Democratic Authority : a Philosophical Framework / David M

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Democratic Authority : a Philosophical Framework / David M Democratic Authority This page intentionally left blank Democratic Authority A PHILOSOPHICAL FRAMEWORK David M. Estlund princeton university press princeton andoxford Copyright © 2008 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 3 Market Place, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1SY All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Estlund, David M. Democratic authority : a philosophical framework / David M. Estlund. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-0-691-12417-9 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Democracy. 2. Democracy—Philosophy. 3. Authority. I. Title. JC423E714 2007 321.8—dc22 2007012303 British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available This book has been composed in Palatino Printed on acid-free paper. ∝ press.princeton.edu Printed in the United States of America 12345678910 To my mother, Ann Estlund, and to the memory of my father, Bruce Estlund This page intentionally left blank Contents Preface ix CHAPTER I Democratic Authority 1 CHAPTER II Truth and Despotism 21 CHAPTER III An Acceptability Requirement 40 CHAPTER IV The Limits of Fair Procedure 65 CHAPTER V The Flight from Substance 85 CHAPTER VI Epistemic Proceduralism 98 CHAPTER VII Authority and Normative Consent 117 CHAPTER VIII Original Authority and the Democracy/Jury Analogy 136 CHAPTER IX How Would Democracy Know? 159 CHAPTER X The Real Speech Situation 184 CHAPTER XI Why Not an Epistocracy of the Educated? 206 CHAPTER XII The Irrelevance of the Jury Theorem 223 CHAPTER XIII Rejecting the Democracy/Contractualism Analogy 237 CONTENTS CHAPTER XIV Utopophobia: Concession and Aspiration in Democratic Theory 258 Notes 277 Bibliography 295 Index 303 viii Preface There are different kinds of philosophy books. While some are written over a relatively short time, say a year, this one grows out of papers written over twenty years. Many books, including this one, bear down on a question (or several), scrutinizing existing arguments in detail and proposing improvements. This book, in addition to that, tries to de- velop a relatively elaborate theoretical framework—what I call epistemic proceduralism. There are advantages and disadvantages of both of these features, but in any case, the reader deserves advance notice. The rela- tion between this work and my previous papers is a close one, but not a simple one. Only a few chapters (noted below) are close to original pa- pers, while in most cases the ideas from previous pieces are inter- spersed throughout. In general, where the treatment in the book differs from the papers, it supersedes them. On the other hand, material has often been left out here for the sake of brevity and readability (I have tried to provide references where appropriate), not in order to retract it. Perhaps most important, especially for those who work as specialists in normative democratic theory, this book is not by any means merely a restatement of my earlier views. The approach to democracy developed here goes well beyond what I have said before, for better or for worse. As for the book’s attempt to develop a new theoretical framework, not just a better argument for this or that point, one consequence is that there are places where I offer only tentative or preliminary argumenta- tion. I think this is unavoidable if the shape of the general approach is to be laid out clearly. I hope there is enough argument to lend promise to the overall approach of epistemic proceduralism. If so, there is more work to be done. This disclaimer is separate from a further point, one with which the book begins, concerning the idea of a philosophical framework, one that steers relatively clear of engagement with empiri- cal social science and stops short of prescribing many institutional specifics. I say more about that in chapter 1. Having worked on these questions over a long time, it would be impossible to remember and thank all the people to whom thanks are owed. The acknowledgments would run back to teachers and fellow students in graduate school at Wisconsin; through students and col- leagues at my first job at the University of California, Irvine; and those PREFACE over the years at Brown, not to mention several visiting stints, and col- loquia and conferences that were particularly helpful to me. I do owe many thanks to people in all those settings. I confine myself here to ac- knowledging several people who have been helpful in the later stages, as my views turned into a book. For facilitating the transition from views to a book, first thanks go to Nomy Arpaly, not only for the philo- sophical camaraderie of our weekly lunches, but for sharing some of her book-writing magic. Her books have virtues that mine lacks, but mine now has what she taught me was the primary one: existence. Nomy, Cindy Estlund, and Mariah Zeisberg gave me excellent com- ments on the first chapter, and thereby on the whole project. My gradu- ate seminar at Brown in the fall of 2005 was where things began to take final form, thanks to the extremely high caliber of critical attention my draft received from the students. Among them was Jed Silverstein, whose additional excellent research assistance helped move the book from rough draft to less rough. Thanks also go to three students who helped with the final proof reading: Sean Aas, Derek Bowman, and Joshua Tropp. John Tomasi and Corey Brettschneider, political theorists in political science here at Brown, are my partners in building a new swirl of activity and excitement in political philosophy here. I have benefited constantly from the discussions at our Political Philosophy Workshop, but also from their own comments on my work, and especially their encouragement. One event in particular, a workshop devoted to my manuscript, was John’s generous idea. The commentators at that workshop—Russell Hardin, Philip Pettit, and Christian List—worked very hard on a difficult manuscript and helped me enormously. I had first gotten to know Philip during a Harsanyi Fellowship in 2001–2 that allowed me to spend a year at Australian National University. I am thankful for that support from ANU and the leave time from Brown, and for the frequent discussions there with Philip, Bob Goodin, Geoff Brennan, Gerry Mackie, John Dryzek, and Michael Smith, as well as the stellar students and vagabond scholars in the tea room at that amazing place. Thanks are also due to the National Endowment for the Humanities for two fellowships, one sup- porting a semester of research time in 1998–99, and the other supporting research during the summer of 2002. Thanks to Ian Malcolm for his en- thusiasm and expert guidance at Princeton University Press. For help of a deep but less specific kind, I must thank several people who were never my teachers or colleagues, but who took my ideas seri- ously when I was a young scholar just out of school (or even before). x PREFACE Jerry Cohen, Josh Cohen, and the late John Rawls all paid me more sup- portive attention than I had any reason to expect. I owe much in my own thought to their distinguished work, but their early attention itself was formative. For help of the deepest kind, I want to thank Meg Denton, Corey Es- tlund, Hannah Estlund, and Marshall Estlund for the years of working and playing together during the time when the book was produced, as were countless things of much greater value than this. There is much new here, but there are also passages and ideas drawn from previously published papers. The bibliography lists most of my published articles that bear on democracy, but several chapters bear an especially close relation to the previously published versions, and I am grateful for permission to draw on them. Chapter 5 is based closely on “Democracy,” in Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, ed. Frank Jackson and Michael Smith, (Oxford University Press, 2005), 208–30. Used by permission of Oxford Univer- sity Press. Chapter 7 is based on “Political Authority and the Tyranny of Non- consent,” Philosophical Issues 15 (2005): 351–67. Used by permission of Blackwell Publishing. Chapter 11 is based on “Why Not Epistocracy?” in Desire, Identity and Existence: Essays in Honor of T. M. Penner, ed. Naomi Reshotko (Acade- mic Printing and Publishing, 2003), 53–69. Used by permission of Aca- demic Printing and Publishing. Chapter 13 is based on “The Democracy/Contractualism Analogy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (2003): 387–412. Used by permission of Blackwell Publishing. xi This page intentionally left blank Democratic Authority This page intentionally left blank CHAPTER I Democratic Authority One of the two, as the wiser or better man, has a claim to superior weight: the difficulty is in ascertaining which of the two it is. John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government Democracy can seem to empower the masses without regard for the quality of the political decisions that will result. Concern for the quality of decisions can seem to lead in an antidemocratic direction, toward identifying and empowering those who know best. Partly for these rea- sons, philosophical treatments of democracy’s value have often tried to explain why politics should be democratic even though democracy has no particular tendency to produce good decisions. I believe these ac- counts are weak, and I want to put democratic convictions on more se- cure footing. My goal is to show how a concern for the quality of politi- cal decisions, properly constrained by other principles, supports democratic political arrangements. Rousseau pleads, “All my ideas are consistent, but I cannot expound them all at once.”1 In this synoptic essay I try to present, all at once, the broad shape and main points of a more elaborate book-length argument.
Recommended publications
  • Curriculum Vitae Samuel R
    CURRICULUM VITAE SAMUEL R. FREEMAN (October 2020) Avalon Chair in the Humanities Professor of Philosophy and of Law University of Pennsylvania Philosophy Department, 433 Claudia Cohen Hall Phone: 215-898-9052 (office) Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19104-6304 215-898-8563 (Philosophy Dept) sfreeman(at)sas.upenn.edu EDUCATION_____________________________________________________ Harvard University, Department of Philosophy, 1979-1985; Ph.D. awarded 1985. Thesis: "Contractarianism and Fundamental Rights," Dissertation Supervisor: John Rawls University of North Carolina, School of Law, J.D., 1977 University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, A.B. with highest honors, 1973 Göttingen University, West Germany, 1971-1972 AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION____________________________________________ Political and Social Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Philosophy of Law, History of Ethics HONORS, GRANTS, AND AWARDS________________________________________ 2017 Election to American Academy of Arts and Sciences 2008-present Avalon Chair in the Humanities, University of Pennsylvania 2005-2006 Fellow at Kadish Center, School of Law, University of California-Berkeley 2001-2008 Steven F. Goldstone Term Chair Professor, University of Pennsylvania 1995 Research Fellowship, University of Pennsylvania 1993 American Philosophical Association Fred Berger Memorial Prize, for the Best Essay in Philosophy of Law published in 1990 and 1991. 1992-93 Laurance S. Rockefeller Visiting Fellow, The Center for Human Values, Princeton University 1993 Pew Foundation, Course Development Grant
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout Revised 11/09 Class Meets Tuesdays 1-4 in the Department Seminar Room
    1 Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Class meets Tuesdays 1-4 in the Department seminar room. My email: [email protected] This course considers some philosophical arguments concerning the justification of the claim that under modern conditions, the political order of a society ought to be democratic. Next question: how democratic ought the political order to be, and what determines the normatively appropriate degree of democracy in particular circumstances. Following David Estlund, let us say a state is legitimate if it issues commands (laws, public policies) and enforces them and does so permissibly, and a state has authority if it has the moral power to issue commands (laws, public policies) to its subjects and thereby to bring it about that those commanded have some moral obligation to comply. Under modern conditions, must a state be democratic in order to rule legitimately and with authority? Texts: Joshua Cohen, Rousseau: A Free Community of Equals; David Estlund, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. J. S. Mill’s Considerations on Representative Government is available on line at www.utilitarianism.net/jsmill/ Jason Brennan’s forthcoming book the Ethics of Voting will be made available by email attachment. Some other readings will be made available by email attachment or in printed copies to be placed in the Philosophy Department Library or both. Note that the reading for weeks 1 and 2 includes Rousseau’s The Social Contract, which is neither a book placed on the shelves of the bookstore for this class nor specially made available in the Department Library.
    [Show full text]
  • Copp Cv 2015
    CURRICULUM VITAE DAVID COPP Department of Philosophy telephone: 530-554-1386 University of California, Davis fax: 530-752-8964 Davis, CA 95616 [email protected] http://philosophy.ucdavis.edu/people/dcopp Education Ph.D. in Philosophy: Cornell University, Ithaca, New York, 1976. Dissertation, “Individuals, Collectives and Moral Agency.” M.A.: Cornell University, 1973. Honours B.A. in Philosophy and Sociology: Glendon College, York University, Toronto, l970. Faculty Positions Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, Simon Fraser University, 1974 - 1976. Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Simon Fraser University, 1976 - 1980 Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Simon Fraser University, 1980 - 1988. (On leave, 1984 - 1987.) Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Chicago, 1984 - 1987. Professor, Department of Philosophy, Simon Fraser University, 1988 - 1989. Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Davis, 1989 - 1999. (On leave, 1998 - 1999.) Professor, Department of Philosophy, Bowling Green State University, 1998 - 2003. Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Florida, 2003 - 2009. Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Davis, 2009 - 2013. Distinguished Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Davis, 2013 - . Other Academic Positions Teaching Assistant to R. Stalnaker and N. Sturgeon, Cornell University, 1971 - 1972. Josephus Daniels Fellow of the Research Triangle Foundation, National Humanities Center, Research Triangle Park, North Carolina, 1988-89. Visiting Professor, Stanford University, Fall 1992. Fellow of the Social Philosophy and Policy Center, Bowling Green State University, August - December, 1996. Fellow of the Centre for Applied Ethics, University of British Columbia, Jan.- June, 1997. Research Fellow, Philosophy Program, Research School of Social Science, Australian National University, June and July, 1998.Senior Research Fellow, Social Philosophy and Policy Center, Bowling Green State University, 1998 - 2003.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Messy “Utopophobia Vs Factophobia” Controversy: a Systematization and Assessment∗
    On the Messy “Utopophobia vs Factophobia” Controversy: A Systematization and Assessment∗ Laura Valentini London School of Economics and Political Science For citations, please refer to the published version. In recent years, political philosophers have been fiercely arguing over the virtues and vices of utopian vs realistic theorizing. Partly due to the lack of a common and consistently used vocabulary, these debates have become rather confusing. In this chapter, I attempt to bring some clarity to them and, in doing so, I offer a conciliatory perspective on the “utopian vs realistic theorizing” controversy. I argue that, once the notion of a normative or evaluative theory is clearly defined and distinguished from the desiderata that any good theory should satisfy, many of the disagreements between supporters and opponents of “utopian” or “ideal” theorizing can be easily dissolved. I conclude that, in general, political philosophers should be cautious when theorizing at the extreme ends of the “utopian-realistic” spectrum, but that, setting extremes aside, the correct level of realism or idealism depends on the particular question a theory aims to address. Keywords: Ideal theory, non-ideal theory, utopianism, realism, idealisations, fact- insensitivity, feasibility. Introduction David Estlund (2008, chap. 14; 2011; 2014) has recently argued against an attitude in political philosophy he calls “utopophobia.” Utopophobes, in Estlund’s understanding, problematically compromise normative principles in order to accommodate empirical realities. If it turns out that people are unlikely to conform with what morality requires, utopophobes let them off the moral hook. While Estlund worries about utopophobia, other political philosophers are concerned about an altogether different pathology within the discipline: what one might call “factophobia.” By “factophobia,” I mean the tendency to elaborate normative principles under deeply counter-factual assumptions.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Not Epistocracy
    Why Not Epnstocracyf David Estlund I Introduction It is natural to think that the wise ought to rule, and yet it is now universally denied. One reason for this is that many people think that ruling arrangements ought to be justifiable in a generally acceptable way. Given so much reasonable dispute about who counts as wise in the right way, and other matters, it might seem doubtful that rule of the wise could meet this standard of generally acceptable justification. On the other hand, a decent education, including, say, some knowledge of politics, history, economics, close experience with others from di­ verse backgrounds, etc., must be admitted to improve the ability to rule wisely, other things equal, or at least assuming a certain measure of good will (otherwise these neutral means might only make a bad person more dangerous). But then why shouldn't there be general agreement that citizens with such an education should have more votes than others^ Is the only reason for this the assumption that whoever has more power will unjustly favor themselves^ Should we all accept rule of the wise if that condition were overcome^ If some political outcomes count as better than others, then surely some citizens are better (if only less bad) than others with regard to their wisdom and good faith in promoting the better outcomes. If so, this looks like an important reason to leave the decisions up to them. For purposes of this essay, call them the knowers, or the wise; the form of government in which they rule might be called epistocracy, and the rulers called epistocrats based on the Greek word episteme, meaning knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Rawls and Political Realism: Realistic Utopianism Or Judgement in Bad Faith?
    This is a repository copy of Rawls and Political Realism: Realistic Utopianism or Judgement in Bad Faith?. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/113810/ Article: Thomas, Alan Price orcid.org/0000-0002-8053-7195 (2015) Rawls and Political Realism: Realistic Utopianism or Judgement in Bad Faith? European Journal of Political Theory. pp. 304-324. ISSN 1741-2730 https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885115578970 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Article EJPT European Journal of Political Theory 0(0) 1–21 ! The Author(s) 2015 Rawls and political realism: Reprints and permissions: Realistic utopianism or sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1474885115578970 judgement in bad faith? ept.sagepub.com Alan Thomas Department of Philosophy, Tilburg School of Humanities, The Netherlands Abstract Political realism criticises the putative abstraction, foundationalism and neglect of the agonistic dimension of political practice in the work of John Rawls.
    [Show full text]
  • Authority, Legitimacy and Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Law
    Authority, Legitimacy and Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Law: Estlund vs. Habermas Jonathan Trejo-Mathys ABSTRACT: David Estlund has recently articulated the most sophisticated form of epistemic proceduralism available in Anglophone legal and political philosophy, one that grants that there are normative political truths and that some possess superior knowledge of them but defeats the claim that superior knowledge can successfully confer legislative authority. In the course of his argument, he charges Habermas’ rival version of proceduralism with ‘political nihilism’. The first two sections of this paper show that this charge is false and based upon a misunderstanding of Habermas and that it obscures the fact that Habermas provides a potentially stronger form of epistemic proceduralism that defeats the claim that those who know should rule by undermining the very idea that there could be some who possess superior normative political knowledge. The third section discusses a weak point in Habermas’ justification of coercive democratic law that is revealed in the course of the defense and suggests a Kantian way of remedying it. Trejo-Mathys 1 Epistemic Accounts of Democratic Authority and Legitimacy: Estlund vs. Habermas1 Epistemic views of democracy defend its legitimacy, or stronger, its authority in light of the epistemic virtues that the democratic process displays with respect to tracking some normative standard such as justice or the common good, however those are understood. They involve the belief that the truth about such matters, and in particular a sufficiently strong and effective tendency to pursue and discover it, is a necessary part of the justification of political authority and the legitimacy of the norms issued by such authority.
    [Show full text]
  • Elizabeth Anderson's Vita
    Elizabeth Anderson's Vita ELIZABETH S. ANDERSON John Rawls Collegiate Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies Arthur F. Thurnau Professor University of Michigan, Ann Arbor Department of Philosophy Angell Hall 2239 / 435 South State St. Ann Arbor, MI 48109-1003 Office: 734-763-2118 Fax: 734-763-8071 E-mail: [email protected] Web: http://www-personal.umich.edu/~eandersn/ EMPLOYMENT University of Michigan, John Rawls Collegiate Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, 2005- University of Michigan, Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, 1999-. University of Michigan, Associate Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, 1993-1999. University of Michigan, Adjunct Professor of Law, 1995, 1999, 2000. University of Michigan, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 1987-1993. Swarthmore College, Visiting Instructor in Philosophy, 1985-6. Harvard University, Teaching Fellow, 1983-1985. EDUCATION Harvard University, Department of Philosophy, 1981-1987. A.M. Philosophy, 1984. Ph.D. 1987. Swarthmore College, 1977-1981. B.A. Philosophy with minor in Economics, High Honors, 1981. HONORS, GRANTS AND FELLOWSHIPS John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation Fellowship, 2013 ACLS Fellowship, 2013 Michigan Humanities Award, 2013 (declined) Three Quarks Daily Philosophy Prize for 2012 blog entry, 2nd place Joseph B. Gittler Award, American Philosophical Association (for "an outstanding scholarly contribution in the philosophy of one or more of the social sciences," in recognition of The Imperative of Integration, 2011) Fellow, American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 2008 Michigan Humanities Fellow (University of Michigan), 2007 Named John Rawls Collegiate Professor, 2005 Honorable Mention, Fred Berger Memorial Prize (American Philosophical Association), 2003 (for "Expressive Theories of Law") John H.
    [Show full text]
  • The Unity of Rawls's Work
    This is a repository copy of The Unity of Rawls’s work . White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/1616/ Article: Wenar, Leif (2004) The Unity of Rawls’s work. The Journal of Moral Philosophy, 1 (3). pp. 265-275. ISSN 1740-4681 https://doi.org/10.1177/174046810400100303 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ White Rose Consortium ePrints Repository http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ This is an author produced version of a paper published in The Journal of Moral Philosophy. This paper has been peer-reviewed but does not include final publisher proof-corrections or journal pagination. White Rose Repository URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/1616/ Published Paper Wenar, Leif (2004) The unity of Rawls’s work.
    [Show full text]
  • David M. Estlund
    Curriculum Vitae February 6, 2020 _____________________________________________ David M. Estlund Lombardo Family Professor of Humanities Philosophy Department Brown University Providence, RI 02912 ADDRESS 97 Elm St. Seekonk, MA 02771 E-mail: [email protected] EDUCATION • B.S., Art, 12/80 (with distinction), Univ. of Wisconsin, Madison. • M.A., Philosophy, 12/82, Univ. of Wisconsin, Madison. • Audited courses in political philosophy, Michaelmas Term (Fall) 1985, Oxford University, England. • Ph.D., Philosophy, 12/86, Univ. of Wisconsin, Madison. - Dissertation: “The Theoretical Interpretation of Voting” EMPLOYMENT • Visiting Assistant Professor, Philosophy, Univ. of California, Irvine, July 1986 - June 1987. • Assistant Professor, Philosophy, Univ. of California, Irvine, July 1987 - June 1991. • Assistant Professor, Philosophy, Brown University, July 1991 - June 1993 • Associate Professor, Philosophy, Brown University, July 1993 - 2001. • Professor, Philosophy, Brown University, July 2001 – present. • Lombardo Family Professor of Humanities and Philosophy, Brown University, July 2009—present. • Visiting Professor, Harvard Law School, January – June 2011. • Visiting Professor, Philosophy Department, Stanford University, July-December, 2019. (See visiting fellowships under “Honors”) p. 1 ACADEMIC HONORS, ETC. (SINCE 1990) 1. American Council of Learned Societies, Fellowship for Recent Recipients of the Ph. D., 7/1/89 - 6/1/90, $10,000. 2. UC Irvine Committee on Research, $3,522 to supplement ACLS Fellowship. 3. Dean's grant (UCI), $10,000 to supplement ACLS Fellowship. 4. Fellowship in Ethics, Program in Ethics and the Professions, in residence at Harvard, 1993-94 academic year, half salary to supplement sabbatical. 5. National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowship for University Teachers (FA-34840). Awarded 12/97, to be used in 1998-99 academic year for one semester teaching relief.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy Catalog 2020
    Philosophy 2020 press.princeton.edu The World Philosophy Made How philosophy transformed human knowledge and the world we live in Philosophical investigation is the root of all human knowledge. Developing new concepts, reinterpreting old truths, and reconceptualizing fundamental questions, philosophy has progressed—and driven human progress—for more than two millennia. In short, we live in a world philosophy made. In this concise history of philosophy’s world-shaping impact, Scott Soames demonstrates that the modern world— including its science, technology, and politics—simply would not be possible without the accomplishments of philosophy. Firmly rebutting the misconception of philosophy as ivory-tower thinking, Soames traces its essential con- tributions to fields as diverse as law and logic, psychol- ogy and economics, relativity and rational decision theory. Beginning with the giants of ancient Greek philosophy, The World Philosophy Made chronicles the achievements of the great thinkers, from the medieval “Philosophy is everywhere, so much so that we and early modern eras to the present. It explores how don’t always notice it, or how it affects us. philosophy has shaped our language, science, math- Scott Soames makes a powerful case that ematics, religion, culture, morality, education, and philosophy has not devolved into abstractions politics, as well as our understanding of ourselves. suited only for the ivory tower. Rather, it continues to vibrantly and crucially interact Philosophy’s idea of rational inquiry as the key to with our intellectual concerns and our every- theoretical knowledge and practical wisdom has day lives. This is the story of philosophy that transformed the world in which we live.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE 2019 Gerald Gaus
    CURRICULUM VITAE 2019 Gerald Gaus James E. Rogers Professor of Philosophy Head, Department of Political Economy and Moral Science University of Arizona Tucson, Arizona 85721-0027 [email protected] www.gaus.biz DEGREES B.A., summa cum laude, 1974, State University of New York at Buffalo (Political Science). M.A., 1975, University of Pittsburgh (Political Science). Ph.D., 1979, University of Pittsburgh (Political Science). PH.D. DISSERTATION The Convergence of Rights and Utility: A Study of Rawls’s and Mill’s Liberalism, 1979. JOURNAL EDITOR 2002-2009: Founding co-editor, Politics, Philosophy, & Economics. Sage Publications, London. Guest editor, APA Newsletter on the Philosophy of Law, Special Issue on Law and Game Theory, Spring 2004. 1997- 2002: Co-editor, Australasian Journal of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. PUBLICATIONS -BOOKS: AUTHORED The Tyranny of the Ideal: Justice in a Diverse Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2016, xxii + 289. The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011, xx + 621pp. Corrected paperback, 2012. GAUS CV |2 On Philosophy, Politics, and Economics. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth-Thomson, 2008, xii + 220pp. Contemporary Theories of Liberalism: Public Reason as a Post-Enlightenment Project. London: Sage, 2003, ix + 240pp. (Translated into Chinese, 2014, Jiangsu People’s Publishing, Ltd.). Political Concepts and Political Theories. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2000, xiv + 288pp. (Translated into Turkish, 2013) Social Philosophy. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, 1999, xiv + 245pp. Justificatory Liberalism: An Essay on Epistemology and Political Theory (Oxford Political Theory). New York: Oxford University Press, 1996, xiv + 374pp. Value and Justification: The Foundations of Liberal Theory (Cambridge Studies in Philosophy).
    [Show full text]