Paul-Feyerabend-Against-Method.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Paul-Feyerabend-Against-Method.Pdf Against Method Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge Paul Feyerabend 1993 (third edition) Contents Preface 4 Preface to the Third Edition 6 Introduction to the Chinese Edition 10 Analytical Index 13 Introduction 16 1 20 2 24 3 27 4 33 5 37 6 48 7 56 8 65 9 71 10 83 11 85 12 97 13 99 14 106 15 110 Appendix 1 118 2 16 122 Appendix 2 152 17 155 18 167 19 172 20 182 Postscript on Relativism 193 3 Preface In 1970 Imre Lakatos, one of the best friends I ever had, cornered me at a party. “Paul,” he said, “you have such strange ideas. Why don’t you write them down? I shall write a reply, we publish the whole thing and I promise you - we shall have lots of fun.” I liked the suggestion and started working. The manuscript of my part of the book was finished in 1972 and I sentitto London. There it disappeared under rather mysterious circumstances. Imre Lakatos, wholoved dramatic gestures, notified Interpol and, indeed, Interpol found my manuscript and returned it to me. I reread it and made some final changes. In February 1974, only a few weeks afterI had finished my revision, I was informed of Imre’s death. I published my part of ourcommon enterprise without his response. A year later I published a second volume, Science in a Free Society, containing additional material and replies to criticism. This history explains the form of the book. It is not a systematic treatise; it is a letter toafriend and addresses his idiosyncrasies. For example, Imre Lakatos was a rationalist, hence rationalism plays a large role in the book. He also admired Popper and therefore Popper occurs much more frequently than his “objective importance” would warrant. Imre Lakatos, somewhat jokingly, called me an anarchist and I had no objection to putting on the anarchist’s mask. Finally, Imre Lakatos loved to embarrass serious opponents with jokes and irony and so I, too, occasionally wrote in a rather ironical vein. An example is the end of Chapter 1: “anything goes” is not a “principle” I hold - I do not think that “principles” can be used and fruitfully discussed outside the concrete research situation they are supposed to affect - but the terrified exclamation ofa rationalist who takes a closer look at history. Reading the many thorough, serious, longwinded and thoroughly misguided criticisms I received after publication of the first English edition I often recalled my exchanges with Imre; how we would both have laughed had we beenableto read these effusions together. The new edition merges parts of Against Method with excerpts from Science in a Free Society.I have omitted material no longer of interest, added a chapter on the trial of Galileo and achapter on the notion of reality that seems to be required by the fact that knowledge is part of a complex historical process, eliminated mistakes, shortened the argument wherever possible and freed it from some of its earlier idiosyncrasies. Again I want to make two points: first, that science can stand on its own feet and does not need any help from rationalists, secular humanists, Marxists and similar religious movements; and, secondly, that non-scientific cultures, procedures and as- sumptions can also stand on their own feet and should be allowed to do so, if this is the wish of their representatives. Science must be protected from ideologies; and societies, especially demo- cratic societies, must be protected from science. This does not mean that scientists cannot profit from a philosophical education and that humanity has not and never will profit from the sciences. However, the profits should not be imposed; they should be examined and freely accepted bythe parties of the exchange. In a democracy scientific institutions, research programmes, and sug- gestions must therefore be subjected to public control, there must be a separation of state and science just as there is a separation between state and religious institutions, and science should 4 be taught as one view among many and not as the one and only road to truth and reality. There is nothing in the nature of science that excludes such institutional arrangements or shows that they are liable to lead to disaster. None of the ideas that underlie my argument is new. My interpretation of scientific knowledge, for example, was a triviality for physicists like Mach, Boltzmann, Einstein and Bohr. But the ideas of these great thinkers were distorted beyond recognition by the rodents of neopositivism and the competing rodents of the church of “critical” rationalism. Lakatos was, after Kuhn, one of the few thinkers who noticed the discrepancy and tried to eliminate it by means of a complex and very interesting theory of rationality. I don’t think he has succeeded in this. But the attempt was worth the effort; it has led to interesting results in the history of science and to new insightsinto the limits of reason. I therefore dedicate also this second, already much more lonely version of our common work to his memory. Earlier material relating to the problems in this book is now collected in my Philosophical Papers.1 Farewell to Reason2 contains historical material, especially from the early history of ra- tionalism in the West and applications to the problems of today. Berkley, September 1987 1 {Preface, 1} 2 vols, Cambridge, 1981. 2 {Preface, 2} London, 1987. 5 Preface to the Third Edition Many things have happened since I first published Against Method (AM for short). There have been dramatic political, social and ecological changes. Freedom has increased - but it has brought hunger, insecurity, nationalistic tensions, wars and straightforward murder. World leaders have met to deal with the deterioration of our resources; as is their habit, they have made speeches and signed agreements. The agreements are far from satisfactory; some of them are a sham. However, at least verbally, the environment has become a world-wide concern. Physicians, developmental agents, priests working with the poor and disadvantaged have realized that these people know more about their condition than a belief in the universal excellence of science or organized re- ligion had assumed and they have changed their actions and their ideas accordingly (liberation theology; primary environmental care, etc.). Many intellectuals have adapted what they have learned at universities and special schools to make their knowledge more efficient and more humane. On a more academic level historians (of science, of culture) have started approaching the past in its own terms. Already in 1933, in his inaugural lecture at the Collège de France, Lucien Feb- vre had ridiculed writers who, “sitting at their desks, behind mountains of paper, having closed and covered their windows”, made profound judgements about the life of landholders, peasants and farmhands. In a narrow field historians of science tried to reconstruct the distant andthe more immediate past without distorting it by modern beliefs about truth (fact) and rationality. Philosophers then concluded that the various forms of rationalism that had offered their services had not only produced chimaeras but would have damaged the sciences had they been adopted as guides. Here Kuhn’s masterpiece played a decisive role.1 It led to new ideas. Unfortunately it also encouraged lots of trash. Kuhn’s main terms (“paradigm”, “revolution”, “normal science”, “prescience”, “anomaly”, “puzzle-solving”, etc.) turned up in various forms of pseudoscience while his general approach confused many writers: finding that science had been freed from the fetters of a dogmatic logic and epistemology they tried to tie it down again, this time with sociological ropes. That trend lasted well into the early seventies. By contrast there are now historians and sociologists who concentrate on particulars and allow generalities only to the extent that they are supported by sociohistorical connections. “Nature”, says Bruno Latour, referring to “science in the making” is “the consequence of [a] settlement” of “controversies”.2 Or, as I wrote in the first edition of AM: “Creation ofa thing, and creation plus full understanding of a correct idea of the thing, are very often parts of one and the same indivisible process and cannot be separated without bringing the process to a stop.”3 Examples of the new approach are Andrew Pickering, Constructing Quarks, Peter Galison, How Experiments End, Martin Rudwick, The Great Devonian Controversy, Arthur Fine, The Shaky Game 1 {Preface to the Third Edition, 1} The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago, 1962. 2 {Preface to the Third Edition, 2} Science in Action, Milton Keynes, 1987, pp. 4 and 98f. 3 {Preface to the Third Edition, 3} London, 1975, p. 26, repeated on p. 17 of the present edition - original emphasis. 6 and others.4 There are studies of the various traditions (religious, stylistic, patronage, etc.) thatin- fluenced scientists and shaped their research;5 they show the need for a far more complex account of scientific knowledge than that which had emerged from positivism and similar philosophies. On a more general level we have the older work of Michal Polanyi and then Putnam, van Fraassen, Cartwright, Marcello Pera6 and, yes, Imre Lakatos, who was sufficiently optimistic to believe that history herself - a lady he took very seriously - offered simple rules of theory evaluation. In sociology the attention to detail has led to a situation where the problem is no longer why and how “science” changes but how it keeps together. Philosophers, philosophers of biology especially, suspected for some time that there is not one entity “science” with clearly defined principles but that science contains a great variety of (high-level theoretical, phenomenological, experimental) approaches and that even a particular science such as physics is but a scattered collection of subjects (elasticity, hydrodynamics, rheology, thermodynamics, etc., etc.) each one containing contrary tendencies (example: Prandtl vs Helmholtz, Kelvin, Lamb, Rayleigh; Trues- dell vs Prandtl; Birkhoff vs “physical commonsense”; Kinsman illustrating all trends - in hydro- dynamics).
Recommended publications
  • Paul Feyerabend
    Against Method Fourth Edition Paul Feyerabend VERSO London • New York Analytical Index Being a Sketch of the Main Argument Introdnction 1 Science is an essentially anarchic enterprise: theoretical anarchism is more humanitarian and more likely to encourage progress than its law-and-order alternatives. 1 7 This is shown both by an examination of historical episodes and by an abstract analysis of the relation between idea and action. The only principle that does not inhibit progress is: anything goes. 2 13 For example, we may use hypotheses that contradict well-confirmed theories and/or well-established experimental results. We may advance science by proceeding counterinductively. 3 17 The consistency condition which demands that new hypotheses agree with accepted theories is unreasonable because it preserves the older theory, and not the better theory. Hypotheses contradicting well-confirmed theories give us evidence that cannot be obtained in any other way. Proliferation of theories is beneficial for science, while uniformity impairs its critical power. Uniformity also endangers the free development of the individual. 4 ~ There is no idea, however ancient and absurd, that is not capable of improving our knowledge. The whole history of thought is absorbed into science and is used for improving every single theory. Nor is political interference rejected. It may be needed to overcome the chauvinism of science that resists alternatives to the status quo. xxx ANAL YTICAL INDEX 5 33 No theory ever agrees with all the facts in its domain, yet it is not always the theory that is to blame. Facts are constituted by older ideologies, and a clash between facts and theories may be proof ofprogress.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defence of Falsificationism Against Feyerabend's Epistemological Anarchism Using the Example of Galilei's Observations with the Telescope
    A Defence of Falsificationism against Feyerabend's Epistemological Anarchism using the Example of Galilei's Observations with the Telescope paper for “Understanding Scientific Theory Change“ held by Karim Thébault handed in by Mario Günther in winter term 2012/13 Logic and Philosophy of Science Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy 1 Directory 1.Introduction........................................................................................................................ 3 2.Feyerabend's Epistemological Anarchism in Differentiation to Critical Rationalism.......4 2.1.Galilei's Utilisation of the Telescope and its Anarchistic Interpretation.....................5 2.2.Feyerabend's Principle of Tenacity and the Thesis of Incommensurability..............7 3.A Falsificationist Interpretation of Observations with and without the Telescope ...........8 4.Galilei's Observations en Détail....................................................................................... 10 4.1.The Explanation of Venus' Phases............................................................................ 11 4.2.The Establishment of the Irradiation Hypothesis..................................................... 13 4.3.The Moon and the Explanation of the Telescope's Functionality.............................14 4.4.Galilei's Incautious Defence of the Copernican Theory based on Reproducibility..15 5.A Rational Reconstruction of Galilei's Falsification of the Ptolemaic Theory................16 6.Evaluation.........................................................................................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Karl Feyerabend (Epistemological Anarchism)
    Theory of Knowledge Topic 13 Paul Karl Feyerabend (Epistemological Anarchism) Epistemological anarchism is an epistemological theory advanced by Austrian philosopher of science Paul Feyerabend which holds that there are no useful and exception-free methodological rules governing the progress of science or the growth of knowledge. It holds that the idea of the operation of science by fixed, universal rules is unrealistic, pernicious, and detrimental to science itself. The use of the term anarchism in the name reflected the methodological pluralism prescription of the theory, as the purported scientific method does not have a monopoly on truth or useful results. Feyerabend once famously said that because there is no fixed scientific method, it is best to have an "anything goes" attitude toward methodologies. Feyerabend felt that science started as a liberating movement, but over time it had become increasingly dogmatic and rigid, and therefore had become increasingly an ideology and despite its successes science had started to attain some oppressive features and it was not possible to come up with an unambiguous way to distinguish science from religion, magic, or mythology. He felt the exclusive dominance of science as a means of directing society was authoritarian and ungrounded. Promulgation of the theory earned Feyerabend the title of "the worst enemy of science" from his detractors. In his books Against Method and Science in a Free Society Feyerabend defended the idea that there are no methodological rules which are always used by scientists. He objected to any single prescriptive scientific method on the grounds that any such method would limit the activities of scientists, and hence restrict scientific progress.
    [Show full text]
  • Session 1: Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Hasok Chang Dept of History and Philosophy of Science University of Cambridge [email protected]
    1 Theories and Methods: Literature, Science and Medicine Event 4: Philosophy and Sociology of Science for Literature and History Students Session 1: Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Hasok Chang Dept of History and Philosophy of Science University of Cambridge [email protected] The main question for this session: • What is it that scientists do when they do science? • This offers a practice-orientated re-formulation of the familiar philosophical question about the scientific method. • (Follow-up question, to be addressed in Session 2: How is scientific work represented in scientific publications?) Some standard answers to the main question: • Inductivism • Falsificationism • Normal science (Thomas Kuhn) • Methodological anarchism (Paul Feyerabend) 1. Inductivism What is inductivism? The central inductivist idea: scientific knowledge is based on unbiased observations; such reliance on observations distinguishes science from other systems; scientists should seek to prove their theories with observations. Empiricism as the common-sense criterion of demarcation Induction in empirical science: generalisation from observations Inductivism as the ideal form of empiricism Historical location of inductivism 17th-century revolt against speculation and received doctrines Francis Bacon The ideal of certainty, proven knowledge model of mathematics attempt to meet that standard in empirical science The inductivist spirit: start with unbiased experience, and allow nothing else into your system of knowledge. 2 Induction as a demarcation criterion Hans Reichenbach : The principle of induction "determines the truth of scientific theories. To eliminate it from science would mean nothing less than to deprive science of the power to decide the truth or falsity of its theories. Without it, clearly, science would no longer have the right to distinguish its theories from the fanciful and arbitrary creations of the poet's mind." "The principle of induction is unreservedly accepted by the whole of science and ..
    [Show full text]
  • Against Method (AM for Short)
    First published by New Left Books, 1975 Revised edition published by Verso 1988 Third edition published by Verso 1993 © Paul Feyerabend 1975, 1988, 1993 All rights reserved Verso UK: 6 Meard Street, London WIV 3HR USA: 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001-2291 Verso is the imprint of New Left Books British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data available ISBN 0-86091-48 1-X ISBN 0-8609 1 -646-4 US Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data available Typeset by Keyboard Services, Luton Printed and bound in Great Britain by Biddies Ltd, Guildford and King's Lynn Contents Preface vii Preface to the Third Edition IX Introductionto the Chinese Edition 1 Analytical Index 5 Introduction 9 Parts1-20 14 Postscript on Relativism 268 Index 273 Preface In 1970 Imre Lakatos, one of the best friends I ever had, corneredme at a party. 'Paul,' he said, 'you have such strange ideas. Why don't you write them down? I shall write a reply, we publish the whole thing and I promise you - we shall have lots of fun.' I liked the suggestion and started working. The manuscript of my part of the book was finished in 1972 and I sent it to London. There it disappeared under rather mysterious circumstances. lmre Lakatos, who loved dramatic gestures, notified Interpol and, indeed, Interpol found my manu­ script and returned it to me. I reread it and made some final changes. In February 1974, only a few weeks after I had finished my revision, I was informed of Imre's death.
    [Show full text]
  • Against Methodism: a Socio-Historical Perspective of Science
    AGAINST METHODISM: A SOCIO-HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE OF SCIENCE Lukman Ademola LAWAL Abstract The received view of science is that of an objective enterprise which possesses the rational methods of inquiry which produce knowledge that is based on factual experience. Science claims to be the most reliable inquiry into the nature of reality; due to the supposed supremacy of the so called “scientific method” over those of other intellectual endeavours. However, the idea of “method” in science is itself a source of controversy to philosophers of science over the years. Indeed, scientists themselves do not bother so much about matters of methodology and as such, there is no unanimous agreement amongst scientists of the specific method which determines the techniques and procedures guiding their inquiry into nature. This notwithstanding, there have been several formulations of the scientific method as evident in the works of some scientists and philosophers of science alike over the years. The method of induction which was first explained by Aristotle was elaborated by Francis Bacon and later prepared the groundwork for logical empiricism and modern empirical science. Inductivism later became challenged by Karl Popper who declared that science only progresses by “conjecture and refutation.” This paper argues in line with the socio-historical and pragmatic conception of science advanced by the likes of Thomas Khun, Paul Feyerabend, Richard Rorty among others that the scientific enterprise is not guided by a definite method, but by certain arbitrary activities that are relative to socio-cultural backgrounds. The paper further contends that the very idea of science is not to be viewed solely from a Western perspective, which gave birth to the appellation “Western Science,” rather it should be seen in the light of the systematic attempts by every society and culture to understand, explain and predict their natural environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Central Issues in Popper's Theory of Science
    FOUR CENTRAL ISSUES IN POPPER’S THEORY OF SCIENCE By CARLOS E. GARCIA-DUQUE A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA 2002 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would not have been able to finish this project without the help and support of many persons and institutions. To begin with, 1 wish to express my deepest gratitude to Dr. Chuang Liu, chair of my doctoral committee for his continuous support and enthusiastic encouragement since the time when this dissertation was nothing more than a inchoate idea. 1 enjoyed our long discussions and benefited greatly from his advice and insightful suggestions. 1 am also very grateful to the other members of my committee, who all made significant contributions to the final product. 1 wish to thank Dr. Kirk Ludwig with whom 1 have had extensive discussions about several specific problems that 1 addressed in my dissertation. His valuable suggestions made my arguments more compelling and helped me to improve substantially Chapter 5. Dr. Robert D’Amico has posed deep questions that led me to refine and better structure my views. My conversa- tions with Dr. Robert A. Hatch about specific episodes in the history of science and their relationship with my topic were inspirational and prompted me to develop new ideas. I completed my doctoral studies with the endorsement of the Fulbright Program and the support of the Department of Philosophy at the University of Florida. 1 also want to thank the Universidad de Caldas and the Universidad de Manizales for granting me a leave of absence long enough to successfully finish this academic program.
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics and Rhetoric of Scientific Method Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
    THE POLITICS AND RHETORIC OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD AUSTRALASIAN STUDIES IN HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE General Editor: R. W. HOME, University of Melbourne Editorial Advisory Board: w. R. ALBURY, University of New South Wales B. D. ELLIS, La Trobe University L. A. FARRALL, Deakin University F. R. JEVONS, Deakin University R. JOHNSTON, University ofWollongong H. E. LE GRAND, University of Melbourne A. MUSGRAVE, University of Otago D. R. OLDROYD, University of New South Wales 1. RONAYNE, University of New South Wales J. J. C. SMART, Australian National University VOLUME 4 THE POLITICS AND RHETORIC OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD Historical Studies Edited by JOHN A. SCHUSTER I hpartment of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Wo/longong, Australia and RICHARD R. YEO School of Humanities, Griffith University, Australia D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY A MEMBER OF THE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS GROUP DORDRECHT / BOSTON / LANCASTER / TOKYO Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The Politics and rhetoric of scientific method. (Australasian studies in history and philosophy of science; 4) Includes index. Contents: The Galileo that Feyerabend missed / Alan Chalmers - Cartesian method as mythic speech / John A. Schuster - Steady as a rock­ methodology and moving continents / H. E. Le Grand - [etc.] 1. Science-Methodology. 2. Science-History. 3. Science- Philosophy. 4. Science-Social aspects. I. Schuster, John A., 1947- . II. Yeo, Richard R., 1948-- . III. Series. Q175.3.P65 1986 502.8 86--6578 ISBN-13: 978-94-010-8527-4 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-4560-9 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-4560-9 Puhlished by D. Reidel Puhlishing Company, P.O.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemological Anarchism Meets Epistemic Voluntarism: Feyerabend’S Against Method and Van Fraassen’S the Empirical Stance FORTHCOMING Martin Kusch
    1 Epistemological Anarchism Meets Epistemic Voluntarism: Feyerabend’s Against Method and van Fraassen’s The Empirical Stance FORTHCOMING Martin Kusch §1. Introduction In this paper I shall compare and contrast central themes of Paul Feyerabend’s best- known work, Against Method (1975, subsequently “AM”) with pivotal ideas of Bas van Fraassen’s 2002 book, The Empirical Stance (subsequently “ES”). The comparison appears fruitful for two reasons: first, because van Fraassen is one of the few contemporary philo- sophers of science who continue to engage closely and charitably with Feyerabend’s work; and, second, because van Fraassen disagrees with some of Feyerabend’s central contentions. I do not here have the space to determine conclusively who of the two phi- losophers is right where they take different views on a given question; I shall be satisfied to clearly identify the issues and disputes that need further reflection. The scope of this investigation is restricted primarily to ES and the first edition of AM. I look beyond these two books only where ES’s discussion of Feyerabend’s views draws on texts other than AM, and where van Fraassen further develops important claims of ES. I have already elsewhere discussed Feyerabend’s relativism in his later writings (Kusch 2016). Moreover, Feyerabend’s and van Fraassen’s respective oeuvres are of such breadth, depth, and development over time, that a full consideration of all of their important similarities and differences would require a book-length treatment. Two ideas from ES will be crucial in what follows. The first idea is that many philosophical positions are best rendered not as “doctrines” but as “stances;” that is, as sets, systems or bundles of values, emotions, policies, preferences, and beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetoric of Science 1 Rhetoric of Science
    Rhetoric of science 1 Rhetoric of science Rhetoric of science is a body of scholarly literature exploring the notion that the practice of science is a rhetorical activity. It emerged from a number of disciplines during the late twentieth century, including the disciplines of sociology, history, and philosophy of science, but it is practiced most fully by rhetoricians in departments of English, speech, and communication. Rhetoric is best known as a discipline that studies the means and ends of persuasion. Science, meanwhile, is typically seen as the discovery and recording of knowledge about the natural world. A key contention of rhetoric of science is that the practice of science is, to varying degrees, persuasive. The study of science from this viewpoint variously examines modes of inquiry, logic, argumentation, the ethos of scientific practitioners, the structures of scientific publications, and the character of scientific discourse and debates. For instance, scientists must convince their community of scientists that their research is based on sound scientific method. From a rhetorical point of view, scientific method involves problem-solution topoi (the materials of discourse) that demonstrate observational and experimental competence (arrangement or order of discourse or method), and as a means of persuasion, offer explanatory and predictive power (Prelli 185-193). Experimental competence is itself a persuasive topos (Prelli 186). Rhetoric of science is a practice of suasion that is an outgrowth of some of the canons of rhetoric. History Since 1970, rhetoric of science, as a field involving rhetoricians, flourished. This flourishing of scholarly activity contributed to a shift in the image of science that was taking place (Harris "Intro," Landmark xv).
    [Show full text]
  • SCIENTIFIC METHOD Howard Sankey
    23 SCIENTIFIC METHOD Howard Sankey Philosophers have long held there to be something special about science that distin- guishes it from non-science. Rather than a shared subject-matter, the distinction is usually taken to reside at the methodological level. What sets the sciences apart from non-scientific pursuits is the possession of a characteristic method employed by their practitioners. It is customary to refer to this characteristic method of science as the “scientific method.” Those disciplines which employ the scientific method qualify as sciences; those which do not employ the method are considered not to be scientific. While most philosophers agree that science is to be characterized in methodological terms, they disagree about the nature of this method. Many take the fundamental method of science to be an inductive method. Others belittle induction or deny its use altogether. It was once taken to be virtually axiomatic that the method of science is a fixed and universal method employed throughout the sciences. Yet, at the present time, it is not uncommon to hold that method depends on historical time-period or cultural context, or that it varies from one field of science to another. While it was once widely believed that there is a single scientific method characteristic of all science, it is now more common to hold that the method of science consists of a multi- faceted array of rules, techniques and procedures which broadly govern the practice of science. Indeed, some have concluded that there is, strictly speaking, no such thing as the scientific method. It is possible to distinguish a number of different levels at which methods may be employed in science.
    [Show full text]
  • 83 Feyerabend, Pluralism and Progress in Science in Against
    International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) Volume 4 Issue 2, February 2020 Available Online: www.ijtsrd.com e-ISSN: 2456 – 6470 Feyerabend, Pluralism and Progress in Science in Against Method (1993) and the Tyranny of Science (2011) Nyuykongi John Paul. PhD Department of Educational Foundations, Faculty of Education, the University of Bamenda, Bamenda, Cameroon ABSTRACT How to cite this paper : Nyuykongi John The epistemological problem associated with Karl Paul Feyerabend as a Paul "Feyerabend, Pluralism and Progress philosopher of Science resides beneath the fact that different critics of his in Science in Against Method (1993) and works give divers interpretations of them. His works and the accounts they the Tyranny of Science (2011)" Published present have no common structure. This plurality and conflictual in International interpretations of him makes it difficult, if not impossible to pin him to a Journal of Trend in particular tradition in the Philosophy of Science. For this reason, while some of Scientific Research his critics consider him to be a relativist, to some, he is a Dadaist, a and Development confusionist and an anarchist, yet others think of Feyerabend as the worst (ijtsrd), ISSN: 2456- enemy of Science. This diversity of interpretation of Feyerabend, in my 6470, Volume-4 | opinion, only goes to reassure us of our reading of him. That is, Feyerabend is Issue-2, February IJTSRD30060 closely associated with pluralism than anything else. My aim, in this paper is 2020, pp.470-478, URL: thus propose a thesis and attempt a justification. The thesis is that; my reading www.ijtsrd.com/papers/ijtsrd30060.pdf of Against Method, (1993) and The Tyranny of Science, (2011), justifies the thesis above.
    [Show full text]