Four Central Issues in Popper's Theory of Science

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Four Central Issues in Popper's Theory of Science FOUR CENTRAL ISSUES IN POPPER’S THEORY OF SCIENCE By CARLOS E. GARCIA-DUQUE A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA 2002 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would not have been able to finish this project without the help and support of many persons and institutions. To begin with, 1 wish to express my deepest gratitude to Dr. Chuang Liu, chair of my doctoral committee for his continuous support and enthusiastic encouragement since the time when this dissertation was nothing more than a inchoate idea. 1 enjoyed our long discussions and benefited greatly from his advice and insightful suggestions. 1 am also very grateful to the other members of my committee, who all made significant contributions to the final product. 1 wish to thank Dr. Kirk Ludwig with whom 1 have had extensive discussions about several specific problems that 1 addressed in my dissertation. His valuable suggestions made my arguments more compelling and helped me to improve substantially Chapter 5. Dr. Robert D’Amico has posed deep questions that led me to refine and better structure my views. My conversa- tions with Dr. Robert A. Hatch about specific episodes in the history of science and their relationship with my topic were inspirational and prompted me to develop new ideas. I completed my doctoral studies with the endorsement of the Fulbright Program and the support of the Department of Philosophy at the University of Florida. 1 also want to thank the Universidad de Caldas and the Universidad de Manizales for granting me a leave of absence long enough to successfully finish this academic program. Last, but not least, 1 want to thank my family as well as my closest friends for encouraging my interest in philosophy and for trying to make my life easier and less lonely through the hardships of a very prolonged absence. 11 TABLE OF CONTENTS page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ii KEY TO ABBREVIATIONS v ABSTRACT3 vi CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION 1 1.1 Motivation 4 1.2 Method 4 1 .3 Main Themes of the Chapters 6 2 SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION 11 2.1 The Problem of Induction 15 2.2 Popper’s Solution 19 2 . 3 Criticisms of Popper’ s Solution 39 FALSIFIABILITY 57 3.1 Deductivism and Falsifiability 58 3.2 Falsifiability Defined 68 3.2.1 Falsifiability and Falsification 71 3.2.2 Falsifiability: Second Definition 3.3 Criticisms of Popper’s Notion of Falsifiability... 80 3.3.1 Kuhn: Testing vs. Puzzle Solving .80 3.3.2 Lakatos: Sophisticated Falsificationism... .91 3.3.3 Feyerabend: Epistemological Anarchism 105 3.3.4 Derksen: Falsifiability is Fake Cement..., 116 4 CORROBORATION 123 4. 1 Corroboration and Probability of Events 125 4.2 The Notion of Corroboration 130 4.3 Corroboration and Logical Probability 133 4.4 Corroboration Revisited 139 4.5 Criticisms of Popper’s Notion of Corroboration 154 4.5.1 Putnam; Theory is not an End for Itself 1 55 4.5.2 Lakatos: Corroboration is a Measure of Verisimilitude 165 4.5.3 Derksen on Corroboration 171 4.5.4 A Whiff of Induction 175 5 VERISIMILITUDE 177 5.1 The Theory of Objective Truth 178 5.2 Popper’s Notion of Verisimilitude 182 5.3 Refining Verisimilitude 188 5 .4 Criticisms of Popper’ s Notion of Verisimilitude 194 5.4.1 Tichy: all False Theories are Equally Verisimilar 196 5.4.2 Miller: No Two False Theories are Comparable by Verisimilitude 200 5.5 Reply to Tichy and Miller 203 5.6 The Quantitative Measure of Verisimilitude 211 5.7 Verisimilitude as a Surrogate for Truth 222 5.8 Are there True Theories? 226 5.8.1 The Epistemic Status of Scientific Theories 235 5.8.2 Aiming at Verisimilitude Rather than Truth 237 6 EPILOGUE 244 LIST OF DEFINITIONS 255 REFERENCES 257 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH 264 IV KEY TO ABBREVIATIONS The main works of Popper are cited in the text as follows: OS The Open Society and its Enemies PH The Poverty ofHistoricism. LScD The Logic ofScientific Discovery CR Conjectures and Refutations: the Growth ofScientific Knowledge OK Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach RSR “The Rationality of Scientific Revolutions” NV “A Note on Verisimilitude” UQ Unended Quest: an Intellectual Autobiograph. QSP Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics OU The Open Universe: an Argumentfor Indeterminism RAS Realism and the Aim ofScience WP A World ofPropensities SBW In Search ofa Better World: Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years KBM Knowledge and the Body-mind Problem: in Defence ofInteraction ME The Myth ofthe Framework: in Defence ofScience and Rationality EPE The World ofParmenides: Essays on the Presocratic Enlightenment EPS All Life is Problem Solving Abstract of Dissertation Presented to the Graduate School of the University of Florida in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy FOUR CENTRAL ISSUES IN POPPER’S THEORY OF SCIENCE By Carlos E. Garcia-Duque December 2002 Chair: Chuang Liu Department: Philosophy Karl Popper’s influential theory of science has been widely debated and s theory, vigorously criticized over the last few decades. The central concepts of Popper the those of falsifiability, corroboration, and verisimilitude have been by-words in to literature of the Philosophy of Science during this period. Popper’s challenges orthodoxy and, in some ways, radical views, have generated considerable controversy. There have been sharp criticisms and a few defenders —but even among the defenders one sees mostly appropriations, rather than genuine defense. There has not, however, been any systematic general defense of his central views in the literature. This dissertation attempts such a defense, by way of a careful examination and sympathetic interpretation to of the main themes of Popper’s theory, namely, the role of falsifiability in responding the demarcation problem and solving the problem of induction, the insistence on corroboration as a desirable feature of scientific theories as well as an indicator of empirical progress, and the theory of verisimilitude, according to which the long-term VI aim of science is properly pursued by means of advancing theories which constitute better approximations to the truth than their competitors. The overall strategy is to review carefully the most important criticisms of each of the above themes in Popper’s theory. After providing background for a discussion of the matters at issue, I try to disarm the objections by showing that they misconstrue Popper’s intent; to this end I provide alternative interpretations of how Popper can be properly understood and propose minor revisions to the concepts analyzed (being always respectful of Popper’s original definitions). After dissolving the objections and developing the fundamental notions with the revisions introduced, Popper’s theory of science emerges rehabilitated. vii CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION This study deals with a particular portion of Popper’s theory of science, namely its treatment of the problem of induction (including the proposal for a solution) and the notions of falsifiability, corroboration and verisimilitude. These four topics are the cornerstones of Popper’s theory because, properly articulated, they are sufficient to account for the crucial problems of epistemology, not to mention that Popper’s image of empirical science depends entirely upon them. In particular, they supply criteria to admit theories into the body of science or remove them from it; they provide means to select among competing theories and they give an explanation of the growth of scientific knowledge, including its piecemeal approach to the truth. In broader terms, they constitute an alternative to the ideas of logical positivism, offer support to scientific realism, and give birth to an increasingly influential theory (now known as critical rationalism). Given its cardinal importance for a methodology that admits hypotheses into the body of scientific knowledge with only the requirement of compliance with a formal criterion, special attention is given to the logical notion of falsifiability and to its relations with corroboration and verisimilitude. However, in spite of the simplicity that these four topics appear to have, this dissertation does not attempt to analyze fully their many ramifications and complications. It settles for the less ambitious goal of providing a clear construal of each of them and explaining the basic form of their inter-relation with the hope of giving the reader the tools necessary to grasp Popper’s theory at its best. 1 2 Popper committed himself to a clear presentation of his ideas and encouraged others to scrutinize them severely with the implicit promise to abandon any view that did not resist criticism. This seems the appropriate attitude for someone who considered criticism to be “the lifeblood of all rational thought” (“Replies to my Critics,” p. 977) and insisted on the fallible nature of the most sophisticated kinds of knowledge, science included. But the criticisms, which came from all quarters and appeared to be devastating, left the essence of his position untouched, and except for minor revisions and additional explanations here and there Popper did not change, let alone give up, any of his key notions. Since several authors (Johansson, 1975; Stove, 1982; Burke, 1983) consider most of these criticisms successful (actually the myth of a conclusively refuted Popper is widespread), at some point one must ask why Popper did not modify drastically or renounce his central ideas after those criticisms were expressed. For many, this was an indication that despite his pronouncements to the contrary. Popper did not really admit criticism. I suspect that most of the criticisms were less apt than first thought. Although this alternation hardly exhausts all the possible explanations, I am inclined to focus my discussion on it.
Recommended publications
  • At Least in Biophysical Novelties Amihud Gilead
    The Twilight of Determinism: At Least in Biophysical Novelties Amihud Gilead Department of Philosophy, Eshkol Tower, University of Haifa, Haifa 3498838 Email: [email protected] Abstract. In the 1990s, Richard Lewontin referred to what appeared to be the twilight of determinism in biology. He pointed out that DNA determines only a little part of life phenomena, which are very complex. In fact, organisms determine the environment and vice versa in a nonlinear way. Very recently, biophysicists, Shimon Marom and Erez Braun, have demonstrated that controlled biophysical systems have shown a relative autonomy and flexibility in response which could not be predicted. Within the boundaries of some restraints, most of them genetic, this freedom from determinism is well maintained. Marom and Braun have challenged not only biophysical determinism but also reverse-engineering, naive reductionism, mechanism, and systems biology. Metaphysically possibly, anything actual is contingent.1 Of course, such a possibility is entirely excluded in Spinoza’s philosophy as well as in many philosophical views at present. Kant believed that anything phenomenal, namely, anything that is experimental or empirical, is inescapably subject to space, time, and categories (such as causality) which entail the undeniable validity of determinism. Both Kant and Laplace assumed that modern science, such as Newton’s physics, must rely upon such a deterministic view. According to Kant, free will is possible not in the phenomenal world, the empirical world in which we 1 This is an assumption of a full-blown metaphysics—panenmentalism—whose author is Amihud Gilead. See Gilead 1999, 2003, 2009 and 2011, including literary, psychological, and natural applications and examples —especially in chemistry —in Gilead 2009, 2010, 2013, 2014a–c, and 2015a–d.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke's Historical Method
    RUCH FILOZOFICZNY LXXV 2019 4 Zbigniew Pietrzak University of Wrocław, Wrocław, Poland ORCID: 0000-0003-2458-1252 e-mail: [email protected] John Locke’s Historical Method and “Natural Histories” in Modern Natural Sciences DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/RF.2019.038 Introduction Among the many fundamental issues that helped shape the philosophy of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, one concerned the condi- tion of philosophy and scientific knowledge, and in the area of our inter- est – knowledge about nature.1 These philosophical inquiries included both subject-related problems concerning human cognitive abilities and object-related ones indicating possible epistemological boundaries that nature itself could have generated. Thus, already at the turn of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, from Francis Bacon, Galileo, and 1 These reflections are an elaboration on the topic I mentioned in the article “His- toria naturalna a wiedza o naturze” [“Natural History vs. Knowledge of Nature”], in: Rozum, człowiek, historia, [Mind, Man, History], ed. Jakub Szczepański (Cracow: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego, 2018); as well as in my master’s thesis: The Crisis of Cognition, the Crisis of Philosophy (not published). It is also a debate over the content of Adam Grzeliński’s article entitled “‘Rozważania dotyczące rozu- mu ludzkiego’ Johna Locke’a: teoria poznania i historia” [“John Locke’s ‘An essay on human understanding’: cognition theory and history”], in: Rozum, człowiek, historia, ed. Jakub Szczepański, (Cracow: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego, 2018), as well as some of the themes of the author’s monograph Doświadczenie i rozum. Empiryzm Johna Locke’a [Experience and reason. The empiricism of John Locke] (To- ruń: Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu Mikołaja Kopernika, 2019).
    [Show full text]
  • Would ''Direct Realism'' Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction?
    NOU^S 38:2 (2004) 197–232 Would ‘‘Direct Realism’’ Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction? MARC LANGE University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill I Recently, there has been a modest resurgence of interest in the ‘‘Humean’’ problem of induction. For several decades following the recognized failure of Strawsonian ‘‘ordinary-language’’ dissolutions and of Wesley Salmon’s elaboration of Reichenbach’s pragmatic vindication of induction, work on the problem of induction languished. Attention turned instead toward con- firmation theory, as philosophers sensibly tried to understand precisely what it is that a justification of induction should aim to justify. Now, however, in light of Bayesian confirmation theory and other developments in epistemology, several philosophers have begun to reconsider the classical problem of induction. In section 2, I shall review a few of these developments. Though some of them will turn out to be unilluminating, others will profitably suggest that we not meet inductive scepticism by trying to justify some alleged general principle of ampliative reasoning. Accordingly, in section 3, I shall examine how the problem of induction arises in the context of one particular ‘‘inductive leap’’: the confirmation, most famously by Henrietta Leavitt and Harlow Shapley about a century ago, that a period-luminosity relation governs all Cepheid variable stars. This is a good example for the inductive sceptic’s purposes, since it is difficult to see how the sparse background knowledge available at the time could have entitled stellar astronomers to regard their observations as justifying this grand inductive generalization. I shall argue that the observation reports that confirmed the Cepheid period- luminosity law were themselves ‘‘thick’’ with expectations regarding as yet unknown laws of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth, Rationality, and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge
    ....... CONJECTURES sense similar to that in which processes or things may be said to be parts of the world; that the world consists of facts in a sense in which it may be said to consist of (four dimensional) processes or of (three dimensional) things. They believe that, just as certain nouns are names of things, sentences are names of facts. And they sometimes even believe that sentences are some- thing like pictures of facts, or that they are projections of facts.7 But all this is mistaken. The fact that there is no elephant in this room is not one of the processes or parts ofthe world; nor is the fact that a hailstorm in Newfound- 10 land occurred exactIy I I I years after a tree collapsed in the New Zealand bush. Facts are something like a common product oflanguage and reality; they are reality pinned down by descriptive statements. They are like abstracts from TRUTH, RATIONALITY, AND THE a book, made in a language which is different from that of the original, and determined not only by the original book but nearly as much by the principles GROWTH OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE of selection and by other methods of abstracting, and by the means of which the new language disposes. New linguistic means not only help us to describe 1. THE GROWTH OF KNOWLEDGE: THEORIES AND PROBLEMS new kinds of facts; in a way, they even create new kinds of facts. In a certain sense, these facts obviously existed before the new means were created which I were indispensable for their description; I say, 'obviously' because a calcula- tion, for example, ofthe movements of the planet Mercury of 100 years ago, MY aim in this lecture is to stress the significance of one particular aspect of carried out today with the help of the calculus of the theory of relativity, may science-its need to grow, or, if you like, its need to progress.
    [Show full text]
  • Ingenuity in Mathematics Ross Honsberger 10.1090/Nml/023
    AMS / MAA ANNELI LAX NEW MATHEMATICAL LIBRARY VOL 23 Ingenuity in Mathematics Ross Honsberger 10.1090/nml/023 INGENUITY IN MATHEMAmCS NEW MATHEMATICAL LIBRARY PUBLISHED BY THEMATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA Editorial Committee Basil Gordon, Chairman (1975-76) Anneli Lax, Editor University of California, L.A. New York University Ivan Niven (1 975-77) University of Oregon M. M. Schiffer (1975-77) Stanford University The New Mathematical Library (NML) was begun in 1961 by the School Mathematics Study Group to make available to high school students short expository books on various topics not usually covered in the high school syllabus. In a decade the NML matured into a steadily growing series of some twenty titles of interest not only to the originally intended audience, but to college students and teachers at all levels. Previously published by Random House and L. W. Singer, the NML became a publication series of the Mathematical Association of America (MAA) in 1975. Under the auspices of the MAA the NML will continue to grow and will remain dedicated to its original and expanded purposes. INGENUITY IN MATHEMATICS by Ross Honsberger University of Waterloo, Canada 23 MATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA Illustrated by George H. Buehler Sixth Printing © Copyright 1970, by the Mathematical Association of America A11 rights reserved under International and Pan-American Copyright Conventions. Published in Washington by The Mathematical Association of America Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 77-134351 Print ISBN 978-0-88385-623-9 Electronic ISBN 978-0-88385-938-4 Manufactured in the United States of America Note to the Reader his book is one of a series written by professional mathematicians Tin order to make some important mathematical ideas interesting and understandable to a large audience of high school students and laymen.
    [Show full text]
  • VU Research Portal
    VU Research Portal Realism, Instrumentalism, and Scientific Symbiosis: Psychological Theory as a search for truth and the discovery of solutions Cacioppo, J.T.; Semin, G.R.; Berntson, G.G. published in American Psychologist 2004 DOI (link to publisher) 10.1037/0003-066X.59.4.214 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Cacioppo, J. T., Semin, G. R., & Berntson, G. G. (2004). Realism, Instrumentalism, and Scientific Symbiosis: Psychological Theory as a search for truth and the discovery of solutions. American Psychologist, 59, 214-233. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.59.4.214 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 03. Oct. 2021 Realism, Instrumentalism, and Scientific Symbiosis Psychological Theory as a Search for Truth and the Discovery of Solutions John T.
    [Show full text]
  • The Demarcation Problem
    Part I The Demarcation Problem 25 Chapter 1 Popper’s Falsifiability Criterion 1.1 Popper’s Falsifiability Popper’s Problem : To distinguish between science and pseudo-science (astronomy vs astrology) - Important distinction: truth is not the issue – some theories are sci- entific and false, and some may be unscientific but true. - Traditional but unsatisfactory answers: empirical method - Popper’s targets: Marx, Freud, Adler Popper’s thesis : Falsifiability – the theory contains claims which could be proved to be false. Characteristics of Pseudo-Science : unfalsifiable - Any phenomenon can be interpreted in terms of the pseudo-scientific theory “Whatever happened always confirmed it” (5) - Example: man drowning vs saving a child Characteristics of Science : falsifiability - A scientific theory is always takes risks concerning the empirical ob- servations. It contains the possibility of being falsified. There is con- firmation only when there is failure to refute. 27 28 CHAPTER 1. POPPER’S FALSIFIABILITY CRITERION “The theory is incompatible with certain possible results of observation” (6) - Example: Einstein 1919 1.2 Kuhn’s criticism of Popper Kuhn’s Criticism of Popper : Popper’s falsifiability criterion fails to char- acterize science as it is actually practiced. His criticism at best applies to revolutionary periods of the history of science. Another criterion must be given for normal science. Kuhn’s argument : - Kuhn’s distinction between normal science and revolutionary science - A lesson from the history of science: most science is normal science. Accordingly, philosophy of science should focus on normal science. And any satisfactory demarcation criterion must apply to normal science. - Popper’s falsifiability criterion at best only applies to revolutionary science, not to normal science.
    [Show full text]
  • Realism and Instrumentalism in Philosophical Explanation
    Simchen, O. 2019. Realism and Instrumentalism in Philosophical Explanation. Metaphysics, 2(1), pp. 1–15. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/met.20 RESEARCH Realism and Instrumentalism in Philosophical Explanation Ori Simchen University of British Columbia, CA [email protected] There is a salient contrast in how theoretical representations are regarded. Some are regarded as revealing the nature of what they represent, as in familiar cases of theoretical identification in physical chemistry where water is represented as hydrogen hydroxide and gold is represented as the element with atomic number 79. Other theoretical representations are regarded as serving other explanatory aims without being taken individually to reveal the nature of what they represent, as in the representation of gold as a standard for pre-20th century monetary systems in economics or the representation of the meaning of an English sentence as a function from possible worlds to truth values in truth-conditional semantics. Call the first attitude towards a theoretical representation realist and the second attitude instrumentalist. Philosophical explanation purports to reveal the nature of whatever falls within its purview, so it would appear that a realist attitude towards its representations is a natural default. I offer reasons for skepticism about such default realism that emerge from attending to several case studies of philosophical explanation and drawing a general metaphilosophical moral from the foregoing discussion. Keywords: realism; instrumentalism; philosophical explanation; philosophical methodology 1 Introduction Any theoretical endeavour employs representations and philosophy is no exception. A representation for present purposes is a theoretical apparatus that stands for some subject matter within a purported explana- tion.
    [Show full text]
  • Brsq #142-144
    THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY QUARTERLY Fall 2009 Issue Numbers 142 -144 / May -November 2009 THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT Published by The Bertrand Russell Society with the support of Lehman College - City University of New York THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SoCIET¥ QUARTERLY is the official organ of the THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Bertrand Russell Society. It publishes Society news and proceedings, and QUARTERLY articles on the history of analytic philosophy, especially those on Russell's life and works, including historical materials and reviews of recent work on Fall 2009 Issue Russell. Scholarly articles appearing in the a"crrfer/,v are peer-reviewed. Numbers 142-144 / May -November 2009 Co-EDITORS: Rosalind Carey and John Ongley ASSOCIATE EDITOR: Ray Perkins Jr. EDITORIAL BOARD Rosalind Carey, Lehman College-CUNY THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT John Ongley, Bloomsburg University Raymond Perkins, Jr., Plymouth State University Christopher Pincock, Purdue University David Hyder, University of Ottawa CONTENTS Anat Biletzki, Tel Aviv University SuBMISsloNS : All communications to the Ber/ra#cJ Rwssc// Soci.edy gwcrr/er- In This Issue /y, including manuscripts. book reviews, and letters to the editor, should be Society News sent to: Prof. Rosalind Carey, Philosophy Department, Lehman College- ln Memoriam: Theo Meijer CUNY, 250 Bed ford Park Blvd. West, Bronx, NY 10468, USA, or by email to: [email protected]. Feature SuBSCRlpTloNS: The BRS gwc}rfedy is free to members of the Bertrand Rus- sell Society. Society membership is $35 a year for individuals, $40 for cou- Nicholas Griffin Speaks His Mind: An Interview by ples, and $20 for students and limited income individuals.
    [Show full text]
  • A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont Scripps Senior Theses Scripps Student Scholarship 2019 A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry Karina Bucciarelli Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses Part of the Epistemology Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Bucciarelli, Karina, "A Feminist Epistemological Framework: Preventing Knowledge Distortions in Scientific Inquiry" (2019). Scripps Senior Theses. 1365. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1365 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Scripps Student Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scripps Senior Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGICAL FRAMEWORK: PREVENTING KNOWLEDGE DISTORTIONS IN SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY by KARINA MARTINS BUCCIARELLI SUBMITTED TO SCRIPPS COLLEGE IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE DEGREE OF BACHELOR OF ARTS PROFESSOR SUSAN CASTAGNETTO PROFESSOR RIMA BASU APRIL 26, 2019 Bucciarelli 2 Acknowledgements First off, I would like to thank my wonderful family for supporting me every step of the way. Mamãe e Papai, obrigada pelo amor e carinho, mil telefonemas, conversas e risadas. Obrigada por não só proporcionar essa educação incrível, mas também me dar um exemplo de como viver. Rafa, thanks for the jokes, the editing help and the spontaneous phone calls. Bela, thank you for the endless time you give to me, for your patience and for your support (even through WhatsApp audios). To my dear friends, thank you for the late study nights, the wild dance parties, the laughs and the endless support.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity in the Feminist Philosophy of Science
    OBJECTIVITY IN THE FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requisites for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Karen Cordrick Haely, M.A. ***** The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Louise M. Antony, Adviser Professor Donald C. Hubin _______________________ Professor George Pappas Adviser Philosophy Graduate Program ABSTRACT According to a familiar though naïve conception, science is a rigorously neutral enterprise, free from social and cultural influence, but more sophisticated philosophical views about science have revealed that cultural and personal interests and values are ubiquitous in scientific practice, and thus ought not be ignored when attempting to understand, describe and prescribe proper behavior for the practice of science. Indeed, many theorists have argued that cultural and personal interests and values must be present in science (and knowledge gathering in general) in order to make sense of the world. The concept of objectivity has been utilized in the philosophy of science (as well as in epistemology) as a way to discuss and explore the various types of social and cultural influence that operate in science. The concept has also served as the focus of debates about just how much neutrality we can or should expect in science. This thesis examines feminist ideas regarding how to revise and enrich the concept of objectivity, and how these suggestions help achieve both feminist and scientific goals. Feminists offer us warnings about “idealized” concepts of objectivity, and suggest that power can play a crucial role in determining which research programs get labeled “objective”.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Feyerabend
    Against Method Fourth Edition Paul Feyerabend VERSO London • New York Analytical Index Being a Sketch of the Main Argument Introdnction 1 Science is an essentially anarchic enterprise: theoretical anarchism is more humanitarian and more likely to encourage progress than its law-and-order alternatives. 1 7 This is shown both by an examination of historical episodes and by an abstract analysis of the relation between idea and action. The only principle that does not inhibit progress is: anything goes. 2 13 For example, we may use hypotheses that contradict well-confirmed theories and/or well-established experimental results. We may advance science by proceeding counterinductively. 3 17 The consistency condition which demands that new hypotheses agree with accepted theories is unreasonable because it preserves the older theory, and not the better theory. Hypotheses contradicting well-confirmed theories give us evidence that cannot be obtained in any other way. Proliferation of theories is beneficial for science, while uniformity impairs its critical power. Uniformity also endangers the free development of the individual. 4 ~ There is no idea, however ancient and absurd, that is not capable of improving our knowledge. The whole history of thought is absorbed into science and is used for improving every single theory. Nor is political interference rejected. It may be needed to overcome the chauvinism of science that resists alternatives to the status quo. xxx ANAL YTICAL INDEX 5 33 No theory ever agrees with all the facts in its domain, yet it is not always the theory that is to blame. Facts are constituted by older ideologies, and a clash between facts and theories may be proof ofprogress.
    [Show full text]