Paradox in Thought and Natural Language by Ethan

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Paradox in Thought and Natural Language by Ethan Paradox in Thought and Natural Language By Ethan J Jerzak A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in Charge Professor John MacFarlane, Co-chair Professor Seth Yalcin, Co-chair Professor John Steel Summer 2019 Paradox in Thought and Natural Language This dissertation is entirely the original work of the author. Copyright Ethan J Jerzak 2019 Abstract Paradox in Thought and Natural Language by Ethan J Jerzak Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professor John MacFarlane, co-chair Professor Seth Yalcin, co-chair Professor John Steel Around 600BC, Epimenides, a Cretan apparently discontented with the honesty of his compatriots, lamented that all Cretans are liars. Together with a few innocent assumptions, well-entrenched principles of logic entail that Epimenides’ lamentation cannot be true, and yet cannot be untrue—a flat contradiction. What’s gone wrong? In this dissertation, I argue that the source of the problem has been misdiagnosed as one about language (especially formal languages). The problem runs deeper, and stems from the structure of thought itself. The dissertation proceeds in two main stages. The first stage (Chapter 2) makes the case that that the intuitions that underlie the paradoxes come from natural languages, not from formal/mathematical ones. The Liar and related paradoxes are generally presented as constraints on the latter. Their lesson, the story goes, is that no formal theory strong enough to represent the primitive recursive functions can include a satisfactory truth predicate. I argue that it’s our natural-language competence with the truth predicate that underlies our understanding of what ‘satisfactory’ means here, which shifts the focus of the project to natural language semantics. In this domain, it’s tempting to think (and many have thought) that the problem with Epimenides’ utterance is that it fails to express a proposition, and this failure explains 1 why we have trouble assigning it a truth-value. Or, perhaps it does express a proposition, but not the one that it seems to express. Or, perhaps it can express a proposition, but which proposition it expresses depends on context. I argue that all such responses fail, in part because they cannot make sense of related attitude attributions. I can believe or disbelieve Epimenides, which wouldn’t be possible if his utterance didn’t express the proposition it seems to express. In the second stage, I argue that such paradoxes arise, not from the language/thought interface, but rather from thought itself. The first step in this argument concerns knowledge attributions (Chapter 3), where I develop and defend a novel solution to the Knower paradox. Then I move from attitude attributions to attitudes themselves (Chapter 4). Just as sentential truth and knowledge predicates gives rise to paradoxical sentences, seem- ingly innocent combinations of beliefs and desires give rise to paradoxical propositions—even when those beliefs and desires are not expressed in lan- guage. The possibility of such pathological combinations isn’t accounted for by any extant theory of mental content, and, I argue, provides support for a non-classical theory. Finally (Chapter 5) I consider an objection to these putative combinations of desires. I introduce what I call advisory desire reports, which seem to exhibit the radically externalist behavior that the previous chapter rejects. I conclude by oering reasons to think that the availability of these readings does not undermine the case for non-classical accounts of attitudes. 2 Acknowledgments There are many humans and institutions without which this dissertation could never have come to be. To my parents and siblings gratitude is due for myriad reasons, but especially for their politely declining to inquire too scrupulously into what graduate school in philosophy entails and portends. The greatest portion of intellectual debt I owe to the graduate community at Berkeley. Most of what I know about anything, I learned from arguments in 301 and at Wollheims. Particular (though by no means exhaustive) thanks to Adam Bradley, Melissa Fusco, Jim Hutchinson, Alex Kerr, Arc Koceruk, Richard Lawrence, Sven Neth, Emily Perry, Kirsten Pickering, Rachel Rudolph, Pia Schneider, and Umrao Sethi for particularly instructive yelling in this regard. Many people gave invaluable comments on drafts and presentations of embryonic forms of what follows. Thanks to Chloé de Canson, Wes Holliday, Hannes Leitgeb, John MacFarlane, and Seth Yalcin for comments on drafts of Chapter 3. Thanks also to audiences at Berkeley, ESSLLI, and the MCMP for entertaining presentations about it. For Chapter 4, thanks to Wes Holliday, Arc Kocurek, John MacFarlane, Sven Neth, Rachel Rudoph, and Seth Yalcin for helpful discussions and comments, and to audiences in Berkeley, San Diego, London, Barcelona, and Oxford. And for Chapter 5, thanks to Chloé de Canson, Janice Dowell, Arc Kocurek, Hannes Leitgeb, John MacFarlane, Francois Reçanati, Rachel Rudolph, and Seth Yalcin for helpful draft commenting, to an anonymous reviewer at The Journal of Philosophy for helpful comments and challenges, and to audiences at UC–Berkeley, UCL, the University of Konstanz, the Institute Jean-Nicod, and the MCMP. I’m very grateful to the DAAD, whose research grant allowed me to spend the 2015/16 academic year at the MCMP in Munich, and because of i whose two language grants I now speak passable German. Thanks to Hannes Leitgeb and the MCMP for agreeing to host me during this year; my time there was invaluable in fixing Chapter 3, and in writing the bulk of Chapter 5. And warm thanks to Catrin Campbell-Moore, Johannes Korbmacher, Hans- Christoph Kotzsch, Lavinia Picollo, Thomas Schindler, and Pia Schneider, who welcomed me into the MCMP community. I’d also like to thank the Mellon Foundation and American Council of Learned Societies, from whom I received a dissertation completion fellowship for the 2017/18 academic year. During this time I published some of the more finished parts, and wrote Chapter 4. Tons of advisers and mentors, both formal and informal, have helped me over the years to think and do philosophy better. Agnes Callard, Robert Pippin, and Jim Conant were all influential in kindling the desire to do philosophy. Without Tom Lockhart I might never have had the wherewithall to apply in the first place. At Berkeley, Hannah Ginsborg and Barry Stroud were formidable first year seminar leaders, and collectively taught me the value of slowing down. Wes Holliday provided insight and guidance in the writing of Chapter 3. Seth Yalcin, despite sternly warning me in my first year not to write a dissertation on the present topic, was otherwise a model of encouragement. And John MacFarlane was extremely helpful, both through his meticulous comments on drafts, and in being most active in reminding me that I would eventually have to turn in a dissertation. Two entities deserve special mention. First, the taco truck parked outside the Hotsy Totsy in Albany was a (sometimes alarmingly exclusive) source of nourishment during the final writing stages. And Schmidt’s Pub in Albany served as the location where the greatest number of words contained herein were actually penned. To these two establishments jointly is this dissertation dedicated. ii Contents Acknowledgments i Contents iii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Chapter 2: Liars, Propositions, and Contexts . 3 1.2 Chapter 3: Non-Classical Knowledge . 4 1.3 Chapter 4: Paradoxical Desires . 5 1.4 Chapter 5: Two Ways to Want . 5 1.5 Conclusion . 6 2 Liars, Propositions, and Contexts 7 2.1 A brief introduction to the Liar . 9 2.2 Intuitive responses . 13 2.3 Banning self-reference . 14 2.4 Failure to express a proposition . 15 2.5 Two kinds of context-based approaches . 19 2.6 Indexical truth predicate (Burge) . 19 2.7 Indexical domain of quantification over propositions (Glanzberg) . 20 2.8 Whither T-out and T-in? . 23 2.9 Two problems for this approach . 29 2.10 Upshot . 33 3 Non-Classical Knowledge 34 3.1 The Knower paradox . 34 3.2 A solution, outlined . 41 3.3 Mathematical knowledge . 52 iii Contents 3.4 The solution, evaluated: natural language . 59 3.5 Concluding thoughts: robustness, new paradoxes . 63 Appendix A . 65 Appendix B . 72 4 Paradoxical Desires 75 4.1 The paradox . 75 4.2 Responses . 77 4.3 Denying the case . 78 4.4 Intrinsic case-denying . 79 4.5 Relational case-denying . 82 4.6 Denying a principle of desire-satisfaction . 84 4.7 Non-classical thought . 87 5 Two Ways to Want? 93 5.1 Existing proposals . 97 5.2 ‘Wants’ in the consequent of conditionals . 102 5.3 Overreaction: perfect information . 106 5.4 Information-neutral desires . 110 5.5 ‘Wants’ and ‘Ought’ . 115 5.6 Whither the predictive ‘wants’? . 117 5.7 The purpose of desire attributions . 121 Appendix C . 122 6 Conclusion 130 Bibliography 135 iv Chapter 1 Introduction The Liar paradox is one of the oldest problems in philosophy. Sometime around 600BC, Epimenides, a Cretian apparently discontented with the honesty of his compatriots, lamented that all Cretians are liars. Together with a few assumptions—that liars are those who only say false things, that as a matter of fact all other Cretians are liars, and that everything Epimenides had said until then was a lie—well-entrenched principles of logic entail that Epimenides’ statement cannot be true, and yet cannot be untrue, a flat contradiction. And these assumptions are not necessary in contemporary versions of the paradox. Suppose Epimenides had simply said: (1) The sentence I’m uttering right now isn’t true. (Liar sentence) Then (1) can’t be true—if it were true, then it wouldn’t be true, since it says that it isn’t true.
Recommended publications
  • Paradox Philosophy
    Paradox Philosophy Course at Akita International University Philipp Blum, University of Lucerne, [email protected] https://philipp.philosophie.ch/teaching/paradoxes20.html Summary of the course, version of February 17, 2020 Contents 1 Administrative info 2 2 What is a paradox? 3 3 Mathematical Paradoxes 4 3.1 Things and their groupings .............................. 4 3.2 Cantor and modern set theory ............................ 4 3.3 Frege’s definition of number and Russell’s paradox ................. 6 4 Physical Paradoxes 7 4.1 Zeno’s paradoxes .................................... 7 4.2 Not easily solved by the modern calculus ....................... 9 4.3 Whitehead’s lesson: becoming is not continuous ................... 9 4.4 Russell’s lesson: the at-at theory of motion ..................... 10 4.5 Black’s lesson: the problem of hypertasks ...................... 11 4.6 Background 1: the line and the points ........................ 11 4.7 Background 2: the metaphysics of persistence and the problem of change . 12 5 Semantic Paradoxes 13 5.1 Truth and Falsity .................................... 13 5.2 The Liar ......................................... 14 5.3 The Strengthened Liar ................................. 15 5.4 A Spicy Curry ..................................... 15 5.5 Having fun with liars and curries ........................... 16 5.6 The Sorites paradox .................................. 17 6 Paradoxes of Rationality 18 6.1 Surprise Exam ..................................... 18 6.2 Prisoners’ Dilemma ..................................
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes Situations That Seems to Defy Intuition
    Paradoxes Situations that seems to defy intuition PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Tue, 08 Jul 2014 07:26:17 UTC Contents Articles Introduction 1 Paradox 1 List of paradoxes 4 Paradoxical laughter 16 Decision theory 17 Abilene paradox 17 Chainstore paradox 19 Exchange paradox 22 Kavka's toxin puzzle 34 Necktie paradox 36 Economy 38 Allais paradox 38 Arrow's impossibility theorem 41 Bertrand paradox 52 Demographic-economic paradox 53 Dollar auction 56 Downs–Thomson paradox 57 Easterlin paradox 58 Ellsberg paradox 59 Green paradox 62 Icarus paradox 65 Jevons paradox 65 Leontief paradox 70 Lucas paradox 71 Metzler paradox 72 Paradox of thrift 73 Paradox of value 77 Productivity paradox 80 St. Petersburg paradox 85 Logic 92 All horses are the same color 92 Barbershop paradox 93 Carroll's paradox 96 Crocodile Dilemma 97 Drinker paradox 98 Infinite regress 101 Lottery paradox 102 Paradoxes of material implication 104 Raven paradox 107 Unexpected hanging paradox 119 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 123 Mathematics 127 Accuracy paradox 127 Apportionment paradox 129 Banach–Tarski paradox 131 Berkson's paradox 139 Bertrand's box paradox 141 Bertrand paradox 146 Birthday problem 149 Borel–Kolmogorov paradox 163 Boy or Girl paradox 166 Burali-Forti paradox 172 Cantor's paradox 173 Coastline paradox 174 Cramer's paradox 178 Elevator paradox 179 False positive paradox 181 Gabriel's Horn 184 Galileo's paradox 187 Gambler's fallacy 188 Gödel's incompleteness theorems
    [Show full text]
  • The Π Research Network
    Version 1.0 THE Π RESEARCH NETWORK Patrick Allo, Bert Baumgaertner, Simon D’Alfonso, Nir Fresco, Federico Gobbo, Carson Grubaugh, Andrew Iliadis, Phyllis Illari, Eric Kerr, Giuseppe Primiero, Federica Russo, Christoph Schulz, Mariarosaria Taddeo, Matteo Turilli, Orlin Vakarelov, Hector Zenil. THE PHILOSOPHY OF INFORMATION AN INTRODUCTION T H E Π RESEARCH NETWORK The Philosophy of Information An Introduction The Philosophy of Information - An Introduction by The Π Research Network is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License. THE PHILOSOPHY OF IN F O R M A T I O N — A N INTRODUCTION Table of Contents Table of Contents 1 List of Figures 5 PREFACE 6 CONTRIBUTORS 7 Part I: Introductory material 8 1. A QUICK HISTORY OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF INFORMATION 9 1.1 Introduction 9 1.2 Turing’s basic idea 10 1.3 Shannon’s basic idea 12 1.4 Extension of the concepts 14 1.5 Cybernetics 15 1.6 Dretske 18 1.7 French Philosophy of Information 21 1.8 Conclusion 26 1.9 Exercises 26 1.10 Further reading 27 2. WHAT IS THE PHILOSOPHY OF INFORMATION TODAY? 28 2.1 Introduction 28 2.2 The information revolution alters our self-understanding 29 2.3 The philosophy of information as a field 31 2.4 Open and closed questions 33 2.5 The idea of a Level of Abstraction (LoA) 36 2.6 The definition of a level of abstraction 37 2.7 The implications of LoAs 39 2.8 Exercises 41 2.9 Further reading 42 3. NATURALISED INFORMATION 43 3.1 Semantic vs.
    [Show full text]
  • List of Paradoxes 1 List of Paradoxes
    List of paradoxes 1 List of paradoxes This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. The grouping is approximate: Paradoxes may fit into more than one category. Because of varying definitions of the term paradox, some of the following are not considered to be paradoxes by everyone. This list collects only those instances that have been termed paradox by at least one source and which have their own article. Although considered paradoxes, some of these are based on fallacious reasoning, or incomplete/faulty analysis. Logic • Barbershop paradox: The supposition that if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved leads to paradoxical consequences. • What the Tortoise Said to Achilles "Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down...," also known as Carroll's paradox, not to be confused with the physical paradox of the same name. • Crocodile Dilemma: If a crocodile steals a child and promises its return if the father can correctly guess what the crocodile will do, how should the crocodile respond in the case that the father guesses that the child will not be returned? • Catch-22 (logic): In need of something which can only be had by not being in need of it. • Drinker paradox: In any pub there is a customer such that, if he or she drinks, everybody in the pub drinks. • Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an argument valid. • Horse paradox: All horses are the same color. • Lottery paradox: There is one winning ticket in a large lottery. It is reasonable to believe of a particular lottery ticket that it is not the winning ticket, since the probability that it is the winner is so very small, but it is not reasonable to believe that no lottery ticket will win.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Mathematics: Gödel's Theorem and Around. by Karlis
    1 Version released: January 25, 2015 What is Mathematics: Gödel's Theorem and Around Hyper-textbook for students by Karlis Podnieks, Professor University of Latvia Institute of Mathematics and Computer Science An extended translation of the 2nd edition of my book "Around Gödel's theorem" published in 1992 in Russian (online copy). Diploma, 2000 Diploma, 1999 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License and is copyrighted © 1997-2015 by me, Karlis Podnieks. This hyper-textbook contains many links to: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia; MacTutor History of Mathematics archive of the University of St Andrews; MathWorld of Wolfram Research. Are you a platonist? Test yourself. Tuesday, August 26, 1930: Chronology of a turning point in the human intellectua l history... Visiting Gödel in Vienna... An explanation of “The Incomprehensible Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences" (as put by Eugene Wigner). 2 Table of Contents References..........................................................................................................4 1. Platonism, intuition and the nature of mathematics.......................................6 1.1. Platonism – the Philosophy of Working Mathematicians.......................6 1.2. Investigation of Stable Self-contained Models – the True Nature of the Mathematical Method..................................................................................15 1.3. Intuition and Axioms............................................................................20 1.4. Formal Theories....................................................................................27
    [Show full text]
  • Critique of Previous Comprehensive Studies of Self-Referential Paradoxes
    Critique of Previous Comprehensive Studies of Self-referential Paradoxes YAMAMORI Maiko Kyoto University Abstract: The fact that it produces a paradox implies the possibility that a theory or a thought is not entirely rational. At the same time, the possible resolution of paradoxes suggests candidates for the conditions that may make theories or thoughts consistent. Many scholars have investigated paradoxes to find their solutions. The primary approach to a paradox is to consider each solution in turn (the one-by-one approach); studies using this approach have resulted in many diverse solutions, but it is limited by serious problems. Hence, I will adopt another approach, termed here as the comprehensive approach, to consider a general solution or solutions to all paradoxes. Here the focus will be on self-referential paradoxes. A self-referential paradox indicates a paradox that occurs when the subject of a proposition is in part the proposition itself. Further, some paradoxes are not self-referential but seem to be. To preserve the appearances of our intuition of a self-reference, I introduce a categorization of self-references into two types (with two corresponding types of accompanying paradoxes): the first is a narrow self-reference, that is, precisely a reference to itself (this matches the existing characterization). The other type is a broad self-reference or a reference to a group or groups containing itself. In this paper, first, I will examine the works of three figures, Bertrand Russell; Graham Priest; and Martin Pleitz, who take a comprehensive approach: considering the general conditions for self-referential paradoxes, analyzing them, and suggesting general solutions for them.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Paradoxes
    Introduction: Mathematical Paradoxes Intuitive approach. Until recently, till the end of the 19th century, mathematical theories used to be built in an intuitive or axiomatic way. The historical development of mathematics has shown that it is not sufficient to base theories on an intuitive understanding of their notions only. This fact became especially obvious in set theory. 1 The basic concept of a set is certainly taken from reality, for there we come across many examples of various sets, all of which are finite. But in mathematics it is also necessary to consider infinite sets, such as the set of all integers, the set of all rational numbers, the set of all segments, the set of all tri- angles. 2 Intuitively, by a set, we mean any collection of objects- for example, the set of all even integers or the set of all students in a class. The objects that make up a set are called its members (elements). Sets may themselves be members of sets for example, the set of all sets of integers has sets as its members. 3 Most sets are not members of themselves. For example the set of all students is not a member of itself, because the set of all students is not a student. However, there may be sets that do belong to themselves. For example the set of all sets. A following simple reasoning indicates that it is necessary to impose some limitations on the concept of a set. 4 Russell Paradox, 1902: Consider the set A of all those sets X such that X is not a member of X.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes in Logic and Set Theory
    MATH110 Lecturenotes–11 Paradoxes in Logic and Set Theory 1. Existence of irrational numbers. About 2.5 thousand years ago, Pythagoreans proved that √2 was irrational, which was controversial at the time. Until then it was believed that all numbers are rational, i.e. can be expressed as quotients of integers. 2. Paradox of enumeration. Which set is bigger? Before formal set theory was introduced, the notion of the size of a set had been problematic. It had been discussed by Italian mathematicians Galileo Galilei and Bernard Bolzano (17th-18th centruries), among others. Are there more as as many natural numbers as perfect squares (squares of natural numbers)? The answer is yes, because for every natural number n there is a square number n2, and likewise the other way around. The answer is no, because the squares are a proper subset of the naturals: every square is a natural number but there are natural numbers, like 2, which are not squares of natural numbers. By defining the notion of the size of a set in terms of its cardinality, the issue can be settled, as there is a bijection between the two sets involved. Georg Cantor (late 19th-early 20th centuries) invented set theory. Cantor es- tablished the importance of one-to-one correspondence between the members of two sets, defined infinite and well-ordered sets, and proved that the real num- bers are more numerous than the natural numbers. He introduced the concept of cardinality. “I see it but I don’t believe,” Cantor wrote to Dedekind after proving that the set of points of a square has the same cardinality as that of the points on just an edge of the square: the cardinality of the continuum.
    [Show full text]
  • Diagonalization and Logical Paradoxes
    DIAGONALIZATION AND LOGICAL PARADOXES DIAGONALIZATION AND LOGICAL PARADOXES By HAIXIA ZHONG, B.B.A., M.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy McMaster University © Copyright by Haixia Zhong, August 2013 DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY (2013) (Philosophy) McMaster University Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Diagonalization and Logical Paradoxes AUTHOR: Haixia Zhong, B.B.A. (Nanjing University), M.A. (Peking University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Richard T. W. Arthur NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 229 ii ABSTRACT The purpose of this dissertation is to provide a proper treatment for two groups of logical paradoxes: semantic paradoxes and set-theoretic paradoxes. My main thesis is that the two different groups of paradoxes need different kinds of solution. Based on the analysis of the diagonal method and truth-gap theory, I propose a functional-deflationary interpretation for semantic notions such as ‘heterological’, ‘true’, ‘denote’, and ‘define’, and argue that the contradictions in semantic paradoxes are due to a misunderstanding of the non-representational nature of these semantic notions. Thus, they all can be solved by clarifying the relevant confusion: the liar sentence and the heterological sentence do not have truth values, and phrases generating paradoxes of definability (such as that in Berry’s paradox) do not denote an object. I also argue against three other leading approaches to the semantic paradoxes: the Tarskian hierarchy, contextualism, and the paraconsistent approach. I show that they fail to meet one or more criteria for a satisfactory solution to the semantic paradoxes. For the set-theoretic paradoxes, I argue that the criterion for a successful solution in the realm of set theory is mathematical usefulness.
    [Show full text]
  • Vagueness and Truth
    Vagueness and Truth Mark Colyvan∗ Abstract In philosophy of logic and elsewhere, it is generally thought that similar problems should be solved by similar means. This advice is sometimes elevated to the status of a principle: the principle of uniform solution. In this paper I will explore the question of what counts as a similar problem and consider reasons for subscribing to the principle of uniform solution. 1 Introducing the Principle of Uniform Solution It would be very odd to give different responses to two paradoxes depending on minor, seemingly-irrelevant details of their presentation. For example, it would be unacceptable to deal with the paradox of the heap by invoking a multi-valued logic,L ∞, say, and yet, when faced with the paradox of the bald man, invoke a supervaluational logic. Clearly these two paradoxes are of a kind—they are both instances of the sorites paradox. And whether the sorites paradox is couched in terms of heaps and grains of sand, or in terms of baldness and the number of hairs on the head, it is essentially the same problem and therefore must be solved by the same means. More generally, we might suggest that similar paradoxes should be resolved by similar means. This advice is sometimes elevated to the status of a principle, which usually goes by the name of the principle of uniform solution. This principle and its motivation will occupy us for much of the discussion in this paper. In particular, I will defend a rather general form of this principle. I will argue that two paradoxes can be thought to be of the same kind because (at a suitable level of abstraction) they share a similar internal structure, or because of external considerations such as the relationships of the paradoxes in question to other paradoxes in the vicinity, or the way they respond to proposed solutions.
    [Show full text]
  • For Cybersecurity, Computer Science Must Rely on the Opposite of Gödel’S Results Carl Hewitt
    For Cybersecurity, Computer Science Must Rely on the Opposite of Gödel’s Results Carl Hewitt To cite this version: Carl Hewitt. For Cybersecurity, Computer Science Must Rely on the Opposite of Gödel’s Results. Symposium on Logic and Collaboration for Intelligent Applications, Mar 2017, Stanford, United States. hal-01566393v14 HAL Id: hal-01566393 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01566393v14 Submitted on 17 Oct 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Copyright Strong Types for Direct Logic Carl Hewitt http://plus.google.com/+CarlHewitt-StandardIoT This article is dedicated to Alonzo Church, Richard Dedekind, Stanisław Jaśkowski, Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Ernst Zermelo. Abstract Mathematics in this article means the precise formulation of standard mathematical theories that axiomatize the following up to a unique isomorphism: booleans, natural numbers, reals, ordinals, sets, lambda calculus procedures, and Actors. In a strongly typed mathematical theory, every proposition, term, and expression has a type where there is no universal type Any. Types are constructed bottom up from types that are categorically axiomatized.1 Strong types are extremely important in Direct Logic because they block all known paradoxes including Berry [Russell 1906], Burali-Forti [Burali-Forti 1897], Church [Church 1934], Curry [Curry 1941], Girard [Girard 1972], and Liar [Eubulides of Miletus], Löb[Löb 1955], and Russell[Russell 1902].2 Blocking known paradoxes makes Direct Logic safer for use in Intelligent Applications by preventing security holes.
    [Show full text]
  • Diplomamunka
    EÖTVÖS LORÁND TUDOMÁNYEGYETEM Bölcsészettudományi Kar DIPLOMAMUNKA Logikai paradoxonok és eldönthetetlen mondatok Logical Paradoxes and Undecidable Sentences Témavezető: Készítette: Csaba Ferenc Cheng, Ka Yue Tudományos munkatárs Logic and Theory of Science 2015 A HKR 346. § ad 76. § (4) c) pontja értelmében: „… A szakdolgozathoz csatolni kell egy nyilatkozatot arról, hogy a munka a hallgató saját szellemi terméke…” SZERZŐSÉGI NYILATKOZAT Alulírott Cheng, Ka Yue (K2VXS8) ezennel kijelentem és aláírásommal megerősítem, hogy az ELTE BTK Logic and Theory of Science angol nyelvű mesterszakján írt jelen diplomamunkám saját szellemi termékem, melyet korábban más szakon még nem nyújtottam be szakdolgozatként és amelybe mások munkáját (könyv, tanulmány, kézirat, internetes forrás, személyes közlés stb.) idézőjel és pontos hivatkozások nélkül nem építettem be. Budapest, 2015-04-15 .................................. a hallgató aláírása A nyilatkozatot a diplomamunkához kell csatolni. Acknowledgements I would like to thank my supervisor Ferenc Csaba for his useful comments and pointing out some mistakes in the draft. Despite this, the responsibility for the remaining typos and errors is mine. I would like to express my gratitude to all my teachers, especially Professor Andr´asM´at´e,Professor Istv´anN´emeti,Professor Hajnal Andr´eka, Professor P´eterMekis, Professor L´aszl´oE. Szab´o,Attila Moln´arand Zal´anGyenis, as well as everyone from the Department of Logic. This thesis would not exist without them, I am grateful for studying logic here. Last but not least, I wish to express my sincere thanks to my family for their support, and to my lovely cat Alice. Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 A Proof of G¨odelIncompleteness Theorems 2 2.1 Syntax .
    [Show full text]