Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition from Alcmaeon to Aristotle

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition from Alcmaeon to Aristotle The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924014363182 Cornell University Library BF 91.B36 1906a Greek theories of elementary cognition f 3 1924 014 363 182 This "0-P Book" Is an Authorized Reprint of the Original Edition, Produced by Microfilm-Xerography by University Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan, 1965 GREEK THEORIES OF ELEMENTARY COGNITION FROM ALCMAEON TO ARISTOTLE BY #+ JOHN ^BEARE, M.A. FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, DUBLIN REGIUS PROFESSOR OF GREEK (SOMETIME PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY) IN THE UNIVERSITY OF DUBLIN OXFORD AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1906 IIPK I IRRflPV «.#rr 354 ^b 21& I Eeare, John Isaac, d. 1918. Greek theories of elementary cognition from Alcmaeon to Aristotle, by John I. Beare ... Oxford, The Clarendon press, 1906. Til. 354 pl' 23-- "Commentaries, monographs, 4c. used" : p. i»i-vtl. 1. Psychology—Hist 2. Senses and sensation. S. Philosophy, An- cient l Title. 7—28078 Library of Congress BF91.B3 i«gl, HENRY FROWDE, MJL PUBLISHER TO THK UNIVERSITY OP OXFORD LONDON, EDINBURGH NEW YORK AND TORONTO PREFACE MOST readers know the difficulty as well as imp. rtance of the de Anima and Parva Naturalia of Aristotle; and any genuine assistance would be welcomed by students who desire to master them. A great deal has been done by editors and others for the elucidation of the former of these works and, indirectly, of the latter, so far as they involve meta- physics, or psychology in its higher reaches. No one.however, has been at the pains to glean and put together systema- tically, from Aristotle himself and his predecessors, whatever may explain or illustrate the parts of his writings essentially concerned with empirical psychology. The results of this, it should seem, would be useful not only to students of ancient Greek psychology, but also to readers who, perhaps knowing and caring little about Greek, might yet desire a clear and objective, even if brief, account of what was achieved for the psychology of the senses by the ancient Greek philoso- phers. The purpose of this book, within the limits defined by its title, is to present such an account; and it will rightly be judged according to the degree in which it fulfils its purpose. Among its most competent critics will be the student who may test its usefulness in connexion with the many passages on the interpretation of which it directly or indirectly bears. To such critics and others its author leaves it ; confiding less, however, in the merits of his work than in the fellow-feeling which all scholars, as well as students of philosophy, have for one who honestly grapples with their common foe, to acrcupts, in whatever form this may present itself. The books used or consulted are named in the list given 159967 ; iv PREFACE below ; but wherever even a hint has been borrowed, the writer to whom obligation has been thus incurred will always be found referred to in the notes. There are many such references, especially to the publications of H. Diels but the mainstay of the whole work has been the actual text of Plato, Aristotle, and Theophrastus. A list of the Greek passages explained or discussed has been added at the end. In some—perhaps most—of these the points raised are of no great interest to scholars, but there is at least one exception ; and it is hoped that what has been said on Arist. 45a 1" 17-24 may be of some value. The author wishes to thank the Delegates of the Claren- don Press for undertaking the publication of this work. His thanks are also due to the Press Reader and Staff for their great care and accuracy. It remains for him, in con- clusion, to express his deep gratitude to Mr. W. D. Ross, Fellow and Tutor of Oriel College, Oxford, for kindly reading the proofs, and making acute suggestions from which much profit has been derived. He is indebted to Mr. Ross for having drawn his attention to Diels' b palaeographical correction of Arist. 985 17, mentioned on p. 37, n. a. 9 Trinity College, Dublin, January 10, 1 906. COMMENTARIES, MONOGRAPHS, &c. USED FOR THE FOLLOWING WORK Adam, J. Plato, Republic (Cambridge, 1903). Alexander of Aphrodisias in Arist. De Sensu, Thurot (.Paris, 1875). „ „ „ „ Wendland (Berolini, 1901). ,, „ „ Metaph. Hayduck ( „ 1891). 1S87). i, „ „ De Anima, Bruns ( „ „ „ „ Quaestiones etc. Bruns ( „ 1892). Archer-Hind, R. D. Plato, Phaedo, ed. 2 (London and New York, 1894). „ „ Timaeus (London and New York, 1888). Bacon, R. Opus Mains, Bridges (Oxford, 1899). Baumker, C. Des Aristoteles Lehre von den dussern und innern Sinnesvermogen (Leipzig, 1877). * b „ Zu Aristot. ' De Sensu 2, 438 16 ff. (Zeitsch.f. d. bst. Gymn., Sept. 1877, 603 ff.). Beck, H. Aristoteles de Sensuum Actione (Berlin, i860). Becker, Guil. Ad. Aristoteles de somno el vigilia etc. (Lipsiae, 1823). Biehl, Guil. Aristotelis Parva Naturalia (Teubner, 1898). Bitterauf, C. Quaestiunculae Criticae ad Par. Nat. (Monachii, 1900). Bocckb, A. Philolaos des Pythagoreers Lehren (Berlin, 1819). Bonitz, H. Aristotelis Metaphysica (Bonnae, 1848). „ Aristotelische Studien (Wien, 1862-7). Brentano, F. Die Psychologie des Arist. (Mainz, 1867). Burnet, J. Early Greek Philosophy (London and Edinburgh, 1892). Bury, R. G. Plato's Philebus (Cambridge, 1897). Bywater, I. Heracliti Epliesii Reliquiae (Oxford, 1877). Campbell, L. Plato, Sophistes (Oxford, 1867). „ „ Theaetetus ( „ 1883). Chappell, W. History of Music, vol. i (London, 1874). Dembowski ,J. Quaestiones Aristotelicae duae (Regimonti Pr. (sic), 1881). Diels, H. Doxographi Graeci (Berolini, 1879). „ Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (Berlin, 1903). Eberhard, E. Die aristotelische Definition der Seele etc. (Berlin, 1868). Freudenthal, J. Zur Kritik und Exegese von Aristot. irtpl tu» mmk»i> o&ijurrot Ktii V"'*'^ (Rhein. Mus. xxtv, pp. 81-93, 392-419)- ,, Ueber den Begriff des Wortes (pavrmrla bei Arist. (Gottingcn, 1863). „ Zu Aristot. ' De Mem.' 452* 17 ff. (Archiv /. Gesch. der Phil., II. Band, i. Heft, 1889). Freytag, W. Di« Entwickclung der griechischen Erktnntmstheorie bis Aristoteles (Halle, 1905). vi COMMENTARIES, MONOGRAPHS, &C Galenus, Claudius. De Placitis Hippocratis et Platonis, I. Mtiller (Lipsiae, 1874). Godenius, R. Libelli Aristotelis de Sensu et Sensilibus castigata versio et analysis logica (Francofurti, 1 596). Gomperz, T. Greek Thinkers (E. Tr.) (London, 1905). Gorland, A. Aristoteles und die Mathetnatrk (Marburg, 1899). Grote, G. Aristotle, 3rd ed. (London, 1883). „ Plato and the other Companions of Socrates (London, 1875). Hammond, W. A. Aristotle's Psychology: De Anima and Parva Naturalia, transl. with introduction and notes (London and New York, 1902). Hayduck, M. Emendationes Aristoteleae (Meldorf, 1877). „ Observations criticae in aliquot locos A rist. (Greifswald, 1873)- Hippocratis Opera. E. Littre* (Paris, 1839-61). Ideler, J. L. Aristot. Metcorologica (Lipsiae, 1834-6). von Jan, C. Musici Scriptores Graeci (Lipsiae, 1895). Jourdain, C. Recherches critiques sur tAge et forigine des traductions latines d'Aristote, Nouv. id. (Paris, 1 843). Kampe, F. F. Die Erkenntnisstheorie des Aristoteles (Leipzig, 1870). Karsten, S. Empedoclis Agrig. Cartn. reliquiae (Amstelodami, 1838). Marchl, P. Des Arist. Lehre von der Tierseele, i. Teil (Beilage zum Jahresberichte des Iiumanistischen Gymnasiums (Metten, 1896-7)). Michaelis Ephesius. In Arist. Parva Naturalia, Wendland (Berolini, 1903). Mullach, F. W. A. Democriti Abderitae Fragtnenta (Berolini, 1843). „ Fragtnenta Philosophorum Graecorum (Parisiis, 1857-79). Neuhauser, J. Aristoteles Lehre von dem sinnlichen Erkenntnissver- m'dgen und seinen Organen (Leipzig, 1878). Ogle, Dr. W. Aristotle on the Parts of Animals, trans, and annot. (London, 1882). „ Aristotle on Youth and Age etc., trans, and annot. (London, 1 897). Pacius, J. Aristotelis Parva (ut vocant) Naturalia (Francofurti, 1601). Panzerbieter, F. Diogenes Apollonialcs (Lipsiae, 1830). Philippson, L. uXij av8pam'ivi\ (Berlin, 1831). Poschenrieder, F. Die naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften des Arist. in ihrem Verhaltnis su den Biichern der hippokratischen Sammlung (Bamberg, 1887). Prantl, C. Aristoteles iiber die Farben (Munchen, 1849). Ritter and Preller. Pontes Philosophiae, Ed. 7 (Gothae, 1886). Rohde, E. Psyche, Ed. 3. (Tubingen u. Leipzig, 1903). Schaubach, E. Anaxagorae Clazomenii Fragtnenta (Lipsiae, 1 827). Schieboldt, F. O. De Imagination Disquisitio ex Arist. Libris repetita (Lipsiae, 1S82). COMMENTARIES, MONOGRAPHS, &c. vii Schmidt, J. Aristotelis et Herbarti Praecepta, quae ad Psychologiam spectant, inter se comparantur (Wien, 1887). Siebeck, H. Geschichte der Psychologie, 1. Teil, I. Abt. (Gotha, 1880). „ Aristotelis et Herbarti doctrinae psychological etc. (Halis Sax. 1872). Simonius, S. Arist. de Sensu et de Metnoria (Genevae, 1566). Sperling, K. Aristoteles' Ansicht von der psychologischen Bedeutung der Zeit als 'Zakl der Bewegung' (Marburg, 1888). Stein, H. Empedoclis Agrigentini Fragmenta (Bonnae, 1852). Stewart, J. A. Notes on Aristotle's ' Nicomachean Ethics' (Oxford, 1892). Sturz, F. G. Empedocles Agrigenfinus (Lipsiae, 1805). Susemihl, F. Various 'Scholae' on passages in Aristotle (Greifswald). Themistius (Sophonias). In Arist. Parva Naturalia, Wendland (Bcrolini, 1 903). Theophrastus Eresius. Op. Omn. Wimmer (Parisiis, 1866). Thurot, C. Etudes sur Artstote (Paris, i860). Torstrik, Ad. Arist. de Anima (Berolini, 1862). Trendelenburg-Belger. Arist. de Anima (Berolini, 1877). Usener, H. Efncurea (Lipsiae, 1887). Volprecht, A. Die physiologischen
Recommended publications
  • 'Pythagorean' Kingship Treatises
    Meeting Different Needs The Implied Readers ofthe ‘Pythagorean’ Kingship Treatises Michael Trapp To cite this version: Michael Trapp. Meeting Different Needs The Implied Readers of the ‘Pythagorean’ Kingship Treatises. KTÈMA Civilisations de l’Orient, de la Grèce et de Rome antiques, Université de Strasbourg, 2020, Les traités néopythagoriciens Sur la royauté, 45, pp.143-160. halshs-03071732 HAL Id: halshs-03071732 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-03071732 Submitted on 16 Dec 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. KTÈMA KTÈMA KTÈMA CIVILISATIONS DE L’ORIENT, DE LA GRÈCE ET DE ROME ANTIQUES CIVILISATIONS DE L’ORIENT, DE LA GRÈCE ET DE ROME ANTIQUES KTÈMA est une revue annuelle de recherche consacrée à l’histoire, l’archéologie et la littérature de la Grèce, de Rome, de l’Égypte et du Les traités néopythagoriciens Sur la royauté Proche-Orient antiques. Fondée en 1976 par Edmond Frézouls et Anne Gangloff Introduction ..............................................................................................................................5
    [Show full text]
  • De Theognide Megarensi. Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara. a Bilingual Edition
    FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE De Theognide Megarensi Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara – A Bilingual Edition – Translated by R. M. Kerr THE NIETZSCHE CHANNEL Friedrich Nietzsche De Theognide Megarensi Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara A bilingual edition Translated by R. M. Kerr ☙ editio electronica ❧ _________________________________________ THE N E T ! " # H E # H A N N E $ % MM&' Copyright © Proprietas interpretatoris Roberti Martini Kerrii anno 2015 Omnia proprietatis iura reservantur et vindicantur. Imitatio prohibita sine auctoris permissione. Non licet pecuniam expetere pro aliquo, quod partem horum verborum continet; liber pro omnibus semper gratuitus erat et manet. Sic rerum summa novatur semper, et inter se mortales mutua vivunt. augescunt aliae gentes, aliae invuntur, inque brevi spatio mutantur saecla animantum et quasi cursores vitai lampada tradiunt. - Lucretius - - de Rerum Natura, II 5-! - PR"#$CE %e &or' presente( here is a trans)ation o* #rie(rich Nietzsche-s aledi!tionsarbeit ./schoo) e0it-thesis12 *or the "andesschule #$orta in 3chu)p*orta .3axony-$nhalt) presente( on 3epte4ber th 15678 It has hitherto )arge)y gone unnotice(, especial)y in anglophone Nietzsche stu(- ies8 $t the ti4e though, the &or' he)pe( to estab)ish the reputation o* the then twenty year o)( Nietzsche and consi(erab)y *aci)itate( his )ater acade4ic career8 9y a)) accounts, it &as a consi(erab)e achie:e4ent, especial)y consi(ering &hen it &as &ri;en: it entai)e( an e0pert 'no&)e(ge, not =ust o* c)assical-phi)o)ogical )iterature, but also o* co(ico)ogy8 %e recent =u(ge4ent by >"+3"+ .2017<!!2< “It is a piece that, ha( Nietzsche ne:er &ri;en another &or(, &ou)( ha:e assure( his p)ace, albeit @uite a s4a)) one, in the history o* Ger4an phi)o)ogyB su4s the 4atter up quite e)o@uently8 +ietzsche )ater continue( his %eognis stu(ies, the sub=ect o* his Crst scho)ar)y artic)e, as a stu(ent at Leip,ig, in 156 D to so4e e0tent a su44ary o* the present &or' D a critical re:ie& in 156!, as &e)) as @uotes in se:eral )e;ers *ro4 1567 on.
    [Show full text]
  • Royal Power, Law and Justice in Ancient Macedonia Joseph Roisman
    Royal Power, Law and Justice in Ancient Macedonia Joseph Roisman In his speech On the Crown Demosthenes often lionizes himself by suggesting that his actions and policy required him to overcome insurmountable obstacles. Thus he contrasts Athens’ weakness around 346 B.C.E. with Macedonia’s strength, and Philip’s II unlimited power with the more constrained and cumbersome decision-making process at home, before asserting that in spite of these difficulties he succeeded in forging later a large Greek coalition to confront Philip in the battle of Chaeronea (Dem.18.234–37). [F]irst, he (Philip) ruled in his own person as full sovereign over subservient people, which is the most important factor of all in waging war . he was flush with money, and he did whatever he wished. He did not announce his intentions in official decrees, did not deliberate in public, was not hauled into the courts by sycophants, was not prosecuted for moving illegal proposals, was not accountable to anyone. In short, he was ruler, commander, in control of everything.1 For his depiction of Philip’s authority Demosthenes looks less to Macedonia than to Athens, because what makes the king powerful in his speech is his freedom from democratic checks. Nevertheless, his observations on the Macedonian royal power is more informative and helpful than Aristotle’s references to it in his Politics, though modern historians tend to privilege the philosopher for what he says or even does not say on the subject. Aristotle’s seldom mentions Macedonian kings, and when he does it is for limited, exemplary purposes, lumping them with other kings who came to power through benefaction and public service, or who were assassinated by men they had insulted.2 Moreover, according to Aristotle, the extreme of tyranny is distinguished from ideal kingship (pambasilea) by the fact that tyranny is a government that is not called to account.
    [Show full text]
  • The Date of the First Pythiad-Again Alden A
    MOSSHAMMER, ALDEN A., The Date of the First Pythiad - Again , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 23:1 (1982:Spring) p.15 The Date of the First Pythiad-Again Alden A. Mosshammer OST HISTORIANS have long agreed that the first in the regular M series of Pythian festivals celebrated every four years at Del­ phi took place in 58211. Now H. C. Bennett and more re­ cently S. G. Miller have argued that we should instead follow Pausa­ nias in dating the first Pythiad to 586/5, because the Pindaric scho­ liasts, they maintain, reckon Pythiads from that year. 1 The debate is an old one, but it has important implications for our understanding of the sequence of events at the time of the First Sacred War. Bennett and Miller have rightly criticized the excessive claims that have been made for some of the evidence; and Miller, in particular, has offered some important new insights into the problem. The argument in favor of 58211 nevertheless remains the stronger case. It needs to be presented once again, both to take these new objections into account and to elucidate the tradition that has given rise to the debate. I. The Problem According to the Parian Marble, our earliest evidence (264/3), the Amphictyons celebrated a victory against Cirrha by dedicating a por­ tion of the spoils as prizes for a chrematitic festival celebrated in 59110, and again the games became stephani tic in 582/1. 2 Pausanias 1 H. C. BENNETT, "On the Systemization of Scholia Dates for Pindar's Pythian Odes," HSCP 62 (1957) 61-78; STEPHEN G.
    [Show full text]
  • Marathon 2,500 Years Edited by Christopher Carey & Michael Edwards
    MARATHON 2,500 YEARS EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS BULLETIN OF THE INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SUPPLEMENT 124 DIRECTOR & GENERAL EDITOR: JOHN NORTH DIRECTOR OF PUBLICATIONS: RICHARD SIMPSON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS PROCEEDINGS OF THE MARATHON CONFERENCE 2010 EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON 2013 The cover image shows Persian warriors at Ishtar Gate, from before the fourth century BC. Pergamon Museum/Vorderasiatisches Museum, Berlin. Photo Mohammed Shamma (2003). Used under CC‐BY terms. All rights reserved. This PDF edition published in 2019 First published in print in 2013 This book is published under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- NoDerivatives (CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0) license. More information regarding CC licenses is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Available to download free at http://www.humanities-digital-library.org ISBN: 978-1-905670-81-9 (2019 PDF edition) DOI: 10.14296/1019.9781905670819 ISBN: 978-1-905670-52-9 (2013 paperback edition) ©2013 Institute of Classical Studies, University of London The right of contributors to be identified as the authors of the work published here has been asserted by them in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Designed and typeset at the Institute of Classical Studies TABLE OF CONTENTS Introductory note 1 P. J. Rhodes The battle of Marathon and modern scholarship 3 Christopher Pelling Herodotus’ Marathon 23 Peter Krentz Marathon and the development of the exclusive hoplite phalanx 35 Andrej Petrovic The battle of Marathon in pre-Herodotean sources: on Marathon verse-inscriptions (IG I3 503/504; Seg Lvi 430) 45 V.
    [Show full text]
  • ANDREW COLLINS, Callisthenes on Olympias and Alexander's Divine
    Callisthenes on Olympias and Alexander’s Divine Birth Andrew Collins The proclamation of Alexander’s divine sonship at Siwah is universally acknowledged to have been of great importance to the steps that led to his later demand for divine honours. But the issue of whether Alexander already held a belief that he was son of a god before he travelled to Siwah is an equally important research question. Already a number of scholars have argued that Alexander believed in his divine sonship before Egypt,1 and I wish to strengthen that case in this paper by arguing that Arrian, Anabasis 4.10.2—a passage ascribing to Callisthenes a remark about Olympias’ stories concerning Alexander’s divine birth—has a greater claim to historicity than has hitherto been thought. First, some prefatory remarks on the notion of divine sonship are pertinent. Alexander’s assertion of divine sonship during his life did not make him a true god or fully divine in Greek thought or culture.2 For the Greeks, a man fathered by a god with a human mother during his lifetime was rather like a demigod of Homeric myth, on a par with the heroes of the mythic times, such as Heracles, Perseus and the Dioscuri. Homer, above all, uses the word “hero” of his living warriors, a subset of whom were sons of one divine and one human parent.3 The child of such a union was not an Olympian god, with the attributes and supernatural powers of the cosmic deities. One must also distinguish between the hero conceived as (1) a living man who was the son of a god (the sense in which the word is used by Homer), and (2) the hero as a powerful spirit of a dead human being, who received 1 E.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • An Examination of the Political Philosophy of Plutarch's Alexander
    “If I were not Alexander…” An Examination of the Political Philosophy of Plutarch’s Alexander- Caesar Richard Buckley-Gorman A thesis submitted to Victoria University of Wellington in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Classics 2016 School of Art History, Classics and Religious Studies 1 | P a g e Table of Contents Acknowledgements…………………………………………………………………………………………3 Abstract…………………………………………………………………………………………………………..4 Introduction…………………………………………………………………………………………………….5 Chapter One: Plutarch’s Methodology…………………………………………………………….8 Chapter Two: The Alexander………………………………………………………………………….18 Chapter Three: Alexander and Caesar……………………………………………………………47 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………………………………….71 Bibliography………………………………………………………………………………………………….73 2 | P a g e Acknowledgements Firstly and foremost to my supervisor Jeff Tatum, for his guidance and patience. Secondly to my office mates James, Julia, Laura, Nikki, and Tim who helped me when I needed it and made research and writing more fun and less productive than it would otherwise have been. I would also like to thank my parents, Sue and Phil, for their continuous support. 3 | P a g e Abstract This thesis examines Plutarch’s Alexander-Caesar. Plutarch’s depiction of Alexander has been long recognised as encompassing many defects, including an overactive thumos and a decline in character as the narrative progresses. In this thesis I examine the way in which Plutarch depicts Alexander’s degeneration, and argue that the defects of Alexander form a discussion on the ethics of kingship. I then examine the implications of pairing the Alexander with the Caesar; I examine how some of the themes of the Alexander are reflected in the Caesar. I argue that the status of Caesar as both a figure from the Republican past and the man who established the Empire gave the pair a unique immediacy to Plutarch’s time.
    [Show full text]
  • ELECTRYONE ΗΛΕΚΤΡΥΩΝΗ Theognis and the Social Role of Measure
    ELECTRYONE ΗΛΕΚΤΡΥΩΝΗ Theognis and the Social Role of Measure. Matus Porubjak, University of Ss. Cyril and Methodius in Trnava ABSTRACT: The paper deals with the beginnings of the Greek ethical discourse in elegies of an archaic lyric poet Theognis of Megara. In the introduction author shortly discusses the question of origin and influence of the Theognidea. Then he gradually follows and interprets the occurrences of the expression “μηδὲν ἄγαν” (Nothing in excess), of the words σωφροσύνη (soundness of mind), σάοφρων (temperate), μέτρον (measure) and μέτριος (moderate), according to the problem of ἀρετή (excellence). On the basis of symposium description in the Theognidea and its functions, author shows the crucial social dimension of researched capabilities. He also tries to show how Theognis grasps the wisdom as a quality that has to be tried for and cared for. In the end author states that for Theognis the excellences such as wisdom, justice, sound mind and proper measure are conditio sine qua non for functioning of all social relations – from erotic relations through symposium to polis itself. KEY-WORDS: Theognis, Solon, temperate, measure, moderate, excellence, justice, wisdom, polis, social behaviour According to the interpretative tradition Socrates followed two Delphic maxims: “γνῶθι σαυτὸν” (Know thyself) and “μηδὲν ἄγαν”(Nothing in excess). These two maxims were so determinative for discourse of ancient philosophy and ethics (including Hellenic) that the whole ancient ethics could be in a simplified way understood as an effort to their reinterpretation and practical application. The aim of this study is to notice some aspects of beginnings of this discourse in elegies of an archaic lyric poet Theognis of Megara, in particular of the maxim “Nothing in excess”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fragments of the Poem of Parmenides
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by D-Scholarship@Pitt RESTORING PARMENIDES’ POEM: ESSAYS TOWARD A NEW ARRANGEMENT OF THE FRAGMENTS BASED ON A REASSESSMENT OF THE ORIGINAL SOURCES by Christopher John Kurfess B.A., St. John’s College, 1995 M.A., St. John’s College, 1996 M.A., University of Hawai‘i at Mānoa, 2000 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of The Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2012 UNVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH The Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences This dissertation was presented by Christopher J. Kurfess It was defended on November 8, 2012 and approved by Dr. Andrew M. Miller, Professor, Department of Classics Dr. John Poulakos, Associate Professor, Department of Communication Dr. Mae J. Smethurst, Professor, Department of Classics Dissertation Supervisor: Dr. Edwin D. Floyd, Professor, Department of Classics ii Copyright © by Christopher J. Kurfess 2012 iii RESTORING PARMENIDES’ POEM Christopher J. Kurfess, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2012 The history of philosophy proper, claimed Hegel, began with the poem of the Presocratic Greek philosopher Parmenides. Today, that poem is extant only in fragmentary form, the various fragments surviving as quotations, translations or paraphrases in the works of better-preserved authors of antiquity. These range from Plato, writing within a century after Parmenides’ death, to the sixth-century C.E. commentator Simplicius of Cilicia, the latest figure known to have had access to the complete poem. Since the Renaissance, students of Parmenides have relied on collections of fragments compiled by classical scholars, and since the turn of the twentieth century, Hermann Diels’ Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, through a number of editions, has remained the standard collection for Presocratic material generally and for the arrangement of Parmenides’ fragments in particular.
    [Show full text]
  • Court Intrigue and the Death of Callisthenes Lara O’Sullivan
    Court Intrigue and the Death of Callisthenes Lara O’Sullivan MPLICATED IN A PLOT by the Royal Pages (the basilikoi paides) against Alexander’s life in Bactria in 327 B.C.E., the historian I Callisthenes was condemned as a traitor and died—either tortured and hanged, or imprisoned and carted about with the army until disease brought about his death.1 His demise marks something of a nadir in Alexander’s reign; indeed, centuries after the fact, Curtius could claim that no one’s execution incited greater resentment of Alexander among the Greeks (nullius caedes maiorem apud Graecos Alexandro excitavit invidiam).2 The reason for that resentment is not difficult to discover. Despite the avowals of the Alexander-apologists that the Pages had implicated Cal- listhenes, his supposed involvement in the plot was unsupported by evidence. Arrian concedes as much, observing that most traditions had no indication of Callisthenes’ guilt, while Plutarch cites a letter purportedly written by the king himself in the im- mediate aftermath of the conspiracy, in which the Pages were said to have confessed under torture that the conspiracy was en- tirely their own, and that nobody else was cognizant of the plot.3 The underlying cause of Callisthenes’ downfall is, instead, 1 For Callisthenes’ fate Arr. 4.14.3 cites divergent accounts by Ptolemy FGrHist 138 F17 (put to death; so too Curt. 8.8.21) and Aristobulus FGrHist 139 F 33 (died while imprisoned). Aristobulus clearly based his account on Chares (FGrHist 125 F 15 = Plut. Alex. 55.9). 2 Curt. 8.8.22.
    [Show full text]
  • Hestia: the Indo-European Goddess of the Cosmic Central Fire
    Hestia: The Indo-European Goddess of the Cosmic Central Fire Marcello De Martino Abstract: The Pythagorean Philolaus of Croton (470-390 BCE) created a unique model of the Universe and he placed at its centre a ‘fire’, around which the spheres of the Earth, the Counter-Earth, the five planets, the Sun, the Moon and the outermost sphere of fixed stars, also viewed as fire but of an ‘aethereal’ kind, were revolving. This system has been considered as a step towards the heliocentric model of Aristarchus of Samos (310-230 BCE), the astronomical theory opposed to the geocentric system, which already was the communis opinio at that time and would be so for many centuries to come: but is that really so? In fact, comparing the Greek data with those of other ancient peoples of Indo-European language, it can be assumed that the ‘pyrocentric’ system is the last embodiment of a theological tradition going back to ancient times: Hestia, the central fire, was the descendant of an Indo-European goddess of Hearth placed at the centre of the religious and mythological view of a deified Cosmos where the gods were essentially personifications of atmospheric phenomena and of celestial bodies. In 1960, an article came out in a scientific journal which specialised in topics which were a bit more eccentric that those of traditional research studies on the history of religions, especially the classical ones. Its title was On the Relation between Early Greek Scientific Thought and Mysticism: Is Hestia, the Central Fire, an Abstract Astronomical Concept?.1 The author was Rudolph E.
    [Show full text]