Gregory of Rimini on the Intension and Remission of Corporeal Forms

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Gregory of Rimini on the Intension and Remission of Corporeal Forms GREGORY OF RIMINI ON THE INTENSION AND REMISSION OF CORPOREAL FORMS Can L. LOEWE Abstract The goal of this paper is to provide an account of Gregory of Rimini’s (1300- 1358) theory of the intension and remission of corporeal forms. Under the influence of new Oxford ideas of the fourteenth century Gregory adopts a highly quantitative approach to intensive change. The paper discusses Gregory’s defense of the addition theory, especially in light of Walter Burley’s counter- arguments. It also considers Gregory’s account of the continuity of intensive change, as well as his views on the possibility of the co-presence of contrary qualities in the same subject. Introduction The goal of this paper is to provide an account of Gregory of Rimini’s (1300-1358)1 theory of the intension and remission of corporeal forms,2 as laid out in book 1, d. 17, qq. 2-4 of his Sentences commentary 1 On the author, see R.L. FRIEDMAN – C. SCHABEL, “Gregory of Rimini,” in: H. LAGER- LUND (ed.), Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy. Philosophy Between 500 and 1500, Vol. 1, Dordrecht 2011, pp. 439-444. All references are to the critical edition: GREGORY OF RIMINI, Lectura Super Primum et Secundum Sententiarum, 6. Vols. (= Spätmittelalter und Reformation. Texte und Untersuchungen, vols. 6-11), ed. A.D. TRAPP – V. MARCOLINO – W. ECKERMANN – M. SANTOS-NOYA – W. SIMON – W. SCHULZE – W. URBAN – V. WEND- LAND, Berlin 1979-84. I refer to Gregory’s Sentences commentary as Sent. All translations from the Latin are mine. (NB: I do not necessarily respect the punctuation and orthography of any text I use.) 2 By ‘corporeal forms’ Gregory means those forms that inhere in extended surfaces. He contrasts those with spiritual (or psychological) forms such as charity or courage; see Sent., 1, 17, 2, vol. 2, p. 250. He thinks, however, that his account of the intension and remission of corporeal qualities can be extended without any significant alterations to spiritual qualities (see pp. 277-278 below and n. 17 for references). Recherches de Théologie et Philosophie médiévales 81(2), 273-330. doi: 10.2143/RTPM.81.2.3062082 © 2014 by Recherches de Théologie et Philosophie médiévales. All rights reserved. 997666.indb7666.indb 227373 222/01/152/01/15 113:273:27 274 C.L. LOEWE (1346).3 This theory was devised to explain how changes of degree within a given quality occur, e.g., how the shade of a color changes, or how an object becomes hotter. Although this topic initially seems to be a narrowly natural philosophical one, in the Middle Ages it had a theological dimension, too. Specifically, the scholastics were concerned with the issue of how to account for the increase of the theological virtue of charity.4 The discussions of this subject matter were extensive, and it is no great exaggeration when Anneliese Maier calls the debate surrounding intension and remission of forms one “of the highest rank” in scholastic thought.5 Gregory of Rimini’s discussion occupies an important place in this debate. His discussion is one of the longest of the fourteenth century,6 and it is characterized by a level of detail and sophistication that was, in many ways, unprecedented. In Gregory’s times and centuries to follow this did not go unnoticed. Gregory’s views on the topic of intension and remission became so influential that the three questions, which Gregory dedicated to this topic, were made available in a separate treatise entitled Tractatus de intensione et remissione formarum corporalium.7 Despite its great sophistication and influence, Gregory’s account of the intension and remission of corporeal forms has, unlike other 3 1346 is the date of release. Gregory lectured on the Sentences in Paris in 1343-44. See V. MARCOLINO, “Der Augustinertheologe an der Universität Paris,” in: H.A. OBERMAN (ed.), Gregor von Rimini. Werk und Wirkung bis zur Reformation, Berlin 1981, pp. 127- 194, esp. 170-171; P. BERMON, “La Lectura sur les deux premiers livres des Sentences de Grégoire de Rimini O.E.S.A (1300-1358),” in: G.R. EVANS (ed.), Mediaeval Commentar- ies on the Sentences of Peter Lombard. Current Research, vol. 1, Leiden 2002, pp. 267-285, esp. 268. 4 See A. MAIER, Zwei Grundprobleme der scholastischen Naturphilosophie (= Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, vol. 2), 3rd ed., Rome 1968, pp. 10-11. 5 See ibid., p. 5. 6 The three questions that Gregory dedicates to this topic (Sent., 1, d. 17, qq. 2-4, vol. 2, pp. 250-417) comprise 167 pages in the critical edition. 7 According to Heiko Oberman, two of the 27 manuscripts of the first book of the Sentences (specifically, manuscripts N, Oxford Bodleian Library, Can. Misc. 177, and X, Venice, Biblioteca Nazionale Marciana MS. VI, 160 [2816]) contain this separate treatise. These manuscripts were for some time in the possession of the Italian philosophers Johannes de Marchanova († 1467) and Nicolettus Vernias Theatinus († 1499). See H.A. OBERMAN, Introduction to Lectura, vol. 2 (d. 7-17), ed. A.D. TRAPP et al., Berlin 1982, p. 5. For more information on the manuscripts of Gregory’s commentary as well as the so-called additiones, i.e., those passages that Gregory did not include in the definitive version of his commentary (ordinatio), see V. MARCOLINO, Introduction to Lectura, vol. 1 (d. 1-6), ed. A.D. TRAPP et al., Berlin 1981, p. 95; BERMON, “La Lectura,” pp. 269-271. 997666.indb7666.indb 227474 222/01/152/01/15 113:273:27 GREGORY OF RIMINI ON CORPOREAL FORMS 275 aspects of his natural philosophy, not received much attention by scholars.8 At least, there has not been, to my knowledge, any study that considers Gregory’s discussion in its entirety.9 In this paper, I will try to fill this gap. What makes Gregory’s discussion particularly interesting is that it is one of the first discussions on the Continent to be extensively influenced by new Oxford ideas, which, as is well known, Gregory was one of the first to introduce.10 Under this influence Gregory adopts a highly quantitative approach to qualities, which, although presented in Aristotelian terminology, is in many ways closer to the account of qualities typically associated with early modern science. To avoid misunderstandings I should say that I do not mean by Gregory’s ‘quantitative approach’ that he uses mathematical formulas to describe physical states of affairs (although some mathematics is present in his account). Unlike the early-fourteenth-century Oxford Calculators, Gregory is not interested in formulating kinematic laws 8 Scholars have studied in depth several of Gregory’s contributions to natural phi- losophy such as his groundbreaking ideas on the continuum and the infinite. Gregory claimed that actual infinites were not only possible, but in fact existed, and that every continuum was an actual infinite. Furthermore, he claimed that one infinity could be greater than another according to a relation that comes very close to the contemporary set-theoretical relation between set and subset. On Gregory’s theory of the comparison of infinities, see J.E. MURDOCH, “Mathesis in Philosophiam Scholasticam Introducta. The Rise and Develop- ment of the Application of Mathematics in Fourteenth Century Philosophy and Theology,” in: Actes du Quatrième Congrès International de Philosophie Médiévale, Montréal 1969, pp. 215-246, esp. 223-224; On infinity and the continuum see J.M.M.H. THIJSSEN, “Het Continuum-Debat bij Gregorius van Rimini (1300–1358),” in: Algemeen Nederlands Tijd- schrift voor Wijsbegeerte 77 (1985), pp. 109-119; K. SMITH, “Ockham’s Influence on Gregory of Rimini’s Natural Philosophy,” in: V. SYROS – A. KOURES – H. KALOKAIRINOU (eds.), Διαλέξεις. Ακαδημαϊκό έτος 1996-7, Lefkosia 1999, pp.107-142; R. CROSS, “Infinity, Continuity, and Composition: The Contribution of Gregory of Rimini,” in: Medieval Philosophy and Theology 7 (1998), pp. 89-110. 9 Some parts, however, have been discussed. Edith Sylla discusses Gregory’s views on minima and maxima as laid out in q. 2. See E.D. SYLLA, “Disputationes Collativae: Walter Burley’s Tractatus Primus and Gregory of Rimini’s Lectura super primum et secundum Sententiarum,” in: Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 22 (2011), pp. 383- 464, esp. 404-410. Onorato Grassi and Francesco Fiorentino, in separate articles, explored Gregory’s arguments in q. 4 against Giles of Rome’s theory of intension and remission. See O. GRASSI, “Gregorio da Rimini e l’agostinismo tardo-medievale,” in: Gregorio da Rimini filosofo (Atti del Convegno - Rimini, 25 novembre 2000), Rimini 2003, pp. 66-96, esp. 85-89; F. FIORENTINO, “Gregorio da Rimini a confronto con Egidio Romano e gli egidiani,” in: Analecta Augustiniana 68 (2005), pp. 6-58, esp. 24-35. 10 See BERMON, “La Lectura,” p. 280. 997666.indb7666.indb 227575 222/01/152/01/15 113:273:27 276 C.L. LOEWE such as the middle degree theorem.11 Nor does he provide anything like a geometrical representation of intensities as can be found in Nicole Oresme.12 What I mean by Gregory’s ‘quantitative approach’ is rather that Gregory treats intensities ontologically as if they were quantities, and that, in this ontological respect, his account is close to that of early modern science (although early modern science drops the as if and, basically, treats intensities as quantities tout court). It is one goal of this paper to shed light on the ontology behind the as if. Section 1 of this paper will provide a brief overview of the structure of Gregory’s discussion of intension and remission in light of the Aristotelian and the medieval background. Section 2 will then discuss Gregory’s account and defense of the then prominent addition theory of intension and remission and his refutation of rival theories (cor- responding to q.
Recommended publications
  • FAITH and REASON in the THOUGHT of GREGORY of RIMINI (C
    FAITH AND REASON IN THE THOUGHT OF GREGORY OF RIMINI (c. 1300-1358) BY GORDON LEFF, B.A., PH.D. LECTURER IN HISTORY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER F any one trait may be said to characterize fourteenth- I century thought it is the progressive withdrawal of faith from the arena of philosophy and rational knowledge. Perhaps the greatest driving force in the development of medieval thought during the twelfth and thirteenth centuries had been the confidence that the truths of faith were accessible to human understanding and rational demonstration. It had nurtured a diversity of summae and systems, designed to incorporate the conclusions derived from the accumulating wealth of natural, mainly Aristotelian, knowledge into a Christian framework; it also led to some of the greatest works of Christian apologetics, including St. Thomas Aquinas's Summa contra gentiles, with the purpose of convincing the unbeliever and the infidel. With Henry of Ghent, Duns Scotus, and, even more with William of Ockham, however, the growing doubts over such a union were given full and lasting expression. Although not the first to do so, they reverted to a conception of theology as an indepen­ dent pursuit which was marked off from natural knowledge in the strict sense. Theology, they held, was a self-contained corpus with its own tenets and principles. It could not be regarded as just one more science governed by laws which were applicable to all knowledge, for, as founded on revealed truth, it was dependent on faith, not natural experience. These thinkers, moreover, were so obsessed by the contingent nature of all creation that they refused to countenance the possibility of arriving at a knowledge of God through creation.
    [Show full text]
  • © in This Web Service Cambridge University
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-89754-9 - An Introduction to Medieval Theology Rik Van Nieuwenhove Index More information Index Abelard, Peter, 82, 84, 99–111, 116, 120 beatific vision, 41, 62, 191 Alain of Lille, 71 beatitude, 172, 195–96 Albert the Great, 171, 264 Beatrijs van Nazareth, 170 Alexander of Hales, 147, 211, 227 beguine movement, 170 allegory, 15, 43, 45, 47, 177 Benedict XII, Pope, 265 Amaury of Bène, 71 Benedict, St., 28–29, 42 Ambrose, 7, 10, 149 Berengar of Tours, 60, 83, 129, 160, see also amor ipse notitia est 51, 117, see love and knowledge Eucharist anagogy, 47 Bernard of Clairvaux, 79, 82, 100, 104, 110, 112–15, analogy, see univocity 147, 251 analogy in Aquinas, 182–85, 234, 235 critique of Abelard, 110–11 Anselm of Canterbury, 16, 30, 71, 78, 81, 83–98, on loving God, 112–14 204, 236 Boccaccio, Giovanni, 251 Anselm of Laon, 72, 99 Boethius, 29–33, 125, 137 Anthony, St., 27 Bonaventure, 34, 47, 123, 141, 146, 148, 170, 173, apophaticism, 8, 34, 271 176, 179, 211–24, 227, 228, 230, 232, 242, 243, Aquinas, 182–83 245, 254 Aquinas, 22, 24, 34, 47, 51, 72, 87, 89, 90, 133, 146, Boniface, Pope, 249 148, 151, 154, 164, 169, 171–210, 214, 225, 227, 230, 235, 236, 237, 238, 240, 241, 244, 246, Calvin, 14 254, 255, 257, 266 Carabine, Deirdre, 65 Arianism, 20, 21 Carthusians, 79 Aristotle, 9, 20, 29, 78, 84, 179, 181, 192, 195, 212, Cassian, John, 27–29, 47 213, 216, 223, 225, 226, 227, 229, 237, 254, Cassidorius, 124 267, 268 cathedral schools, 82, 169 Arts, 124, 222 Catherine of Siena, 251 and pedagogy (Hugh), 124–28
    [Show full text]
  • The Fourteenth and Seventeenth Century Project of Mathematical Physics
    ORG ANON 41:2009 Elżbieta Jung (Łódź, Poland) THE FOURTEENTH AND SEVENTEENTH CENTURY PROJECT OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS. CONTINUITY OR DISCONTINUITY?* Introduction Medieval philosophers while commenting on Aristotle's works on natural philosophy noticed many apporiai in his physics. What is more, inspired by William of Ockham (ca. 1280-1349), they rejected Aristotelian prohibition of metabasis limiting the use of geometry only to scientice media? (intermediate sciences), such as optics or astronomy, which deal only with quantified aspects of natural phenomena and not the whole phenomenon'. In the 14th century the members of the famous English School, so-called Oxford Calculators introduced to physics both: mathematics, understood as a proper language of science, and logic understood as the convenient way to pose problems. Therefore, it seems interesting to examine if they have any project of mathematical physics and if so whether it made them stand any closer to modern science. Since it is no more doubtful that Galileo, while proving a proper rule of accelerate motion, used the Mean Speed Theorem, formulated by one of the Calculators, William Heytesbury (ca. 1313-1372)2, and that Newton employed the 14lh century theory of compounding ratios3, it seems attractive to go back to a continuity/discontinuity in the history of natural science. One of the most distinguished historians of medieval science, Annelise Maier, regarded the history of natural philosophy from the thirteenth to the 181'1 century as the history of the gradual rejection of Aristotelianism. She claimed that it did not evolve uniformly from century to century, but it " The paper is a revised version of an article titled: Why vra.v Medieval Mechanics Doomed? The Failure lo Substitute Mathematical Physics for Aristotelianism in: Miscellanea Mediaevalia: Herbst des Mittelalters? Fragen zur Bewertimg des 14, und 15.
    [Show full text]
  • 62F16fbeaf706c4a09c9a65a7f2c
    TOWARDS THE MODERN THEORY OF MOTION Oxford Calculators and the new interpretation of Aristotle vol. IV Elżbieta Jung Robert Podkoński TOWARDS THE MODERN THEORY OF MOTION Oxford Calculators and the new interpretation of Aristotle Łódź 2020 Elżbieta Jung, Robert Podkoński – University of Lodz Faculty of Philosophy and History, 90-131 Lodz, 3/5 Lindleya St., Poland Series Research on Science & Natural Philosophy, vol. IV EDITORIAL BOARD Jagna Brudzińska, Universität zu Köln Daniel A. Di Liscia, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, München Paweł Maślanka, University of Lodz Jean-Paul Pittion, Trinity College, Dublin Sabine Rommevaux-Tani, Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris Elżbieta Żądzińska, University of Lodz REVIEWER Mikołaj Olszewski INITIATING EDITOR Natasza Koźbiał EDITORS Latin – Dariusz Gwis English – Guy Torr TYPESETTING Katarzyna Turkowska TECHNICAL EDITOR Anna Sońta COVER DESIGN Katarzyna Turkowska Cover Image: © depositphotos.com/Exi Printed directly from camera-ready materials provided to the Łódź University Press by Faculty of Philosophy and History © Copyright by Elzbieta Jung, Robert Podkoński, Łódź 2020 © Copyright for this edition by University of Łódź, Łódź 2020 NATIONAL SCIENCE CENTER, POLAND 2015/17/B/HS1/02376 Published by Lodz University Press Edition I. W.09767.20.0.K Printing sheets 28.75 ISBN 978-83-8220-327-1 e-ISBN 978-83-8220-328-8 Lodz University Press 90-131 Lodz, 8 Lindleya St. www.wydawnictwo.uni.lodz.pl e-mail: [email protected] phone. 42 665 58 63 Table of contents Preface .......................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Patristic Legacy in the Middle Ages (II) 16:00 - 18:30 Wednesday, 21St August, 2019 Room 8 Presentation Type Workshop
    Politics and Society: The Patristic Legacy in the Middle Ages (II) 16:00 - 18:30 Wednesday, 21st August, 2019 Room 8 Presentation type Workshop 499 Side by Side: Augustine's supporting role in William of St. Thierry's attacks on Peter Abaelard Delphine Conzelmann University of Basel, Basel, Switzerland Abstract How far can a theologian go? What can, and more importantly, what can't he say? It was not merely a personal rivalry, but this very question, that drove William of St. Thierry (1080-1148) to consider the theology of Peter Abaelard (1079-1142) as a problem that needed to be dealt with. For him, the limits of the theological task as such were at stake. In William's eyes, Abaelard approached the Bible in a way too speculative and philosophical manner. In contrast, he understood his own theology as Biblical and true to the opinions of the Fathers, a sentiment he strongly expressed in his Expositio super Epistolam ad Romanos. In this paper I am going to discuss William's reception of Augustine, in order to present his own reading of Romans as firmly grounded in ecclesial tradition. Not only does he take up Augustine's thought, but he uses Augustine's biographical background – mainly his anti-Pelagian fervor – to support his own fight against heretical ideas, such as Peter Abaelard's or William of Conches'. This paper will explore how William introduced Augustine as a third player into his rising conflict with the school of Abaelard, both as authority in matters of theological content and methodology, and as a role model for his concrete political actions in the matter.
    [Show full text]
  • Good Positive Reasons" for an Ethics of Divine Commands: a Catalogue of Arguments
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 6 Issue 1 Article 4 1-1-1989 In Search of "Good Positive Reasons" for an Ethics of Divine Commands: A Catalogue of Arguments Janine Marie Idziak Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Idziak, Janine Marie (1989) "In Search of "Good Positive Reasons" for an Ethics of Divine Commands: A Catalogue of Arguments," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 6 : Iss. 1 , Article 4. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol6/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. IN SEARCH OF "GOOD POSITIVE REASONS" FOR AN ETHICS OF DIVINE COMMANDS: A CATALOGUE OF ARGUMENTS J anine Marie Idziak Recent proponents of a divine command ethics have chiefly defended the theory by refuting objections rather than by offering "positive reasons" to support it. We here offer a cata­ logue of such positive arguments drawn from historical discussions of the theory. We pre­ sent arguments which focus on various properties of the divine nature and on the unique status of God, as well as arguments which are analogical in character. Finally, we describe a particularform of the theory to which these arguments point, and indicate how they counter­ act a standard criticism of it.
    [Show full text]
  • William of Ockham (C.1287-1347)
    HPS 322 Michael J. White History of Science Fall semester, 2013 The 14th century A.D.: A. (1) William of Ockham (c.1287-1347). (2) The ‘Oxford Calculators’ or ‘Mertonians’ (after Merton College, Oxford) of the 14th century: Thomas Bradwardine, William Heytesbury, Richard Swineshead, John Dumbleton. The graphic/geometrical representation of the ‘intension and remission of forms’ (of which ‘speed’ is only one). ‘Uniform’, ‘uniformly difform’, and ‘difformly difform’ continuous change (i.e., continuous qualitative ‘intension’ or increase and ‘remission’ or decrease–which includes intension/remission of speed). Statement and proof of a ‘mean-value theorem’: a body moving with at a constant speed v/2 travels the same distance s in a time t as does a body uniformly accelerated body from rest to speed v in the same time t. Representation of quantity of motion (distance traversed) as area of plane figure. B. Those associated with the University of Paris: Jean Buridan (ca. 1300-1361)–further development of impetus theory. Nicole Oresme (ca. 1323-1382). C. Oresme on commensurability/incommensurability of the orbital periods of the celestial bodies. Recollect that: magnitudes A and B are commensurable iff (if and only if) there exists some positive magnitude M that is a common ‘aliquot part’ of both A and B (i.e., there exist positive integers n and m such that A = M × n and B = M × m). Consider any spatial configuration S of alignment of celestial bodies (e.g., planets) P1 and P21 and assume that the periods of P and P2 (T1 and T2, respectively) are incommensurable. Will P12 and P ever again assume exactly that alignment S? Answer: no.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustinianism.Pdf
    Augustinianism. This term is used to characterize philosophical, theological and political political ideas which were more or less close to those of S. Augustine of Hippo. The term came into use relatively recently, and can cover a spectrum of views: Augustinianism has never been a homogeneous movement. In particular, it is necessary to distinguish between a broad and a strict sense of the word, In the broad sense, the whole of Latin theology of the medieval and early modern period was strongly influenced by Augustine, as emerges very clearly from the Summae of the twelfth century and above all from Hugh of St Victor and from the authoritative Book of Sentences of Peter Lombard. The early generations of theologians of the mendicant orders – Hugh of St Cher, Alexander of Hales, Bonaventura of Bagnoregio – developed a close bond with Augustine, but they interpreted him in the light of neoplatonic or Aristotelian theories (for example, divine illumination of the intellect, the ‘agent intellect’, matter, rationes seminales [seminal principles]. In the strict sense one must distinguish between the following. #1. Augustinianism from the end of the thirteenth and the beginning of the fourteenth century emerged - especially in the Franciscan School (William de la Mare) and among Augustinian Hermits (“the old Augustinian School according to Giles of Rome) - as a reaction to the widespread reception of Aristotle in the work of Thomas Aquinas, after the condemnations of 1277 at Paris and 1284 at Oxford. Consciously drawing on Augustinian on Augustinian ideas (illumination, the form of created things in the mind of God), Henry of Ghent [a member of the secular clergy] created a coherent new system of speculative theology which would provide a a basis for acute critical analysis and the new order introduced by John Duns Scotus, who substituted for illumination the idea of an intuitive grasp of the essence of things.
    [Show full text]
  • Behind the Mirror Revealing the Contexts of Jacobus's Speculum
    Behind the Mirror Revealing the Contexts of Jacobus’s Speculum musicae by Karen Desmond A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Music New York University May, 2009 ___________________________ Edward H. Roesner © Karen Desmond All Rights Reserved, 2009 DEDICATION For my family iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank my advisor, Edward Roesner, for his unfaltering support throughout this process, for his thoughtful suggestions regarding lines of inquiry, and his encyclopedic knowledge of the field. I would like to thank Stanley Boorman and Gabriela Iltnichi for their friendship and expertise, and their critical eye in their careful reading of many drafts of my work. For their assistance during my research trip to Belgium, I must mention Monsieur Abbé Deblon and Christian Dury at the Archives de l’Evêché, Liège, Paul Bertrand at the Archives de l’Etat, Liège, Philippe Vendrix for his kind hospitality, and to Barbara Haggh-Huglo for her tips and advice in advance of my trip, and for also reading a final draft of this dissertation. I would also like to thank Margaret Bent and Ruth Steiner for help during the early stages of my doctoral research, and Suzanne Cusick for her reading of the final draft. Finally, heartfelt thanks are due to my husband, Insup; my two sons, Ethan and Owen; and my parents, John and Chris, who have been steadfast in their encouragement of this endeavor. v ABSTRACT This study addresses the general question of how medieval music theory participated in the discourse of the related disciplines of philosophy, natural science and theology.
    [Show full text]
  • 178 Petrus Martyr Vermigli This Volume Is a Fine Critical Edition of Pietro Martire Vermigli's
    178 Book Reviews Petrus Martyr Vermigli Kommentar zur Nikomachischen Ethik des Aristoteles, ed. Luca Baschera and Christian Moser (Studies in Medieval and Reformation Traditions, vol. 158). Leiden/Boston: Brill, 2011. viii, 689 pp. ISBN 9789004218734. This volume is a fine critical edition of Pietro Martire Vermigli’s (1499-1562) relatively unexplored but rich commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. When Vermigli lectured on the Nicomachean Ethics during his second profes- sorship at Strasbourg 1553-1556, he most likely continued the practice he had learnt at the University of Padua, which in the first half of the sixteenth cen- tury had distinguished itself by installing an ordinary professorship in moral philosophy devoted to the exposition of the Nicomachean Ethics. Vermigli comments on his own Latin translation of (most likely) Erasmus’s Greek edi- tion. He follows the mediaeval tradition of both literal comments and topical digressions, but his analysis of Greek terminology and grammar as well as the generous use of classical and patristic sources shows his debt to his Renaissance context. The style of his Latin is classical, fused with mediaeval philosophical terminology. On the surface the commentary of Eustratios appears to be more important than those of Albert the Great, Thomas Aquinas and Jacques-Louis d’Estrebay. Each section usually begins with a statement of the subject or even a summarizing syllogism and Vermigli then argues for the major and minor premises in the commentary. Many of the subsections end with digressions on difficulties and problems. Although Vermigli does not con- form to the fixed scholastic genres of quaestio, dubia and solutio, he uses them informally.
    [Show full text]
  • MOLINA and JOHN DUNS SCOTUS Jean-Pascal Anfray the Influence of John Duns Scotus
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers MOLINA AND JOHN DUNS SCOTUS Jean-Pascal Anfray The influence of John Duns Scotus (1265/6–1308) on late medieval and early modern philosophy and theology can hardly be overlooked. The Subtle Doctor’s concepts and doctrines set the shape of much of the discussions of the time, on the nature and subject of metaphysics, on the freedom of the will, and on the principles of morality. More pre- cisely, Scotus’s definition of being qua being as that to which being is not repugnant (cui non repugnat esse),1 and as a possible being, left a twofold legacy to later philosophy: on the one hand, his conception of metaphys- ics as a transcendental science of the univocal concept of being, and on the other hand the centrality of the notion of freedom, whose first mani- festation is the contingency of the world order. During the Renaissance and early modern period, those who would qualify as Scotists were so many that the Cistercian Juán Caramuel Lobkowitz could claim that Scoti schola numerosior est aliis simul sumptis (the school of Scotus counts more than all the other schools taken together).2 Not only was the institutional authority of Scotus uncontroversial but his thought also exercised a more diffused influence. Jesuit philosophy and theology was undoubtedly the main channel of diffusion for Scotus’s thought in the early modern era, and this, despite the fact that the ratio studiorum of the order (1586–99) made the study of Thomas Aquinas’s doctrine the basis of their theo- logical teaching.3 Especially well known is the importance of the Scotist 1 See John Duns Scotus, Quodl.
    [Show full text]
  • What the Middle Ages Knew IV
    Late Medieval Philosophy Piero Scaruffi Copyright 2018 http://www.scaruffi.com/know 1 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – The Bible is infallible, therefore there is no need for scientific investigation or for the laws of logic – Conflict between science and religion due to the Christian dogma that the Bible is the truth – 1.Dangerous to claim otherwise – 2.Pointless to search for additional truths – Tertullian (3rd c AD): curiosity no longer necessary because we know the meaning of the world and what is going to happen next ("Liber de Praescriptione Haereticorum") 2 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – Decline of scientific knowledge • Lactantius (4th c AD) ridicules the notion that the Earth could be a sphere ("Divinae Institutiones III De Falsa Sapientia Philosophorum") • Cosmas Indicopleustes' "Topographia Cristiana" (6th c AD): the Earth is a disc 3 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – Plato's creation by the demiurge in the Timaeus very similar to the biblical "Genesis" – Christian thinkers are raised by neoplatonists • Origen was a pupil of Ammonius Sacca (Plotinus' teacher) • Augustine studied Plotinus 4 What the Middle Ages knew • Preservation of classical knowledge – Boethius (6th c AD) translates part of Aristotle's "Organon" and his "Arithmetica" preserves knowledge of Greek mathematics – Cassiodorus (6th c AD) popularizes scientific studies among monks and formalizes education ("De Institutione Divinarum" and "De artibus ac disciplinis liberalium litterarum") with the division of disciplines into arts (grammar, rhetoric, dialectic) – and disiplines (arithmeitc,geometry, music, astronomy) – Isidore of Sevilla (7th c AD) preserves Graeco- Roman knowledge in "De Natura Rerum" and "Origines" 5 What the Middle Ages knew • Preservation of classical knowledge – Bede (8th c AD) compiles an encyclopedia, "De Natura Rerum" – St Peter's at Canterbury under Benedict Biscop (7th c AD) becomes a center of learning – Episcopal school of York: arithmetic, geometry, natural history, astronomy.
    [Show full text]