981 Starr 2014, Willer ;2017 see also Fine 2012 for a related diagnosis). theories have the additional burden of explaining why the crop At this point, adopting a theory that validates SDA globally seems very attractive. In sum, McKay & van’s Inwagen ) (1977 purported counter-examples to SDA However, there is a very promising explanation for this apparent failure of example (2) and similar sentences are felt to be false. For them, (2) has two readings: case, the net resultinterpretation is that that sentences generates like onlysupporting (2) the interpretation are reasonable that ambiguous also inference between generates incall the a (3a), theories bizarre non-SDA in (3b). and this For an general a SDA- class brief “ambiguity label, theories”. I will readings arise. Some theories invokesupporting optional disjunctive covert antecedents operators into that ones thatthat convert receive SDA- does a not classical support interpretation SDA2017). (e.g., Others Alonso-Ovalle have2009, positedCiardelli more etreadings or al. less from2018 , complicatedSantorio a pragmatic theory derivations that, ofinterpretation SDA like (e.g., Loewer Lewis’,1976, doesNute not1980, supportBennett it2003, semantically Franke 2011). on In any either room for theories of counterfactuals that do validate SDA. Such a theory would explainother why examples SDA in readings a are very prominent straightforward inmore way. Theories (2) work that to and do do. so not First, many validate SDA they have must explain how both SDA-supporting and classical Example (4) conveys exactly what weand would (b) expect counterfactuals it with to impossible convey, antecedents if are (a) trivially SDA true. is valid, are often cited as showingfact that provide the an principle airtight is case not for this valid. conclusion, However, they and do the not empirical in situation leaves Likewise, someone who had little backgroundjustified knowledge in about inferring the from war (4) would that be 7) ( (7) is true. SpainFar would from never being have a fought refutation with of the SDA, Allies. then, McKay & van’s Inwagen 1977) ( example is presumably aware ofrender Spain’s the fascist possibility leanings of during alliance with the the WWII Allies period, against which Hitler exceedingly remote. Suppose that are vacuously true. Insince that both case, are both trivially true. counterfactuals So, in if (5) SDA is are valid unobjectionable, then (4)(6) should simply imply that Spain might have fought with the Allies. Complex sentential operators refute unrestricted SDA SDA, which has led some authors to argue that SDA is unrestrictedly valid after all Spain fights with the Allies This prediction appears to be correct. Someone whose knowledge supports (4) (4) is beginning to look like surprising confirmation of this principle’s validity. (Warmbr with (1973)Lewis and many others, that counterfactuals with impossible antecedents early access r rval as.So, false. trivially are (9) in entailments purported the of both but sensible, is (8) a. 9). ( in counterfactuals the of (9) both entail would (8) valid, were SDA If make also theories ambiguity that way the in such interpreted why naturally sensible of not a explanation are (2) additional examples its assigning an with require of theories possibility reading Ambiguity the SDA-supporting interpretation? ignoring ways false while two the with (3b), on faced entailment uncharitably listener bizarre a would (2) more why is interpret But weather cold). to growing good sun that the knowledge than background contextually plausible the is (against that (3a) interpretation true to a equivalent and interpretation, SDA-supporting false, a (10) would (12). SDA and Likewise, (11) ( 10b). for or inferences (10a) bizarre entailments clearly generate unsatisfiable (10) the example, have For etc. not generality, does frequency, probability, on bound lower a general. in valid be cannot SDA consequent. the in (8) does operators ( 4) complex (1977) certain Inwagen’s with van examples clever & to The McKay extend appeared. against not has principle it the than of SDA defense for pragmatic worse valid is generally situation not empirical is the However, SDA that show operators Complex 2 (4). it example lore, (1977) to Inwagen’s contrary van not and, & is (2); McKay ambiguity like by the examples refuted why in not way of is posits charitable account that maximally additional one a an than in need complex resolved not less does strictly it is ambiguity; theory an a Such SDA. validates simply (3b). false plainly the of entails explanation it immediate (2): an of have oddity SDA the validate that theories contrast, In available. h rbe xed oohrsneta prtr htips oha pe and upper an both impose that operators sentential other to extends problem The that theory a favor to seems situation empirical and theoretical the point this At fSanhdfuh ihteAi rteAle tslkl,btntcran that certain, not but likely, Axis. it’s the Allies with the fought or have Axis would the it with fought had Spain If fJmhdbto r3 hr sa xcl 0 rbblt hth would he that probability 50% exactly an is there 3. 3, on or bet 1 have on bet of had roll the Jim on If 5.] Betting chose them. he among indifferent die, is a but numbers, odd likes [Jim b. fSanhdfuh ihteAle tslkl,btntcran hti would it that certain, not Axis. but likely, the it’s with Allies fought the have with fought would had it Spain that If certain, not Axis. but likely, the it’s with Axis fought the have with fought had Spain If 4 ailLassiter Daniel early access plausible application of SDA 5 prima facie If a classical musician switchednot to necessarily playing — jazz switch she to would playing normally jazz. If — a but classical musician switched to playingnot hip-hop necessarily she — would switch normally to — but playing jazz. If Jim had bet onbet 1 on there 3. is an exactly 50%If probability Jim that had he bet would on have bet 3 on there 3. is an exactly 50% probability that he would have If it were to rain in NewIf Mexico, it it were would to usually snow — in but New not Mexico, it always — would rain. usually — but not always — rain. tain — that it rained. If a person isally — driven but not by always — starvation choose to to eat eat insects. either dirt or insects, they usu- [Jim likes odd numbers, but ishe indifferent bet.] among them. We don’tIf know Jim how bet on 1 or 3 there isIf an it exactly rained 50% probability or that snowed he in bet New on Mexico 3. last week, it’s likely — but not cer- a. If a classical musician switchedmally — to but not playing necessarily jazz — switch or to hip-hop playinga. she jazz. would nor- b. a. b. If it were to rain or snow in New Mexico, it would usually —b. but not al- ways — rain. The same problems apply to the These observations refute theories on which SDA is unrestrictedly valid. They implicature-based account. (16) Indicative conditionals may alsoHowever, this default is to apparently due an to interpretation semantic ambiguity that or licenses pragmatic enrichment, SDA. as intuitive interpretation of (13), none of16) (14)-( SDA entail would the assign conditionals them. that indicative (13) If you eat sea(14) cucumber or dung beetles you’ll get a stomachache. (15) are consistent with ambiguitydisjunctive theories, antecedents where are counterfactuals semantically withreading or syntactically which pragmatically validates SDA ambiguous and between one which a does not. to indicative conditionals. While indicative SDA would correctly characterize the (12) (11) Complex sentential operators refute unrestricted SDA we would expect (for example) from Alternative/ or from an early access miut hoisoeadtie xlnto fwa rcsl swrong. is precisely what of explanation detailed a owe pragmatically theories something Ambiguity be also must there suggest, (1980) Nute (1976), Loewer As con- interpretation sensible a has that (2)/(17) like sentence a with presented when okwl enee odfn uhapamtcacuti ealadt ofotit confront to and detail in examples. account of pragmatic range a wider such a defend with to needed be will work idct hteeyter fcutratasms eable be must counterfactuals of theory every that indicate 2 Section in data The a. (18) over theories ambiguity for lower-bounding and SDA support upper- validate compelling of that sense theories provides make result to able This is that operators. that and antecedents SDA disjunctive support with not counterfactuals does for interpretation an generate to Conclusion 3 irel,Iao imnZag&LcsCaplin 08 w wthsi the in switches Two 2018. Champollion. Lucas & Zhang Linmin Ivano, Ciardelli, 2003. Francis. Jonathan Bennett, disjunction. and correlatives, Counterfactuals, 2009. Luis. Alonso-Ovalle, more However, Quality. by ( 18b) and by Manner, (17) by of out would ruled interpretations bizarreness is its the (18a) of explain infelicitous: both can be why reasons we motivated out, independently works to explanation appealing of style this If (19) cold? growing the sun’s simpler, without the a content about is this (to detour conveys there pointless why that when — (18a), (17) (19) — in in available rigamarole expression meaning the unambiguous the choose she communicate would to Grice) intended paraphrase speaker the If Manner. (18a). interpretation sensible the convey to (17) sentence of use the about defective (17) interpreter an interpretation? would bizarre (18b), the interpretation on bizarre fixate a and (18a) to equivalent textually oapa in appear To hoyo onefcul:Asuyo rt odtoaiyadmnmlchange. minimal and conditionality truth of study A counterfactuals: of theory Oxford. Press Philosophy and tics of Maxim (1989) Grice’s to related is explanation the that is suspicion My Why, though. remains, 1 Section in mentioned theories ambiguity for puzzle One fw eet aego ete hssme,w ol aeabme crop. bumper a have would we summer, this weather good have to were we If cold crop. grow bumper to a were have sun would the we summer, or of summer end this the weather before good have to were we If ( b. odweather good odweather good igitc n Philosophy and Linguistics . https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-009-9059-0 207–244. 32(2). > > otcourt tout uprcrop bumper uprcrop bumper hlspia ud oconditionals to guide philosophical A . 6 ) ∧ . ( u rw cold grows sun > uprcrop bumper ailLassiter Daniel Clarendon . Linguis- ) early access , , 6(1). Hand- Formal Journal of Journal of The Journal of Journal of Semantics Journal of Philosophy 84(1). 451–458. https: Journal of Philosophical Mind . . Harvard University Press. Journal of Philosophical Logic 4. 1–82. . https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.4.1 7 31(5). 353–356. https://doi.org/10.1007/ 10(2). 267–289. https://doi.org/10.1007/ . Harvard University Press. . Counterfactuals , 178–188. Cambridge University Press. , 387–439. Springer. 9(2). 153–166. . https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00247746 Studies in the Way of Counterfactuals Philosophical studies Semantics and Pragmatics 73(16). 531–537. . https://doi.org/10.2307/2025717 72(21). 773–778. . https://doi.org/10.2307/2025340 Journal of Philosophy Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung 43(6). 1019–1064. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-013-9300-8. ¯ od, Ken. 1981. Counterfactuals and substitution of equivalent antecedents. BF00248853. book of Philosophical Logic 23(4). 383–402. . https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffl004 appear in BF01873862. semantics of natural language antecedents. 651–656. Walter de Gruyter. 639–650. Walter de Gruyter. conversation. 355–357. . https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00262069 Logic . //doi.org/10.1093/mind/LXXXIV.1.451 Philosophy Philosophical Logic Philosophy (eds.), (eds.), world semantics for counterfactual logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic 109(3). 221–246. . https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil201210938 Starr, William B. 2014. A uniform theory of conditionals. Warmbr van Rooij, Robert. 2006. Free choice counterfactual donkeys. Santorio, Paolo. 2017. Alternatives and truthmakers in conditional semantics. To Nute, Donald. 1975. Counterfactuals and theNute, similarity Donald. of 1980. worlds. Conversational scorekeeping and conditionals. Nute, Donald. 1984. Conditional logic. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenther (eds.), Loewer, Barry. 1976. Counterfactuals with disjunctive antecedents. McKay, Thomas & Peter van Inwagen. 1977. Counterfactuals with disjunctive Kratzer, Angelika. 1991b. Modality. In Arnim von Stechow & Dieter Wunderlich Lewis, David. 1973. Lewis, David. 1975. Adverbs of quantification. In Edward L. Keenan (ed.), Franke, Michael. 2011. Quantity implicatures, exhaustive interpretation, and rational Grice, H. Paul. 1989. Kratzer, Angelika. 1991a. Conditionals. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich Fine, Kit. 1975. Critical Notice: Fine, Kit. 2012. Counterfactuals without possible worlds. Complex sentential operators refute unrestricted SDA Ellis, Brian, Frank Jackson & Robert Pargetter. 1977. An objection to possible- early access 5 er al ulig460 Building Mall, Serra 450 [email protected] 94305 CA Stanford, University Stanford Linguistics of Department Lassiter Daniel choice. free with Simplifying 2017. Malte. Willer, . https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9437-5 8 Topoi nieFrt 1–14. First. Online ailLassiter Daniel