<<

Davidson on Believers Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes?

Adina Roskies

Donald Davidson has argued that only -users can have propositional at- Author titudes. His strongest argument in support of this claim is one that links having propositional attitudes to language via a of . Here I consider various Adina Roskies possible interpretations of this argument, looking first at the canonical conception adina.l.roskies @dartmouth.edu of a concept of belief from the Theory of literature, then at a weaker of the concept of belief corresponding to a conception of objective , and fi- Dartmouth College nally at an intermediate notion involving the ability to attribute mental states. I Hanover, NH, U.S.A. argue that under each of these various interpretations, analysis and appeal to em- pirical evidence from developmental and comparative psychology shows the Dav- Commentator idsonian argument to be unsound. Only on a reading of the argument that slides between different interpretations of “concept of belief” are all the premises true, Ulrike Pompe-Alama but in that case the argument is invalid. I conclude that Davidson doesn’t provide ulrike.pompe-alama@ philo.uni- sufficient reason to deny that non-linguistic creatures can have propositional atti- stuttgart.de tudes. Universität Stuttgart Stuttgart, Germany Keywords Belief | Capacity | Concept | False belief test | Language | Non-linguistic | Pro- Editors positional attitudes | Rationality | Thought | Thomas Metzinger metzinger @uni-mainz.de Johannes Gutenberg-Universität Mainz, Germany

Jennifer M. Windt [email protected] Monash University Melbourne, Australia

1 Introduction

More often than not, great divides have been other claims about the uniqueness of humans postulated between humans and other animals: have been shown to be untrue or only half-true. it has variously been maintained that only hu- Recently, in response to philosophical and em- mans have souls; that only humans laugh; that pirical work, there has there been significant only humans play; that only humans are ra- political pushback. For example, the Great Ape tional. The status of these claims is not merely Project (http://www.projetogap.org.br/en/) of theoretical interest: human exceptionalism aims to establish great apes as persons with re- has long been used to justify or discount arbit- cognized legal rights. Whether we should stand rary and often inhumane treatment of animals, behind such a project or other less ambitious ef- including the abuses perpetrated in factory forts to treat animals as entities with moral farms and the devastation of habitats for hu- worth depends at least in part on what kind of man gain. While the issue of the soul is beyond capacities they have, both cognitive and affect- empirical confirmation or disconfirmation, many ive.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 1 | 16 www.open-mind.net

Here I combat a philosophically prominent having language is an enabling condition for claim of human uniqueness: Donald Davidson’s having propositional attitudes. Since only hu- famous argument that only humans can think. mans have language, it follows that only hu- In the light of the complex cognitive activities mans have propositional attitudes.2 Thus, his of which animals are clearly capable, one might main argument against animal thought is: think this patently untrue. However, Davidson means by this not that animals have no cognit- P1 If something has propositional attitudes, ive capacities at all, but that nonhuman anim- then it has language. als cannot have beliefs, desires, and other pro- P2 Animals don’t have language. positional attitudes. What the thesis does is C Animals don’t have propositional attitudes. animal apart from human cognition as a different natural kind, due to radically differ- The logic here is unassailable: if P1 and ent representation schemes (see also arguments P2 can be established then the conclusion that in Malcolm 1972). This is not a straw man, but animals lack propositional attitudes follows. an interesting and challenging thesis. In critic- For Davidson, having language is having the ally evaluating the arguments Davidson ability to speak (1984, p. 167, 2001a, p. 99), provides in light of empirical evidence from de- to express one’s thoughts, and to understand velopmental psychology and ethology, insight the speech and propositional attitudes of oth- can be gained into the of the relation- ers. It is generally accepted that nonhuman ship between thought and language. Despite its animals don’t have this ability, despite some prima facie plausibility, I conclude that in light evidence that certain birds and higher mam- of contemporary studies from human and an- mals have some nontrivial linguistic abilities imal cognition, arguments for restricting pro- (Kaminski et al. 2004; Pepperberg 2000; Sav- positional attitudes to humans fail.1 The im- age-Rumbaugh 1986). Therefore, we will grant plications of this result could be far-reach- P2.3 The success of this argument denying ing. Language as a cognitive ability has held a propositional attitudes to nonhumans there- special status in , where it is fore rests on the ability to establish P1, often assumed to be foundational to thought namely the claim that having propositional at- and cognition. Rethinking the role of language titudes requires language. In this paper I con- as a cognitive newcomer and possibly in large sider the various avenues by which Davidson part a cognitive overlay resting atop a toolbox tries to establish P1, for his arguments make of already-powerful cognitive abilities may lead contact with a broad range of research con- us to rethink a number of fundamental issues in cerning mind and language, and serve as a philosophy, as well as to reconsider our cognit- good guide to attempts to link propositional ive and ethical relationship to the rest of the attitudes to language. I begin by situating natural world. This critique of Davidson is illus- Davidson’s arguments in his larger theoretical trative of Dennett’s caution: context, and raise a few methodological wor- ries about his approach. I then briefly con- [p]hilosophy of psychology driven by the sider some of his minor arguments, before concerns of does turning to his strongest argument linking pro- not fall happily into place. (Dennett positional attitudes to language. I argue that 1987b, p. 204) on the most plausible consistent readings of

2 Davidson equates thought with propositional attitudes. He famously The various arguments Davidson supplies for expresses his denial of propositional attitudes to nonhuman animals thinking that humans are unique in having pro- as the claim that animals can’t think. See Davidson (2001a). Here I focus upon arguments found in his 1975 paper “Thought and Talk”, positional attitudes all rest upon the that and his later paper “Rational Animals”. 3 Another reason for focusing on P1 rather than is that finding 1 However, some very interesting and very recent (currently unpub- counterexamples to P2 will at most make room to usher specific spe- lished) work by Susan Carey calls into question the interpretation of cies into the thought-capable fold, but will not challenge Davidson‘s some of the extant pro- empirical work. argument directly.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 2 | 16 www.open-mind.net his arguments, one or another premise can be ments that stem from his interpretationist empirically falsified. I conclude by considering philosophy.5 In general, interpretationist how to proceed to better understand the strategies answer the following three questions nature and limitations of animal thought. simultaneously: “In virtue of what does a creature have propositional attitudes?”, 2 Initial considerations “which propositional attitudes do they have?” and “when is one justified in attributing these 2.1 Propositional attitudes attitudes to a creature?” According to inter- pretationism, a creature has propositional at- A creature is said to have a propositional atti- titudes in virtue of interpretable; the tude when she stands in some appropriate rela- most coherent, charitable interpretation that tion (i.e., hoping, wanting, fearing, believing, accurately (or accurately enough) predicts be- etc.) to a .4 What propositional atti- havior is the justified interpretation; and the tudes are, and who may enjoy them, may well contents of that interpretation serve to de- be influenced by what one takes to termine the contents of the creature’s proposi- be. For instance, a skeptic about propositions tional attitudes. As Byrne puts it, in an inter- may deny that anyone has propositional atti- pretationist strategy, “there is no gap between tudes in the above sense. For our purposes it is our best judgments of a ’s beliefs and not necessary to resolve questions about the desires and the truth about the subject’s be- nature of propositions, provided that we accept liefs and desires,” (1998). Thus, if a creature’s that humans can (and do) have propositional behavior can be accurately predicted or ex- attitudes— that there is something plained by an attribution of beliefs and desires proposition-like to which a thinker can be ap- in conjunction with the assumption of ration- propriately related, whether this be a ality, we are justified in attributing proposi- (Fodor 1978), a set of possible worlds (Lewis tional attitudes to the creature. 1979; Stalnaker 1984), or a state of affairs (Mar- Davidson’s strongest arguments for why cus 1990). What remains to be determined is thought requires language are motivated by whether appropriate to proposition- his interpretationism. On a strict interpreta- like entities can be supported in non-linguistic tionist view, meaning does not exist without creatures. interpretation; so if a system is uninterpreted, it lacks contentful states. Davidson 2.2 Methodological attitudes that language is a prerequisite for entering the world of interpretation. If no language, then Davidson’s arguments are offered in the con- no interpretation, so no content. But let us text of his larger theoretical commitments to consider, from an interpretationist stance, why the nature of mind and meaning, commit- one might think that language is a prerequis- 4 Some have argued that there is no account of what a proposition ite for interpretation. is that is both coherent and satisfies the various criteria that pro- One might think that Davidson is moved positions are traditionally supposed to satisfy (that tradition stemming initially from Frege). See e.g., Dennett (1987a), and by the idea that only linguistic behavior can be Churchland (1981). It is unfortunate, but true, that if our notion interpreted. However, this cannot be Davidson’s of a proposition is fundamentally incoherent, and no compromises position. If it were, Davidson’s approach to pro- can be reached on the criteria propositions must satisfy, then there is no such thing as a proposition. A fortiori, we can’t stand positional attitude attribution would be at odds in any meaningful relation to propositions, so we lack proposi- with his own interpretive strategy for attribut- tional attitudes. Such is the position of some eliminativists. Oth- ers have compromised on the demands put on propositions. ing content to mental states. The basic idea of Quine, for instance, while being no friend of abstract entities Davidson’s interpretationism is that in ascribing such as propositions as usually conceived, found sentences to be less ontologically troublesome stand-ins for them, and held that content to another person’s mental states, we to have a propositional attitude is to stand in some relevant rela- tion to an eternal sentence—thereby still satisfying our philo- 5 In the literature, “interpretationism” is often used interchangeably with sophical about the role of propositional attitudes in ex- “interpretivism”. Since “interpretivism” is more commonly used to de- planations of human thought and behavior. note a strategy of legal interpretation, I will use “interpretationism” here.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 3 | 16 www.open-mind.net assume that that person is rational, and we ality, construed in this way. Building on this ascribe content to her utterances, behaviors, view of rationality promises to enable us to and mental states in such a way as to maximize posit criteria or hallmarks for minimally ra- the coherence of that person’s beliefs and de- tional behavior that are independent of lan- sires in light of her behavior. Undeniably, there guage, yet also to concede that some rational is a of behaviors that humans have and behaviors are linguistically dependent, and thus animals lack, namely linguistic behaviors. How- unique to humans. Indeed, one might think that ever, both humans and animals share a wide a good way to assess rationality would be to see range of non-linguistic behaviors that admit of to what extent an animal’s behavior is predict- interpretation. On the face of it, those behaviors able or explicable with reference to survival re- provide ample evidence upon which to base at- quirements and common sense belief–desire psy- tributions of mental content, and Davidson him- chology. A wide range of animal behaviors cer- self would not refuse to attribute propositional tainly seem apt for with reference attitudes to a silent person. However, Davidson to the rational interplay of ecologically-relevant pointedly refuses to apply a straightforward in- propositional attitudes. If one thinks that apt- terpretationist strategy to non-linguistic anim- ness for explanation in terms of rationality is als. To avoid arbitrariness, an independent ar- sufficient evidence for rationality, and accepts, gument is needed to privilege language over as Davidson does, that rationality rests on the other behaviors. interplay of propositional attitudes, then we Perhaps Davidson believes that rationality have ample evidence that animals have proposi- is impossible without language. If we cannot at- tional attitudes, rather than that they do not. tribute rationality to a creature, the interpreta- Davidson, however, obviously thinks that tionist strategy does not apply. More than a few the reasons to deny animals propositional atti- people have argued that animals are not ra- tudes supersede reasons to attribute rationality tional, yet there is reason to believe, under to them; he applies modus tollens to my modus some plausible construals of rationality, that ponens. Since he denies that animals have pro- they are. To hold that rationality presupposes positional attitudes, and he thinks rationality language commits one to a narrow view of ra- requires propositional attitudes, he denies that tionality, already colored by a linguistic bias. animals are rational. We are led to very differ- Such a view implicitly begs the question in ent conclusions about the nature of animals’ which we are interested. Admittedly, what ra- mental lives depending upon whether we take tionality is is a vexed question in philosophy, ourselves to be more justified in attributing ra- and determining whether a creature is rational tional behavior to them or in refusing to attrib- falls prey to the same holistic problems as de- ute to them propositional attitudes. Because the termining whether it has propositional atti- questions of propositional attitudes and of ra- tudes. A theory of rationality predicated upon a tionality are both equally troubling and closely conception of practical reason instead of upon linked, arguments against animal thought based linguistic manipulation appears to be more on assumptions about rationality are not com- neutral. There is abundant evidence for practic- pelling. ally rational behavior in the animal world. After Thus, we have as yet failed to find ample all, animals of all stripes are here now because reason to refuse to apply the basic interpreta- they have been evolutionary successful, and to tionist strategy to non-linguistic animal beha- have succeeded requires in some nontrivial sense vior. Perhaps Davidson thinks that, in the ab- that goals are achieved by instrumental beha- sence of language, we have insufficient evidence vior.6 All animals exhibit some degree of ration- for attributing propositional attitudes to anim-

6 Decision theory, for instance, gives us one model of rationality. Inter- als. Perhaps it is because Davidson thinks that estingly, in many ecological studies of foraging behavior that use de- “having the gift of tongues” is both necessary cision theory to assess animal , animal behavior is found not to and sufficient for having propositional attitudes just be adaptive, but optimal. For example, animal foraging decisions approach optimality. See e.g., Stephens & Krebs (1986). (1984, p. 156, 2001a, p. 104), he views language

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 4 | 16 www.open-mind.net possession as the evidential criterion for proposi- one is a realist about thought, it is not the evid- tional attitude attribution. He consequently ential question, but rather the question of the denies that we can be justified in attributing grounds of possibility for having propositional propositional attitudes to creatures on the basis attitudes that should be of primary interest. of non-linguistic behavior. Language gives the The Davidsonian mix of interpretationism and radical interpreter the green light: evidence of realism creates an uneasy tension, for while he linguistic behavior licenses application of the tends toward realism about belief, he often radical interpretive strategy. seems to think the metaphysical and epistemo- Even if we grant that language is the best logical construals of the question amount to the evidence for propositional attitudes, we should same thing: a creature has propositional atti- be immediately suspicious of the presumption tudes if we ought to interpret him as having that the only evidence relevant for deciding them. I suspect that this collapsing of the issues whether something has propositional attitudes accounts for Davidson’s view that the question is the presence of a necessary and sufficient con- of whether a creature has propositional atti- dition for having them. In normal empirical in- tudes is closely tied to the evidential question of quiry, criteria that are necessary and sufficient what evidence is relevant for deciding whether are rarely the only ones that qualify as evidence something has propositional attitudes. for assessing empirical claims. For instance, a There is, as fard as I can tell, a lack of a rash may be relevant evidence for determining substantive argument for requiring that a whether a person has Lyme disease, despite the creature has language to be a candidate for in- fact that not all people with rashes have Lyme terpretation, as well as for holding that only the disease, and not all people with Lyme have presence of language provides sufficient evidence rashes. Might there not be evidence highly in- for attributing propositional attitudes. Thus, dicative of whether a creature has propositional neither the interpretationist strategy itself, nor attitudes, despite the fact that the evidence is Davidson’s concerns about evidential warrant not decisive? Reasonable, predictable behavior justify the position that only language-speaking is surely a clear source of evidence for the exist- creatures can be candidates for propositional at- ence of propositional attitudes, despite the fact titudes. Now let us turn to the specific argu- that it only provides defeasible reasons for ments Davidson offers for denying animals pro- thinking they exist. positional attitudes: the reasons he offers for Furthermore, unlike instrumentalists like holding that language is necessary for thought. Dennett, Davidson seems to favor the idea that beliefs are real; his anomolous posits a 3 Minor arguments physical-causal substrate for mental states, al- beit one that exempts psychology from being Why might someone think that language is ne- reduced to physical laws.7 One might think, cessary for having propositional attitudes? A nonetheless, that it would be reasonable for a common reason for supposing that language is realist to accept the possibility that beliefs in- necessary for thought is that one is in the grip volve some internal representational structures, of a picture about the nature of thought— and that there could therefore be other types of namely that thought is a type of language, or is reliable evidence besides linguistic evidence for linguistic or language-like. If propositions are the presence of propositional attitudes. Thus, linguistic entities, then creatures that lack the Davidson’s exclusive focus on language is in capacity for linguistic representation might well tension with his realist leanings. Furthermore, if be unable to represent propositions and thus be unable to hold an attitude toward a proposi- 7 The debate about propositional attitudes, language, and capacity for thought has implications beyond to ethics. As tion. However, since there are competing ac- Davidson himself noted, personal and sub personal levels of descrip- counts of what propositions actually are, several tion refer to different logical subjects, and thus Davidson’s argument of which see them as non-linguistic in nature, has implications for the possibility of attributing personhood to an- imals. See again, http://www.projetogap.org.br/en/. the intuitive language-like characteristics of pro-

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 5 | 16 www.open-mind.net positions does not settle the question (Lewis (see Fodor 1975), for instance, thinks that a 1979; Stalnaker 1984). creature must have a language of thought to In several places Davidson gestures at re- have propositional attitudes, but he holds that lated arguments for denying non-linguistic it need not be able to speak or understand a creatures propositional attitudes (1984, p. 156, public language to have a language of thought. 2001a, p. 98). These stem from an implicit com- Even if claims about definite content and opa- mitment to propositional attitudes having cer- city were true, that is, if Fodor is right, David- tain characteristics that only possess. son has erred in thinking that thought requires For instance, Davidson claims that proposi- an external as opposed to an internal language. tional attitudes have definite content, and that If animals have a language of thought, they are only things expressed in language have definite non-language-using believers. content. Drawing on the discussion of Malcolm (1972) before him, he gives an example of a dog 4 Davidson’s Master Argument chasing a cat up a tree. Like Malcolm, he notes that we cannot attribute to the dog the thought The above minor arguments don’t play a central that the cat ran up the maple, as opposed to role in Davidson’s support of P1. The strongest that the cat ran up the tree. If there is no par- support for the crucial premise is found in what I ticular thought we can attribute to the dog, will call his Master Argument.9 The Master Argu- then the dog hasn’t had a thought with definite ment puts psychological restrictions on what it is content, and so hasn’t had a propositional atti- to be an interpreter, and it supports the claim that tude. Davidson elsewhere claims that proposi- one cannot have propositional attitudes without tional attitudes are opaque8, and that language language. If the Master Argument succeeds, then accounts for their opacity (Davidson 2001a, p. Davidson’s arguments for denying that animals 97). Although these claims can be combatted have propositional attitudes is compelling. But, as directly, I will not pursue those arguments here. I shall argue, the Master Argument ultimately Both the definite content claim and the opacity fails, and thus also fails to support the denial of claim lose their teeth when it is recognized that propositional attitudes to animals. they take the following form: According to Davidson’s interpretationism, having beliefs entails being an interpreter. The P1 Propositional attitudes have a , p basic idea of the Master Argument is that pos- P2 Language has property p sessing certain is a prerequisite for be- C Therefore, language is necessary for proposi- ing an interpreter, and that an organism must tional attitudes have language in order to have these concepts.10

9 Davidson nowhere presents his Master Argument in this precise This argument is fallacious—it would only form. I reconstruct the of his argument from “Thought be valid if nothing but language had property p. and Talk” and “Rational Animals”. 10 This ought to be distinguished from the idea that having proposi- But no such argument is on offer. It is worth tional thought requires having some concepts, and that the contents noting, moreover, that whether propositional at- that can be entertained by a creature in propositional thought are constrained by the set of concepts that the creature possesses. This titudes have the property p in question is itself view, held by a variety of thinkers from Frege to Fodor, stems from contentious—do all our beliefs have definite the belief that the propositions to which a thinker stands in relation content? Finally, even if having property p were in having a propositional attitude are complex entities composed of concepts. But then the question of whether animals have proposi- somehow constitutive of thought, and to have p tional thought can be recast as the question of whether animals have thought had to be linguistic, this would still not concepts. If, additionally, one combined this view of the cognitive structure of propositions with a view according to which concept entail that a creature with beliefs and desires possession requires language, one would have an argument for why must have language in Davidson’s sense. Fodor language is necessary for propositional thought. However, whether concept possession requires language is a question that depends, 8 Substitution of co-reffering terms in “opaque” contexts may not pre- among other things, on what concepts are. Whether the vehicles of serve truth. Such is the case with propositional attitudes. Thus, thought are language-like, as I argued earlier, is orthogonal to the is- while it is true that Lois Lane believes “Superman is a hero”, it may sue of whether an organism possesses the capacity to speak or under- be false that she believes “Clark Kent is a hero”, despite the fact stand speech. Therefore Davidson’s argument cannot rest on the that Clark Kent is identical to Superman. nature of concepts.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 6 | 16 www.open-mind.net

Davidson’s position differs from the more or how one takes it to be, or that belief can come widely-held view that having some concepts is apart from reality. On a deflationary view, then, required for having propositional thought, by having the concept of belief is rather like having supposing that there are specific concepts that a the concept of an objective reality. Finally, we creature must possess in order to have proposi- might consider an intermediate notion of the tional thought. The Master Argument links concept of belief that involves the ability to at- thought to language by way of higher-order tribute representational mental states to oneself thoughts. Specifically, Davidson suggests that a and others, without satisfying all the constraints concept of belief is a prerequisite for proposi- that a robust conception must meet. Which, if tional attitudes, and that a concept of belief is any, of these conceptions of “concept of belief” is unavailable without language. Here is David- important for Davidson’s argument linking belief son’s Master Argument: to language?

M1 If S has propositional attitudes, then S has 4.1 The robust conception of belief beliefs. M2 If S has beliefs, then S has a concept of be- The robust conception of belief became import- lief. ant in developmental psychology in the context M3 If S has a concept of belief, then S has lan- of concerns about : having a no- guage. tion of false belief was taken to be diagnostic of MC If S has propositional attitudes, then S has a mature TOM, and, according to many re- language. searchers in the field, only develops in humans at around four years of age (Saxe et al. 2004; The argument is clearly valid. But is it Wellman et al. 2001; Wimmer & Perner 1983). sound? However, requiring a concept of belief in the ro- M1 is plausible; it just highlights Davidson’s bust sense seems too demanding a condition for view that beliefs are a fundamental propositional having propositional attitudes. While we might attitude, and that to have any propositional atti- plausibly doubt whether prelinguistic infants tudes at all, a creature must have some beliefs. really have propositional attitudes, it is hard to M2 and M3, the remaining premises, are interest- deny that young children who have already ac- ing, but their meaning is unclear, for they contain quired a sophisticated facility with language a clause that needs to be unpacked: what exactly have propositional attitudes. Children of two is a “concept of belief”? Let us distinguish three and three, for instance, clearly refer to objects different conceptions of a “concept of belief”, in the world using language, and they readily varying in stringency. One conception of the express their desires (“I want the green concept of belief is robust, in which the concept of monkey!”), beliefs (“I think the ball is under belief is the fully articulated belief-concept that is the bed”), as well as fears and other proposi- taken to be definitive of a mature theory of mind. tional attitudes. They understand others, refer On this robust view, having a concept of belief is to their own and others’ mental states, and an epistemologically-rich notion that entails hav- communicate effectively. We typically and with ing an ability to pass the “false belief test”. That great conviction attribute propositional atti- is, it is criterial for having the concept of belief tudes to children of these ages. Nonetheless, ac- that one has the ability to attribute to others a cording to most developmental psychologists mental representation of the world that may differ (See e.g., Perner et al. 1987; Call et al. 1999; from the way the world is, as well as a recognition http://youtu.be/8hLubgpY2_w), until the age of the perceptual circumstances that would en- of four (two years after they develop consider- gender false representations. In contrast, a defla- able language abilities) children lack a concept tionary conception of what it is to have the of belief in the robust sense.11 And if so, we concept of belief merely requires an understand- 11 Kristen Andrews takes autistic subjects to be counterexamples to David- ing that the world is distinct from how it appears son’s view, which would also argue against M2. (Andrews 2002).

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 7 | 16 www.open-mind.net make ordinary propositional attributions to states to have determinate content we must inter- children well before they possess the robust act with another being in order to “triangulate” concept of belief. Thus, M2 is false.12 and thus make determinate the referents of our Not all psychologists agree that a robust thoughts. Nothing in this picture requires that an concept of belief doesn’t develop until about interpreter have a robust concept of belief as op- four years of age. Some have argued that the posed to a more deflationary one. methods used in many of the classic false belief studies rely too much on language or on inhibit- 4.2 The deflationary conception of belief ory control, and that tests other than the classic false belief test are sufficient for demonstrating In line with the idea that Davidson has a more of false beliefs. For instance, a deflationary view in mind, in both “Thought recent study suggests that children have a and Talk” and “Rational Animals” he mentions concept of belief at far earlier ages than previ- a different criterion for having a belief, which he ously thought—earlier, in fact, than the devel- also thinks links the possession of language to opment of language (Onishi & Baillargeon 2005; the ability to have propositional attitudes. This Baillargeon et al. 2010; Caron 2009). However, is the criterion of possessing a concept of “ob- if this is so, then M3 is false, for the robust con- jective truth.” Davidson’s argument for language ception of belief does not depend on having lan- via the criterion of objective truth is as follows: guage. This version of the Master Argument de- pends upon a tight connection between compet- O1 In order to have propositional attitudes, one ence in the false-belief task and belief. On one must have beliefs. conception of what evidence is sufficient to re- O2 In order to have beliefs, one must have a flect performance on the false-belief task, M2 is concept of objective truth. false, and on another conception, M3 is false. O3 In order to have a concept of objective Either way, the Master Argument is empirically truth, one must have language. refuted, and the robust conception of “the OC Propositional attitudes require language. concept of belief” fails to link language posses- sion and propositional attitudes.13 The logic here is again unproblematic, but Davidson may well be unperturbed, for unpacking the premises is not. At David- there is no textual evidence that he means to im- son seems to equate the concept of objective plicate the robust conception of belief when he truth with that of belief. I take this as evidence claims the concept of belief is necessary for having that he intends “the concept of belief” in the beliefs. After all, from the standpoint of his rad- Master Argument in its most deflationary inter- ical interpreter, one can only be a believer in vir- pretation: as an understanding that how the tue of interpreting others, but it is unclear why world is can come apart from how one takes the the possibility of such interpretation should rest world to be. Given this interpretation one could upon a grasp of others’ mental states being beliefs believe that the concept of objective truth co- in this robust sense, rather then in some weaker occurs with that of belief, or that the cognitive sense. In “The Second Person” (1992), for in- conditions that make possible the concept of be- stance, Davidson argues that for our mental lief are the same as those that make possible the concept of objective truth. In any case, 12 In addition, at ages far younger than those at which children pass the false-belief task, they act as interpreters, in Davidson’s sense. Davidson sees a tight connection between the Any parent knows that their children interpret speech well before notions of belief and objectivity. they are speakers, and long before the age at which they pass the false-belief task. So if interpretation is central to having proposi- How are we to understand the “concept of tional attitudes, it doesn’t require a robust theory of mind. objective truth” in O2 and O3? If Davidson 13 Of course, Onishi and Baillergeon’s interpretation is subject to refut- ation. Should their findings (they developed a nonverbal task that means it to be a metasemantic concept, such as suggest that infants much younger than previously supposed repres- having a Tarskian definition of truth, or an un- ent others’ mental states, such as goals, and beliefs.) re- derstanding that truth applies to propositions, flect something like proto-beliefs rather than full-blown propositional attitude-sustaining beliefs, M3 would not be falsified. and so on, then it would be almost assured that

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 8 | 16 www.open-mind.net one could not grasp the concept of truth So triangulation also fails as a mechanism for without language. It would explain the prima constructing the concept of objectivity. Non- facie plausibility of the Objective Truth version etheless, Davidson’s emphasis on triangulation of the Master Argument. However, if we adopt strongly suggests that by “objective truth” he is that reading of objective truth, O2 would be referring to the appearance/reality distinction. false, for people certainly have propositional at- This interpretation is further strengthened titudes even if they never become philosophers, by taking seriously the fact that Davidson and even if they never have an inkling about thinks the concepts of belief and truth are metasemantic notions. closely linked (1984). As mentioned earlier, hav- Another clue about what Davidson means ing the concept of objective truth is nothing by objective truth comes from his emphasis on other than understanding that how the world is triangulation. Davidson thinks we need to inter- can come apart from how one takes the world act with another person in order to come to see to be. What evidence do we have that language the world as external to us—in order to develop is required for this? a notion of objectivity. By linguistically triangu- lating on an with another, we are forced 4.3 Surprise to recognize that object as part of an objective reality. Davidson illustrates this view in “The As further evidence that Davidson intends a de- second person”: flationary view of the concepts of belief and ob- jective truth, we can turn to another formula- Belief, , and the other proposi- tion of the Master Argument. In his most forth- tional attitudes are all social in that they right explication of what he means by “concept are states a creature cannot be in without of belief”, he suggests that there is a behavioral having the concept of intersubjective mark that is coextensive with having such a truth, and this is a concept one cannot concept: surprise. have without sharing, and knowing that one shares, a world, and a way of thinking In order to have any propositional attitude about the world, with someone else. at all, it is necessary to have the concept (2001b, p. 121) of a belief, to have a belief about some be- lief. But what is required in order to have However, there are two fundamental problems the concept of a belief? Here I turn for with using triangulation as an argument for the help to the phenomenon of surprise, since necessity of language for thought. First, there is I think that surprise requires the concept nothing apparent about triangulation that re- of belief. (Davidson 2001a, p. 104) quires spoken language as opposed to some other sort of joint interaction or non-linguistic The willingness to consider some sort of non- communication. It is, indeed, difficult to see linguistic behavior as relevant to the question why language as opposed to action would be of whether a creature has propositional atti- operative in developing a notion of a world ex- tudes is a methodological breakthrough, for it ternal to ourselves. So triangulation fails to provides an avenue independent of language show that language is necessary for thought. for assessing whether an animal has the re- Second, it is difficult to see how triangulation quisite cognitive machinery to be a believer. could itself suffice for a notion of objectivity. In Davidson maintains that the ability to be sur- order for me to triangulate with another, I must prised is diagnostic of having the concept of first see the other as part of the external world, belief. It indicates recognition that one’s own as opposed to an element in my mentality. As mental representation fails to conform to that long as the other is merely a part of the way I which it represents, and as such it constitutes take things to be, it cannot fulfil the role of the necessary and sufficient evidence of the second person (see for example, Roskies 2011). concept of belief.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 9 | 16 www.open-mind.net

Following this , we can amend Wynn and colleagues demonstrated that infants Davidson’s Master Argument to incorporate can do simple arithmetic (Wynn 1992). She this insight: showed infants as young as five months a toy, and placed it behind a screen. Then she showed S1 If S has propositional attitudes, then S has them another toy and also placed it behind the beliefs. screen. The screen was then lowered, revealing S2 If S has beliefs, S has a concept of belief. either two toys (the expected outcome), or only S3 S has a concept of belief iff S has the capa- one toy. Infants looked longer at the unexpected city for surprise. outcome. The same was used with dif- S4 If S has the capacity for surprise, S has lan- ferent numerical combinations, demonstrating guage. that for numerosity up to three, infants can do SC Propositional attitudes require language. simple addition and subtraction, and are sur- prised when what is revealed behind the screen The idea that surprise goes hand-in-hand does not comply with their expectations. Signi- with the concept of belief is not implausible: if ficantly, this robust effect, which is due to sur- surprise issues from the recognition that one’s prise, precedes the development of language by belief about how the world is fails to correspond more than a year. with the way the world is, then surprise is good Davidson might reply that it is not actu- evidence for the concept of belief. Moreover, be- ally possessing language, but rather possessing cause this idea does not have implications for the capacity for language that is important for the ability to attribute propositional attitudes surprise, and thus for the concept of belief. to others in an operative sense, it suggests that Maybe, even though they cannot yet speak, in- the interpretation of “concept of belief” that fants possess a language faculty, which, imma- Davidson favors is a deflationary interpretation: ture as it may be, is sufficient to support sur- one that involves appreciation of the appear- prise. However, this attempt to patch the argu- ance/reality distinction, or, as discussed above, ment also fails. The VELM is used frequently in the concept of objective truth. Thus, S2 takes studies with nonhuman primates, and while the deflationary interpretation of the concept of they never develop language nor seem to have a belief, and for the argument to be valid, S3 capacity for natural language, they too exhibit must also take that interpretation. surprise when their expectations are violated Unfortunately for this version of the argu- (Hauser 2000; Hauser et al. 1996). So, it seems, ment, S4 is false. There is clear and abundant language is not a requirement for surprise, nor empirical evidence that the ability to be sur- is surprise evidence for the presence of or capa- prised at the mismatch between the world and city for language. one’s own representation of the world is inde- The empirical studies of developmental pendent of language (Dupoux 2001; Feigenson psychologists and primatologists undermine the et al. 2002; Hauser & Carey 1998; Santos et al. Surprise version of the Master Argument: sur- 2002; Wynn 1992). Take, for example, an in- prise does not depend upon having language. valuable tool in the developmental psycholo- Moreover, if premises S2 and S3 are true—if the gist’s toolkit: the violation of expectancy look- capacity for surprise is evidence of the concept ing method (V) for testing infants. Many stud- of belief, and if propositional attitudes depend ies performed on pre-linguistic human infants upon possession of the concept of belief—then employ this paradigm in order to explore what propositional attitudes do not depend upon lan- an infant knows. The idea is simple: infants look guage. longer at stimuli that fail to correspond with Let us briefly revisit the Objective Truth their expectations. This method has been used version of the Master Argument. I have argued to determine, among other things, that infants that only a deflationary notion of objective have an innate (or very early developing) truth is a candidate interpretation for the argu- concept of number. In now classic experiments, ment. I have also suggested that this is the only

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 10 | 16 www.open-mind.net notion of “the concept of objective truth” that beliefs involves self-reflection: perhaps being a meshes with the arguments Davidson raises re- believer requires being able to think of oneself garding belief and surprise. Thus, having a as a believer, and thus requires the concept of concept of objective truth is having a concept belief. This amounts to the claim that beliefs that the way the world is can come apart from cannot be held non-reflectively. Since we clearly how one takes it to be. If this is correct, then do have beliefs that we do not have beliefs the Objective Truth version of the Master Argu- about, what is at issue is not the actuality of ment is false. having beliefs about beliefs, but the possibility In Wynn’s looking- studies discussed or capacity to do so. However, while there are above, the child has clearly developed expecta- arguments that the ability to think about one- tions of what lies behind the screen, and must self as a believer is required for a rich construal somehow represent this to herself. When the of theoretical rationality (see Bermúdez 2003, screen is lowered and the child sees what is be- Ch. 7), there is no clear argument why such re- hind the screen, there must be some sense in flective ability should be constitutive of having which correspondence with the expectation or beliefs. Indeed, it seems like the ability to be- lack of correspondence is noted, and in which lieve things about one’s beliefs would require the data coming in from the senses is privileged that one could believe things, so that belief is over the internal representation. This is, in es- conceptually prior to self-reflection. In any case, sence, what it is to recognize that beliefs about self-reflection is not Davidson’s stated reason the world can come apart from the way the for thinking that the concept of belief is import- world is. Clearly this sort of grasp of reality ant for having beliefs. does not depend upon language: pre-linguistic The other reason to hold that having be- infants and non-linguistic animals possess it. lief requires having a concept of belief under the One can easily imagine how violation of expect- intermediate conception links the ability to at- ation can be instantiated in a system with ima- tribute mental states to others with having the gistic thought. The languageless child need only concept of belief. Thus there are two different conjure up an image of the objects behind the strengths of intermediate interpretations to con- screen and compare this with the visual scene sider. According to the less demanding inter- before him. As long as the child privileges the pretation, a concept of belief is required in or- sensory over the mental representa- der to attribute contentful states to other tion, we might say that he has a concept of creatures; whereas the more demanding inter- reality and of the belief/reality distinction. In pretation holds that a concept of belief is re- summary, then, language is not required for a quired to attribute propositional attitudes to concept of objective truth. others: one must be an interpreter, not just an interpretee. 4.4 The intermediate conception of belief We can discount the less demanding of these interpretations for the purpose of this ar- We have ruled out both the robust and weakest gument linking thought to language,14 because if notions of “concept of belief” as candidate no- M2 (“If S has beliefs, then S has a concept of tions for a successful interpretation of David- belief”) is interpreted in this way, then M3, the son’s argument linking belief to language. Per- claim that language is required for a concept of haps an intermediate notion can do the job. belief, read in this way, is false. There is grow- This notion involves the ability to attribute rep- ing evidence that non-language-using animals resentational states to oneself and others; it is are able to attribute representational states to less sophisticated than that required to pass the other animals. One compelling illustration of false-belief task, but more complex than the re- this comes from (Hare et al. 2000), who show cognition of an appearance/reality distinction. One potential reason why representational- 14 We ought to reject this interpretation for the purposes of Davidson’s argument, despite the fact that we may ultimately agree with it as a state attribution may be important for having necessary condition for having propositional thought.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 11 | 16 www.open-mind.net that subordinate rhesus monkeys only approach aimed at representing objective truth, but in- food in the presence of a dominant male when stead as attitudes with propositional contents they know that the male is unable to see the that provide information regarding motivation food (interestingly, dominant males appear not to act (2011a). Lurz characterizes this as a kind to care whether or not a subordinate male sees of belief–desire attribution. Baillargeon’s data food, pointing to yet a further level of sophistic- proves relevant here too, for her results are best ation in the cognitive processes of non-linguistic explained by taking the infants in her study as animals). Thus, if it is the case that to believe postulating representational mental states of the requires having the ability to attribute content- actor in order to predict her behavior; violation ful mental states to others, then it is not the of their expectation causes them to look longer. case that believing requires language. Indeed, Thus, without imputing these infants some un- recent work on non-human primate theory of derstanding of others’ representational mental mind suggests that monkeys and chimpanzees states, we would be unable to account for this have a theory of mind that represents goal data. However, in this case M3 would then be states and distinguishes between knowledge and false, for the linguistic abilities of fifteen-month- ignorance of other agents (the presence and ab- old infants typically are minimal—certainly not sence of contentful mental representations), of the sophistication we would expect would be even if it fails to account for misrepresentation necessary to linguistically encode a belief- (Call & Tomasello 2008; Kaminski et al. 2008; concept. While the evidence that bears on this Marticorena et al. 2011). Although they may case is perhaps the least well-established, and have a less articulated theory of mind than we this study involves infants at an age when they do, we may nonetheless adequately characterize are poised to develop language, the burden of their representational system with mental-state proof is shifted to the person who wants to ar- terms (Butterfill & Apperly 2013; Marticorena gue that language is necessary for a concept of et al. 2011). belief. That burden is not discharged: Davidson What remains is the notion that the abil- lacks a positive argument for why this relatively ity to attribute beliefs qua propositional atti- demanding notion of attributing content to oth- tudes to others is necessary for having beliefs. ers is the one required for an organism to be a That is, not only must they attribute mental believer. states to others, but those mental states must possess the characteristics of beliefs. Remember 5 Beyond interpretationism that we have already discounted the robust no- tion of belief as too demanding, so what is ne- Davidson argues that language is required for cessary is not that animals have a notion of thought. His Master Argument posits that hav- false belief per se, but rather that they have a ing a concept of belief is a necessary intermedi- notion of a belief as a representational mental ary for having propositional attitudes, and that state that can play a role in behavioral explana- language is necessary for having a concept of tion or prediction. So far there is no compelling belief. Of the various conceptions of “concept of evidence that nonhuman animals have this, con- belief” that might play a role in Davidson’s ar- sistent with the possibility that such a repres- gument, the robust conception is too strong, entational ability as this may indeed require and empirically falsified. While the robust con- language, or at least some sophisticated ability ception may require language, we attribute pro- to symbolize abstractions and predicate them of positional attitudes before children are clearly objects. Whether this is so is ultimately an em- in possession of such concepts. Davidson’s ex- pirical question. However, at least some philo- amples and arguments support only deflation- sophers think monkeys may be able to do this. ary interpretations of the concept of belief and As Lurz characterizes the above studies, anim- the associated concept of objective truth: those als do have the ability to represent proposi- that involve distinguishing between appearance tional mental states in others—not as attitudes and reality, or those that involve attributing

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 12 | 16 www.open-mind.net mental content. However, as numerous studies complex representational abilities 2) the unique in developmental and comparative psychology elements of linguistic competence and what have shown, the deflationary conception is one they may or may not make possible vis-à-vis that many creatures without language enjoy. thought. In an example of the first, Proust Even an intermediate conception does not seem (1999); see also this collection) provides an illu- to play the role Davidson’s argument requires, minating philosophical discussion of structured for the ability to attribute mental content does non-linguistic representational abilities (or not require language, and neither does the abil- “structured competences”) and how they could ity to attribute to others representational men- make possible objective representations. Struc- tal states, though here the evidence is less clear. tured representations as such could form the Davidson’s arguments seem compelling because building blocks of propositional attitudes. Ber- their plausibility relies upon a slide between less mudez argues for abilities and for certain logical and more demanding conceptions of the concept limitations on both the inferential and repres- of belief. For instance, a weak conception of entational abilities of non-linguistic representers “concept of belief” in M2 and a robust one in (Bermúdez 2003). Whether such limitations ne- M3 yields an argument with apparently true cessarily obtain is a of dispute (Lurz premises, but because the argument equivocates 2007). on “concept of belief”, the argument is invalid. When considering how linguistic abilities This analysis, as well as an appreciation of the could augment thought, it is useful to identify methodological considerations for using non-lin- elements of language that could contribute to guistic behavior as evidence of propositional at- representational complexity even if present titudes, supports the view that some mental without all the components of language. For ex- states of non-linguistic animals can aptly be ample, Clark suggests that the human language- classified as propositional attitudes. like ability to use to represent abstract In empirical circles it seems to be taken objects allows us to objectify our own thoughts for granted that at least some non-linguistic an- and operate upon them (2000). Depending on imals have mental states best described as pro- what things can be symbolized, this could make positional attitudes. But this acceptance is possible metacognition or higher-order thought merely the first step in a larger project. For ex- that might not otherwise be possible. Thus, the ample, even if there is good reason to think that ability to represent symbolically can influence non-linguistic creatures have propositional atti- the kinds and complexity of reasoning available tudes, how they could have these remains to be to a creature, even if that creature is not lin- elucidated. That is, what is the nature of the guistic in Davidson’s sense. Symbolic capacities representational resources available to them? are necessary but not sufficient for linguistic And given these representational resources, competence, and could be present even when what sorts of contents are they capable of rep- language is not. And if mere use of symbols is resenting? What kinds of reasoning and infer- taken to be sufficient for language, then some ence could such representations support? What nonhuman primates are capable of language and are the cognitive limitations necessitated by thus again can have propositional attitudes. In- their representational architectures? One can deed, it is clear that some nonhuman primates begin addressing these fascinating questions em- can be trained to use abstract symbols, even if pirically either at the functional psychological they do not do so naturally. Boysen and col- level or at the level of representation, and from leagues, for example, relate how naïve chimps either level one can work toward answering fail to learn to make second-order generaliza- questions about the other. tions about object classification, but those Instead of thinking that language itself is trained to associate objects with symbols (for what makes complex, structured, or proposi- relations of “same” and “different”) are able to tional thought possible, we should consider: 1) succeed on a second-order classification task how non-linguistic capacities could underlie (Thompson et al. 1997). These interesting res-

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 13 | 16 www.open-mind.net ults give causal punch to the notion that sym- propositional attitudes, but rather to elucidate bolic objectification is a prerequisite for higher- the scope of these attitudes and understand- level or abstract thought, and help to explain ing the ways in which they may be limited by the competences that appear to come along limitations in representational resources. In the with linguistic abilities. most exciting work, the philosophical and psy- Focusing less on the vehicles and more on chological projects come together. This interdis- the ways in which they can be exploited, Fitch ciplinary approach takes seriously evolutionary and colleagues argue that recursion, which is a relationships and has a more nuanced view of core element of natural language processing, can the human being’s place among other anim- only operate on symbolic structures subject to als. The arguments that result will be of great rules, and that neither rules nor the objects on interest to philosophers of language and mind, which they operate can exist without language- as well as to those interested in ethical issues like representations (Hauser et al. 2002). If so, that transcend academia. And while they may one might expect that forms of reasoning that vindicate a certain kind of human exceptional- rely on recursion may only be possible for ism, they may also articulate our place on a creatures that also possess linguistic capacities. spectrum that will ultimately lead to a more in- Thus, use of symbols and recursive rules are two tegrated and humane picture of our place in candidates that could help explain the different the world. representational capacities of linguistic and non- linguistic creatures.

6 Conclusion

Here I have argued that Davidson‘s arguments that nonlinguistic creatures lack thought are either unsound or invalid. While this negative project does not allow us to conclude that they have propositional attitudes or thoughts, it makes room for positive arguments that will take advantage of recent and future empirical work on animal cognition and on the nature of nonlinguistic representations and their role in cognitive processing, as well as for novel negat- ive arguments that might set limits on the capa- cities of nonlinguistic creatures. Much current research in animal cognition focuses on whether animals have theory of mind paralleling that of humans (Marticorena et al. 2011), or metacog- nition (Bermúdez 2003; Carruthers 2008; Lurz 2007, 2011a, 2011b; Proust 2010). One might therefore think that the debate has not pro- gressed much since Davidson asked the question about whether animals can have a concept of belief. But Davidson’s interest in these ques- tions was narrow, driven by his interpretation- ism and the view that these states are necessary for being an interpreter and thus for possessing mental content. In contrast, contemporary re- search does not aim to disprove the of

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 14 | 16 www.open-mind.net

References Feigenson, L., Carey, S. & Spelke, E. S. (2002). Infants’ dis- crimination of number vs. continuous extent. Cognitive Andrews, K. (2002). Interpreting autism: A critique of Dav- Psychology, 44 (1), 33-66. 10.1006/cogp.2001.0760 idson on thought and language. Philosophical Psychology, Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. New York, 15 (3), 317-332. 10.1080/09515080210000061111 NY: Crowell. Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M. & He, Z. (2010). False-belief (1978). Propositional attitudes. Monist, 61 (4), understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 501-523. 10.5840/monist197861444 14 (3), 110-118. 10.1016/j.tics.2009.12.006 Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B. & Tomasello, M. (2000). Bermúdez, J. (2003). Thought without words. Oxford: Ox- Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not ford University Press. see. Animal Behavior, 59 (4), 771-785. Butterfill, S. A. & Apperly, I. A. (2013). How to con- 10.1006/anbe.1999.1377 struct a minimal theory of mind. Mind & Language, 28 Hauser, M. D. (2000). Wild . New York: Henry Holt (5), 606-637. 10.1111/mila.12036 and Co. Byrne, A. (1998). Interpretivism. European Review of Hauser, M. D. & Carey, S. (1998). Building a cognitive Philosophy, 3, 199-223. creature from a set of primitives. In D. D. Cummin & Call, J. & Tomasello, M. (1999). A nonverbal false belief C. Allen (Eds.) The evolution of mind (pp. 51-83). Ox- task: The performance of children and great apes. Child ford, UK: Oxford University Press. Development, 70 (2), 381-395. 10.1111/1467-8624.00028 Hauser, M. D., MacNeilage, P. & Ware, M. (1996). Nu- (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of merical representations in primates. Proceedings of the mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12 National Academy of Sciences of the United States of (5), 187-192. 10.1016/j.tics.2008.02.010 America, 93 (4), 1514-1517. 10.1073/pnas.93.4.1514 Caron, A. J. (2009). Comprehension of the representa- Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N. & Fitch, W. T. (2002). The tional mind in infancy. Developmental Review, 29 (2), faculty of language: What is it, who has it, and how 69-95. 10.1016/j.dr.2009.04.002 did it evolve? Science, 298 (5598), 1569-1579. Carruthers, P. (2008). Meta-cognition in animals: A skep- 10.1126/science.298.5598.1569 tical look. Mind & Language, 23 (1), 58-59. Kaminski, J., Call, J. & Fischer, J. (2004). Word learning 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2007.00329.x in a domestic dog: Evidence for “fast mapping”. Sci- Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative and ence, 304 (5677), 1682-1683. 10.1126/science.1097859 the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, Kaminski, J., Call, J. & Tomasello, M. (2008). Chimpanzees 78 (2), 67-90. know what others know, but not what they believe. Cog- Clark, A. (2000). Mindware: An introduction to the philo- nition, 109 (2), 224-234. 10.1016/j.cognition.2008.08.010 sophy of . Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer- Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes de dicto, de se. Philosophical sity Press. Review, 88 (4), 513-543. 10.2307/2184843 Davidson, D. (1984). Thought and talk. Inquiries into Lurz, R. W. (2007). In defense of wordless thoughts Truth and Interpretation (pp. 155-170). Oxford, UK: about thoughts. Mind and Language, 22 (3), 270-296. Clarendon Press. 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2007.00309.x (2001a). Rational animals. Subjective, intersubject- (2011a). Belief attribution in animals: On how to ive, objective (pp. 95-106). Oxford, UK: Clarendon move forward conceptually and empirically. Review of Press. Philosophy and Psychology, 2 (1), 19-59. (2001b). The second person. Subjective, intersub- 10.1007/s13164-010-0042-z jective, objective (pp. 107-121). Oxford, UK: Clarendon (2011b). Mindreading animals: The debate over Press. what animals know about other minds. Cambridge, Dennett, D. C. (1987a). Beyond belief. The intentional MA: MIT Press. stance (pp. 117-202). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Malcolm, N. (1972). Thoughtless brutes. Proceedings and (1987b). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: Addresses of the American Philosophical , MIT Press. 46, 5-20. 10.2307/3129585 Dupoux, E. (Ed.) (2001). Language, brain, and cognitive Marcus, R. B. (1990). Some revisionary proposals about development: Essays in honor of Jacques Mehler. Cam- belief and believing. Philosophy and Phenomenological bridge, MA: MIT Press. Research, 50 (supplement), 133-153.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 15 | 16 www.open-mind.net

Marticorena, D. C. W., Ruiz, A. M., Mukerji, C., Goddu, Wellman, H. M., Cross, D. & Watson, J. (2001). Meta- A. & Santos, L. R. (2011). Monkeys represent others’ analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth knowledge but not their beliefs. Developmental Science, about false belief. Child Development, 72 (3), 655-684. 14 (5), 1406-1416. 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2011.01085.x 10.1111/1467-8624.00304 Onishi, K. H. & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old Wimmer, H. & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308 (5719), Representation and constraining function of wrong be- 255-258. 10.1126/science.1107621 liefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Pepperberg, I. M. (2000). The alex studies. Cambridge, Cognition, 13 (1), 103-128. MA: Harvard University Press. 10.1016/0010-0277(83)90004-5 Perner, J., Leekam, S. R. & Wimmer, H. (1987). Three- Wynn, K. (1992). Addition and subtraction by human in- year-olds’ difficulty with false belief: The case for a con- fants. Nature, 358 (6389), 749-750. 10.1038/358749a0 ceptual deficit. British Journal of Developmental Psycho- logy, 5, 125-137. 10.1111/j.2044-835X.1987.tb01048.x Proust, J. (1999). Mind, space and objectivity in non-hu- man animals. Erkenntnis, 51 (1). 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00145 (2010). Metacognition. Philosophy Compass, 5 (11), 989-998. 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00340.x (2015). The representational structure of feelings. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group. Roskies, A. L. (2011). Triangulation and objectivity: Squaring the circle? In C. M. Amoretti & G. Preyer (Eds.) Triangulation: From an epistemological point of view (pp. 97-102). Frankfurt am Main, GER: Ontos Verlag. Santos, L. R., Hauser, M. D. & Spelke, E. S. (2002). Do- main-specific knowledge in human children and nonhu- man primates: Artifacts and foods. The cognitive an- imal: Empirical and theoretical perspectives on animal cognition (pp. 205-215). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Savage-Rumbaugh, S. (1986). Ape language: From condi- tioned response to . New York: Columbia Uni- versity Press. Saxe, R., Carey, S. & Kanwisher, N. (2004). Understand- ing other minds: Linking developmental psychology and functional neuroimaging. Annual Review of Psy- chology, 55 (1), 87-124. 10.1146/annurev.psych.55.090902.142044 Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Stephens, D. W. & Krebs, J. R. (1986). Foraging theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Thompson, R. K. R., Oden, D. L. & Boysen, S. T. (1997). Language-naive chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) judge relations between relations in a conceptual matching-to-sample task. Journal of Experimental Psy- chology: Animal Behavior Processes, 23 (1), 31-43. 10.1037/0097-7403.23.1.31

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on Believers - Can Non-Linguistic Creatures Have Propositional Attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND: 33(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. doi: 10.15502/9783958570337 16 | 16