UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Kant, Hegel, and The

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Kant, Hegel, and The UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Kant, Hegel, and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception DISSERTATION submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in Philosophy by Kourosh Christian Alizadeh Dissertation Committee: Associate Professor Jeremy Heis, Chair Assistant Professor Marcello Oreste Fiocco Professor Karl Schafer 2019 © 2019 Kourosh Christian Alizadeh DEDICATION To small things ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS v CURRICULUM VITAE vii ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION viii INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER 1: Kant’s Transcendental Unity of Apperception 7 Kant’s Primary Goals in the Critique 7 Kant’s Conception of Experience 12 The Transcendental Unity of Apperception 22 Kant’s Answer to Metaphysical Skepticism 35 Understanding and Reason 40 CHAPTER 2: Hegel’s Criticism of Kant 53 The Transcendental Unity of Apperception in German Idealism 55 The Restriction of the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 63 Three Other Hegelian Objections 77 Responses and Alternative Readings 96 Conclusion - The History of Philosophy 106 CHAPTER 3: Hegel’s Thought and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 109 Criticisms of Kant 110 Hegel’s Solution - Thought 114 The Hegelian Dialectic 132 Thought as the Successor to the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 148 Alternative Interpretation 160 CONCLUSION 175 BIBLIOGRAPHY 178 iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to express the deepest appreciation and gratitude to my central advisor, Associate Professor Jeremy Heis, who was my committee chair. He was my guide throughout the dissertation process from its tiny beginning as a comparison of Hegel and Wittgenstein to this, its culmination. His constant encouragement and well-articulated feedback were what made this dissertation possible, and I felt every day how lucky I was to have him as my mentor through this. I would also like to thank my committee members, Professor Karl Schafer and Associate Professor Marcello Oreste Fiocco. Karl was an invaluable aid in navigating the secondary literature, and his eye for detail and gentle manner helped me through many a conceptual tangle. I had been taking classes with Mark before I even officially enrolled at UCI, and while my dissertation ultimately went in a different direction, his approach to philosophy and focus on clean and clear writing were enormous positive influences on me. My work with him at the TH!NK program also opened my eyes to new perspectives on what philosophy is and how to share it with the world, and I thank him for that opportunity. In addition, I want to be sure to thank Professor Ermanno Bencivenga, whose writing on Kant and Hegel was crucial to my thinking on them, and whose reading group was a constant source of intellectual stimulation. Last, I want to thank all the people who supported me in non-academic ways, without whose help I would not have been able to even start this project, much less finish it: my father, who raised us all with philosophy from birth; my mother, whose unconditional love gave me the iv strength to carry through; my brother and sister, who were always cheering me on; my aunt Sharareh, who was a constant emotional support to me through all the difficult periods when I felt like giving up; the rest of my family, whose love of learning and care for one another inspired me and kept me going through the whole process; my partner Ashley, who made the jizzertation fun; my cohort-mates Adam Sanders, Dylan Popowicz, and Jacob Heim, who went through it all with me; Professor Candice Shelby at the University of Colorado, who encouraged my first steps into philosophy and made me feel I could actually do it; Sean Sanders, without whose late night conversations I don’t think I would have survived; Suz Michelle, who always supported my work and gave me the best advice; my UCI Libraries coworkers, with whom I worked through my entire graduate career, and who showed me that there was a world outside of academia; the Meme Chat crew, who showed me the only form of ethical consumption under capitalism; and all my magical friends - Bishop Bliss, Stephen Bretall, Nathan Puchalski, Tom Crowther, Denis McGovern, Daniel Wright, Chris Tolar, Ryan Borashan, Warren Doller, Kevin Kiang, Kevin Celinder, Mike Chung, Carter Barsh, Travis Young, Dylan Feeman, & Nicolas Johnson, among so many more. Finally, thank you also to the fish in the sea (and the sea itself) for being so stunningly beautiful at all times. v CURRICULUM VITAE Kourosh Christian Alizadeh 2012 B.A. summa cum laude in Philosophy, University of Colorado, Denver ​ ​ 2014-19 Graduate Student Assistant, UCI Libraries Department of Development 2015 Graduate Student Research Assistant, UCI Humanities Commons 2015-19 Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Irvine 2015-19 TH!NK Program Facilitator and Coordinator 2016 Graduate Student Research Assistant, UCI Humanities Commons 2016 M.A. in Philosophy, University of California, Irvine 2017 Humanities Out There Public Fellow, Santa Ana Public Libraries 2017-19 Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, California State University, Long Beach FIELD OF STUDY Kant, Hegel, German Idealism, Chinese and Japanese Philosophy vi ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Kant, Hegel, and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception By Kourosh Christian Alizadeh Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Irvine, 2019 Associate Professor Jeremy Heis, Chair This dissertation focuses on the transcendental unity of apperception in the work of two major German philosophers: Kant and Hegel. The transcendental unity of apperception was first described by Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason, where he gave it pride of place in his system of ​ ​ transcendental idealism. There, it was posited as a condition on the subject’s representations, such that they must form a necessary unity in order to constitute experience of an object. While Hegel does not make the phrase ‘transcendental unity of apperception’ a central one his work, he and other post-Kantian German idealists can be read as transforming this central Kantian insight. Specifically, as I argue in my second chapter, Hegel criticizes Kant’s construal of the unity of apperception as a condition among representations alone, and several commonly distinguished Hegelian criticisms of Kant can be understood as consequences of this central objection. Hegel’s criticism of Kant on this point also creates a valuable point of entry into his own sometimes-obscure positive philosophical claims. In the third chapter, I make use of this by identifying Hegel’s conception of Thought as the successor concept to the transcendental unity of apperception in Kant. By reading Thought as a transformation of the unity of apperception - a transformation that takes it from a condition on representations to a condition on reality as a vii whole - I am able to provide a reading of Hegel that does justice to his more metaphysically-loaded texts as well as to his claims to be doing properly post-Kantian metaphysics. viii 5/28/2019 Numbered Section - Google Docs INTRODUCTION “Kant and Hegel disagree on their answer to the question: what is the unity of apperception?”1 - Béatrice Longuenesse The aim of this dissertation is simple: to describe the transformation of an idea. More specifically, that idea is the transcendental unity of apperception originally put forward by Kant. My aim is to study how Hegel takes this idea and transforms it from a condition on the subject’s representations to a condition on reality as a whole.2 That Kant and Hegel are philosophers worthy of study is a claim that needs no defense; both could legitimately claim to among the most influential thinkers in history. Kant’s ideas, in particular, continue to be of importance 200 years after his death in fields as disparate as computer science, philosophy of perception, and metaethics. And while Hegel’s influence is perhaps less explicit, his ideas have impacted the vast majority of philosophers in the continental tradition, and the analytic tradition, too, was in part born out of Russell and Moore’s reaction to Hegel’s British disciples. And that is to say nothing of his student, Karl Marx, whose ideas have literally shaped the world in a quite tangible way. Perhaps more important, then, is the question: why the transcendental unity of apperception? This esoteric phrase disguises, with its obscure terminology, one of the most important concepts in Kant’s philosophy.3 Indeed, Kant himself describes it as “the supreme principle of all use of the understanding.”4 Yet it is less clear that the concept has anything to do with Hegel. To be sure, Hegel does describe it as “one of the most profound principles for 1 Longuenesse, Hegel’s Critique of Metaphysics, 187. 2 There is, in the second chapter, a brief consideration of other German Idealists and their approaches to the transcendental unity of apperception, but for the most part I focus entirely on these two philosophers. 3 The reader will, I hope, forgive me for not explaining what exactly this concept is just yet - that will be made more clear in the first chapter. At this point it is sufficient to simply note that it is explicitly one of Kant’s central concepts. The aim of this dissertation is to make clear the central role it plays in Hegel’s thought as well. 4 Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, B136. 1 https://docs.google.com/document/d/1PcVNX8zUYtlzMDaDon5LvoVEYUBcF_qrZ2AAljtTi2A/edit 1/182 5/28/2019 Numbered Section - Google Docs speculative development,” while at the same time claiming that Kant’s “further development, however, did not live up to this beginning.”5 But that in itself does not demonstrate that a study of the transcendental unity of apperception could have any bearing on Hegel’s positive philosophy. That such a connection does exist is something that I aim to demonstrate in the course of this dissertation.
Recommended publications
  • Pt: Must Translate By: 2
    Solution to Challenge 3 Start by using the description of the MPSC cipher and Hint 1. We have: pt: m u s t Translate by: 2 3 4 5 CT: P Y X Z What this tells you: 1. If “m” was shifted two to the right to arrive at “p”, the “n” or “o” must be missing in between them. That means that “n” or “o” (but not both) appear in the keyword. This assumes that “m” isn’t in the keyword, but since it lies two letters from “p” it looks like it is in the normal alphabetical sequence. 2. One of “v”, “w”, or “x” must also be in the keyword. (The keyword is not “kryptos” !). Again, this assumes that “u” is not in the keyword. 3. Once again, since “s” is about 4 letters from “x” in the normal alphabet, we assume that “s” and “x” are not in the keyword but appearing in alphabetical order. This agrees nicely with #2: “v” or “w” is in the keyword AND “t” and “u” are NOT in the keyword (since we need these letters to keep “s” and “x” 4 letters apart. 4. If “v” or “w” is in the keyword, this makes “t” 5 letters from “z” if “y” and “z” are not in the keyword. Then end of the alphabet line looks like: … m (n o ) p… s t u (v w) x y z where parentheses were used to indicate groupings where one letter is missing (and appears earlier in the keyword). In order to make further progress, one might start guessing at possible two letter words that could reasonably precede “must”: “we” and “it” come to mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Euripides” Johanna Hanink
    The Life of the Author in the Letters of “Euripides” Johanna Hanink N 1694, Joshua Barnes, the eccentric British scholar (and poet) of Greek who the next year would become Regius Professor at the University of Cambridge, published his I 1 long-awaited Euripidis quae extant omnia. This was an enormous edition of Euripides’ works which contained every scrap of Euripidean material—dramatic, fragmentary, and biographical —that Barnes had managed to unearth.2 In the course of pre- paring the volume, Barnes had got wind that Richard Bentley believed that the epistles attributed by many ancient manu- scripts to Euripides were spurious; he therefore wrote to Bentley asking him to elucidate the grounds of his doubt. On 22 February 1693, Bentley returned a letter to Barnes in which he firmly declared that, with regard to the ancient epistles, “tis not Euripides himself that here discourseth, but a puny sophist that acts him.” Bentley did, however, recognize that convincing others of this would be a difficult task: “as for arguments to prove [the letters] spurious, perhaps there are none that will convince any person that doth not discover it by himself.”3 1 On the printing of the book and its early distribution see D. McKitterick, A History of Cambridge University Press I Printing and the Book Trade in Cambridge, 1534–1698 (Cambridge 1992) 380–392; on Joshua Barnes see K. L. Haugen, ODNB 3 (2004) 998–1001. 2 C. Collard, Tragedy, Euripides and Euripideans (Bristol 2007) 199–204, re- hearses a number of criticisms of Barnes’ methods, especially concerning his presentation of Euripidean fragments (for which he often gave no source, and which occasionally consisted of lines from the extant plays).
    [Show full text]
  • All of a Sudden: the Role of Ἐξαίφνης in Plato's Dialogues
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 1-1-2014 All of a Sudden: The Role of Ἐξαιφ́ νης in Plato's Dialogues Joseph J. Cimakasky Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Cimakasky, J. (2014). All of a Sudden: The Role of Ἐξαιφ́ νης in Plato's Dialogues (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/68 This Worldwide Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Joseph Cimakasky May 2014 Copyright by Joseph Cimakasky 2014 ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES By Joseph Cimakasky Approved April 9, 2014 ________________________________ ________________________________ Ronald Polansky Patrick Lee Miller Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ________________________________ John W. McGinley Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ________________________________ ________________________________ James Swindal Ronald Polansky Dean, McAnulty College Chair, Philosophy Department Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES By Joseph Cimakasky May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Professor Ronald Polansky There are thirty-six appearances of the Greek word ἐξαίφνης in Plato’s dialogues.
    [Show full text]
  • The Practice of the Presence of God by Brother Lawrence
    The Practice of the Presence of God Brother Lawrence 2002 Edition Edited by Lightheart at PracticeGodsPresence.com Wheeler eBook Library Editor’s Preface Brother Lawrence was born Nicholas Herman around 1610 in Herimenil, Lorraine, a Duchy of France. His birth records were destroyed in a fire at his parish church during the Thirty Years War, a war in which he fought as a young soldier. It was also the war in which he sustained a near fatal injury to his sciatic nerve. The injury left him quite crippled and in chronic pain for the rest of his life. The details of his early life are few and sketchy. However, we know he was educated both at home and by his parish priest whose first name was Lawrence and who was greatly admired by the young Nicolas. He was well read and, from an early age, drawn to a spiritual life of faith and love for God. We also know that in the years between the abrupt end of his duties as a soldier and his entry into monastic life, he spent a period of time in the wilderness living like one of the early desert fathers. Also, prior to entering the monastery, and perhaps as preparation, he spent time as a civil servant. In his characteristic, self deprecating way, he mentions that he was a “footman who was clumsy and broke everything.” At mid-life he entered a newly established monastery in Paris where he became the cook for the community which grew to over one hundred members. After fifteen years, his duties were shifted to the sandal repair shop but, even then, he often returned to the busy kitchen to help out.
    [Show full text]
  • Hymns of Synesius of Cyrene in Their Christian and Platonist Context
    Hymns of Synesius of Cyrene in Their Christian and Platonist Context By Dachi Pachulia Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy Supervisor: István Bodnár Budapest, Hungary 2019 CEU eTD Collection i Abstract The thesis intends to promote the importance of Synesius of Cyrene as a thinker and a philosopher in general. First of all, this is achieved by stressing his influence on Proclus on the one hand and Pseudo-Dionysius on the other. Therefore, the thesis suggests, that in the Athenian philosophical school Christian Neoplatonist philosophers, such as Synesius were indeed read and discussed. The suggestion continues that it was under Proclus that the author of Dionysian corpus got acquainted with Synesius’ writings. But while Proclus was probably ignoring the Christian tenet of Synesius’ philosophy, Ps.-Dionysius held this very nature of Synesius’ thought the most important to “Christianize Proclus”, in other words to construct his own Christian metaphysical system to match it with the pagan counterpart. Thus, in the first chapter of the thesis, I stress the influence of Synesius’ hymns on Proclus’ hymns and Ps.-Dionysius’ letters. The second and third chapter of the thesis intends to further emphasize the uniqueness of Synesius’ thought. It starts with the rethinking of Theiler’s and Hadot’s thesis on Christian Platonist philosophers, who were denying the originality of their thought by making them dependent on Porphyry, the student of Plotinus. In the third chapter, I try to reconstruct the metaphysics of Synesius’ hymns concentrating on the anthropology of the hymns that I argue to be Christocentric in its nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Hidden Words
    Hidden Words Don’t put your head in the sand--try this tricky word brain teaser! Spell a hidden word by choosing the right letter for each clue. The hidden word is related to one of the clues. Hidden Word #1 1. The first letter is in ECHO but not NOISE. ______ 2. The second letter is in ACTOR but not SCRIPT. ______ 3. The third letter is in BIRD and in BRAIN. ______ 4. The fourth letter is in CORN but not COB. ______ 5. The fifth letter is in NICE and in KIND. ______ 6. The sixth letter is in EVENING but not MORNING. ______ 7. The seventh letter is in TRAPEZE but not TIGHTROPE. ______ 8. The eighth letter is in LAKE but not STREAM. ______ Answer: ________________ Hidden Word #2 1. The first letter is in ASLEEP but not AWAKE. ______ (SLP) 2. The second letter is in PEACH but not CHERRY. ______ (AP) 3. The third letter is in UNCLE and in AUNT. ______ (N) 4. The fourth letter is in TIGER but not JUNGLE. ______ (TIR) 5. The fifth letter is in SHIP and in SHORE. ______ (SH) 6. The sixth letter is in EARLY and in LATE. ______ (LAE) 7. The seventh letter is in ARMY but not NAVY. ______ (RM) Answer: ________________ Hidden Word #3 1. The first letter is in BREEZE but not BLOW. ______ (REZ) 2. The second letter is in SQUASH but not SPINACH. ______ (QU) 3. The third letter is CUB but not BEAR. ______ (CU) 4. The fourth letter is in PITCH and in CATCH.
    [Show full text]
  • Dooyeweerd's Second Letter to the Curators October 12, 1937
    Dooyeweerd’s Second Letter to the Curators October 12, 1937 [Draft] Translated and annotated for study purposes only by Dr. J. Glenn Friesen The text below is a provisional translation. Copyright is held by the Dooyeweerd Centre, Ancaster, Ontario, and publishing right is held by Mellen Press, Lewiston, New York. A definitive translation will be published in the series The Collected Works of Herman Dooyeweerd. Notes: This long letter, a copy of which was in the Dooyeweerd Archives in Amsterdam, bears a date of April 27, 1937, although the last page bears the date of October 12, 1937, with Dooyeweerd’s signature. April 27, 1937 is the date of Dooyeweerd’s First Letter to the Curators. It therefore seems that he had prepared this extensive reply, but chose to send his first four page letter in April instead. A comparison with excerpts from this letter in Verburg (Verburg, 219) indicate that what I have translated here is a draft, since there are some differences from what Verburg has cited. The differences, at least in the passages I have compared, appear to be stylistic and not substantial. A full comparison needs to be made with the copy of the letter received by the Curators, presumably in the Curators Archive. In the meantime, I thought it important to make this version available, since it contains so much information of interest to Dooyeweerd scholars. Dooyeweerd’s italics are shown as underlining in the original letter. The pdf version maintains that underlining; this online version changes the underlining to italics. All footnotes are by Dooyeweerd himself except where indicated otherwise by my initials JGF.
    [Show full text]
  • ONE-LETTER WORDS a Dictionary for M
    www.IELTS4U.blogfa.com www.IELTS4U.blogfa.com CRAIG CONLEY ONE-LETTER WORDS A Dictionary www.IELTS4U.blogfa.com For M. T. Wentz The conquest of the superfluous gives us greater spiritual excitement than the conquest of the necessary. — Gaston Bachelard, French philosopher www.IELTS4U.blogfa.com www.IELTS4U.blogfa.com www.IELTS4U.blogfa.comINTRODUCTION WHEN THE WORDS GET IN THE WAY Ninety- nine down: a one letter word meaning something indefi nite. The indefinite article or—would it perhaps be the personal pronoun? But what runs across it? Four letter word meaning something With a bias towards its opposite, the second letter Must be the same as the one letter word. It is time We left these puzzles and started to be ourselves. And started to live, is it not? —Louis MacNeice, Solstices e live in a world of mass communication. As you read this, words are staring you W in the face. But they’re not the only ones. Miles above you, words are flown in jets across the country and over the oceans. They are www.IELTS4U.blogfa.comtossed at 5 a.m. on newspaper routes. They are deliv- ered six days a week by mail carriers. They’re propped up on display at book stores. They’re bouncing off satellites and showing up on television and cell phone screens. We are constantly bombarded by language pollution. And these empty words are overwhelming. Either they scream out to be noticed (as in TV commercials), or they hide in small print (at the bottom of contracts), or they bury their meaning behind jargon (generated by computers and bureaucracy).
    [Show full text]
  • Politics, Philosophy, Writing : Plato's Art of Caring for Souls
    Politics, Philosophy, Writing: Plato's Art of Caring for Souls Zdravko Planinc, Editor University of Missouri Press Politics, Philosophy, Writing This page intentionally left blank Politics, Philosophy, Writing i PLATO’S ART OF CARING FOR SOULS Edited with an Introduction by Zdravko Planinc University of Missouri Press Columbia and London Copyright © 2001 by The Curators of the University of Missouri University of Missouri Press, Columbia, Missouri 65201 Printed and bound in the United States of America All rights reserved 54321 0504030201 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Politics, philosophy, writing : Plato’s art of caring for souls / edited by Zdravko Planinc. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-8262-1343-X (alk. paper) 1. Plato. I. Planinc, Zdravko, 1953– B395 .P63 2001 184—dc21 00-066603 V∞™ This paper meets the requirements of the American National Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, Z39.48, 1984. Designer: Kristie Lee Typesetter: The Composing Room of Michigan, Inc. Printer and Binder: The Maple-Vail Book Manufacturing Group Typeface: Minion For Alexander Tessier This page intentionally left blank Contents Introduction 1 Zdravko Planinc Soulcare and Soulcraft in the Charmides Toward a Platonic Perspective 11 Horst Hutter Shame in the Apology 42 Oona Eisenstadt The Strange Misperception of Plato’s Meno 60 Leon Craig “A Lump Bred Up in Darknesse” Two Tellurian Themes of the Republic 80 Barry Cooper Homeric Imagery in Plato’s Phaedrus 122 Zdravko Planinc “One, Two, Three, but Where Is the Fourth?” Incomplete Mediation in the Timaeus 160 Kenneth Dorter Mystic Philosophy in Plato’s Seventh Letter 179 James M.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Aesthetic Education of Man in a Series of Letters, Published by Yale University Press, New Haven, Connecticut, in 1954
    Bibliographical Note This Dover edition, first published in 2004, is an unabridged republication of On the Aesthetic Education of Man in a Series of Letters, published by Yale University Press, New Haven, Connecticut, in 1954. The work was originally published in 1795. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Schiller, Friedrich, 1759—1805. [Über die ästhetische Erziehung des Menschen in einer Reihe von Briefen. English] On the aesthetic education of man / Friedrich Schiller ; translated with an introduction by Reginald Snell. p. cm. Originally published: New Haven : Yale University Press, 1954. Includes index. 9780486117393 1. Aesthetics, Modern—18th century. I. Snell, Reginald. II. Title. BH183.S25 2004 111’.85—dc22 2004050046 Manufactured in the United States by Courier Corporation 43739605 www.doverpublications.com Table of Contents Title Page Bibliographical Note Copyright Page Introduction On the Aesthetic Education of Man First Letter Second Letter Third Letter Fourth Letter Fifth Letter Sixth Letter Seventh Letter Eighth Letter Ninth Letter Tenth Letter Eleventh Letter Twelfth Letter Thirteenth Letter Fourteenth Letter Fifteenth Letter Sixteenth Letter Seventeenth Letter Eighteenth Letter Nineteenth Letter Twentieth Letter Twenty-first Letter Twenty-second Letter Twenty-third Letter Twenty-fourth Letter Twenty-fifth Letter Twenty-sixth Letter Twenty-seventh Letter Index A CATALOG OF SELECTED DOVER BOOKS IN ALL FIELDS OF INTEREST Introduction IT may help the general reader to a fuller understanding of these important and not always easy Letters if they are first set before him in their proper historical and philosophical context. In one sense, to be sure, they need neither explanation nor commentary; they were published without the help of either—but the time and the circumstances of their publication provided both.
    [Show full text]
  • Ficino, Plato's Second Letter, and Its Four Epistolary
    MICHAEL J. B. ALLEN SENDING ARCHEDEMUS: FICINO, PLATO’S SECOND LETTER, AND ITS FOUR EPISTOLARY MYSTERIES Though now relegated to the status of being a spurious, or at best, a dubious text of Plato’s, the Second Letter has had a distinguished history,1 particularly and predictably so among the ancient Neoplatonists and those they inspired in the Renaissance.2 Most notably Plotinus’s Enneads invoke its enigma at 312DE three times (1.8.2, 5.1.8, 6.7.42); and Proclus glosses it in detail in his Theologia platonica 2.8-9, as does Marsilio Ficino, their Florentine disciple, on several occasions. For a mere letter it has made a signal contribution and this in itself should give us pause: perhaps our whole notion of a letter as a medium for philosophical formulation is in need of some revision, and par- ticularly when we recall the extraordinary contributions in antiquity of St. Paul’s and Seneca’s letters (real and spurious) and in the Quattrocento of Ficino’s letters, not to mention those of Leibniz and of many other thinkers subsequently. This paper dedicated to Eckhard, our distinguished peripatetic colleague and friend, is going to examine Ficino’s introduction (argumentum) for his translation of Plato’s Second Letter. There are several reasons it deserves our scrutiny: first it not only takes up the most famous enigma in the canon (or certainly one of the most famous), but also identifies three other enigmas or mysteries in the same letter. Next it provides us in the process with four per- 1 Scholars now seem agreed on its inauthenticity; see Norman Gulley, “The Authenticity of the Platonic Epistles,” in Pseudepigrapha 1, Entretiens sur l’antiquité classique 18 (Vandoeuv- res-Geneva, 1972), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Genesis Treasure Hunt Worksheet God Saw All That He Had Made, And
    Genesis Treasure Hunt 1 Genesis Treasure Hunt Worksheet God saw all that He had made, and it was very good. [Gen. 1:31] Secret Verse: ________ ________ ________ ________ ________ ________ ________, ________ ________ ________ ________ ________. 1. For the first word take the first three letters of the first password. 2. For the second word take the fifth, eighth, and tenth letters from the first password. 3. For the third word take the fourth, fifth, and seventh letters from the second password. 4. For the fourth word take the second, third, seventh, and eleventh letters from the third password. 5. For the fifth word take the third and eight letters from the fourth password. 6. For the sixth word take the sixth, ninth and tenth letters from the fifth password. 7. For the seventh word take the third, fourth, fifth and ninth letters of the sixth password. 8. For the eight word take the first, fifth and seventh letters of the seventh password. 9. For the ninth word take the tenth and twelfth letters of the seventh password. 10. For the tenth word take the third, ninth and twelfth letters of the eighth password. 11. For the eleventh word take the third, fourth, eighth and eleventh letters of the ninth password. 12. For the twelfth word take the third, sixth, eighth and ninth letters of the tenth password. PAGE 1 God saw 1. Was the Flood local or global? global 7:19, 24 2. What was Leahʼs daughterʼs name? Dinah 3. What was Sarahʼs name to begin with? Sarai 4.
    [Show full text]