Reflections on Stoic Pragmatism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Reflections on Stoic Pragmatism limbo Núm. 33, 2013, pp. 167-179 issn: 0210-1602 Th e Lachsian Version of San ta ya na: Refl ections on Stoic Pragmatism Charles Padrón John Lachs (2012): Stoic Pragmatism, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 204pp. To sense the culmination of another human’s life achievement approximating its mature zenith is a moment that most of us experience only rarely, at fi rst-hand, in our own lives. One calls that, speaking in plain words, “in one’s prime.” As I have read, reread, and refl ected on John Lachs’Stoic Pragmatism, I have undergone an experienced appreciation of an attained trajectory of accomplishment. Th e renowned San ta ya nan scholar, teacher, and original philosopher in his own right, has given us an elevated piece of scholarship: a work that elucidates the evolutionary development of both his own thought, and indirectly, though not in a defi nitive manner, a fi nal say on where he stands with his lifelong involvement with San ta ya na’s thought and writings. Lachs informs us in the “Introduction”: “I take delight in thinking that I have now discovered my beliefs about some of the deepest problems, beliefs I think I have acted upon all my life. In my writing, I have come closer and closer to expressing these ideas, but I have not formulated them explicitly until a few years ago” [Lachs 2012, p. 1]. It could be argued that no scholar or thinker, living or deceased, can match Lachs’ accomplishments in studying, teaching, and writing about San ta ya na’s œuvre. Yet Lachs himself would react with amusement to a statement like this, as if it mattered or was of any importance. Th is includes both his M.A. thesis and 167 168 Charles Padrón Ph.D. dissertation at Yale University, some twenty-three articles, encyclopedic and dictionary entries, and introductions, with “San- ta ya na” mentioned in the title (and these do not include the many articles among his nearly 200 smaller pieces that mention San ta- ya na at some point or address some aspect of the individual or his writings), four reviews of scholarly publications on San ta ya na, six books (and I include Stoic Pragmatism here) that have San ta ya na as the primary focus, along with having been Chair of the Editorial Board of Th e Collected Works of George San ta ya na, currently being published by Th e mit Press, and on the editorial board of Overheard in Seville, the San ta ya na Society’s annual publication. Strictly speaking, when Dr. Lachs talks or writes about George San ta ya na, one should listen to, or read, what is expressed, for there is gravitas and authority behind it. Yet there is an openness also, along with a willingness to listen to others who might think diff erently. Th ere is a learned modesty that enriches anyone who has had contact with him. As a result, what is unmistakable is that Lachs furthers his lifelong, engaged interpretation of, and dialogue with, San ta ya- na’s œuvre in Stoic Pragmatism. Helpful in understanding this evolution is to note that Lachs identifi ed San ta ya na as related to the pragmatists in 1992, in Ávila, at the 1st International Conference on San ta ya na. In that paper, “San ta ya na as Pragmatist,” are to be found some principal claims concerning his position of viewing San ta ya- na as sharing many tenets of pragmatism, but never the claim that San ta ya na himself was a pragmatist, and this background aids in understanding the arguments in Stoic Pragmatism. Th ey are cautious claims. Among them are the following: My aim, accordingly, is not to reveal such hidden truths as that San- ta ya na is or is not a pragmatist, but to see how much viewing him as a pragmatist contributes to our understanding, assessment and appreciation of his philosophy… [Pragmatists] do not think that our primary mode of contact with reality is cognitive and that the world Th e Lachsian Version of San ta ya na 169 exists in or for consciousness alone. Th ey are fallibilists, dispense with the solitary subject and remain resolute in the attempt to situate knowledge as an incident of animal life… Viewed in this perspective, San ta ya na is in complete agreement with the pragmatist… On the positive side, both the pragmatists and San ta ya na ground the good in the needs and desires of living creatures. An unmistakable family resemblance connects James’ account of the source of obligation in “Th e Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life,” Dewey’s discussion of the construction of good in Th e Quest for Certainty, and San ta ya na’s comments on animal nature and the good relative to it in “Hypostatic Ethics.” Th e naturalization of knowledge and the naturalization of value are one piece: both must be situated in the life-cycle of animals making their way in a diffi cult, sometimes even hostile, environment [Lachs 2003, pp. 156-160]. I quote these claims at some length in order to prepare the ground for what comes in Stoic Pragmatism. Lachs reveals his own pragmatic proclivities in the book’s fi rst chapter, “What Can Philosophy Do to Make Life Better?” Ranging from such discussions as philosophy and progress, whether the discipline of philosophy can actually form public intellectuals in today’s world, and even whether philosophy has anything to accord to human life in the twenty-fi rst century at all, the chapter concludes with the modest assertion that it does, in fact, have something to off er, but that somehow individuals need to make a serious venture “in regaining for philosophy the power it once enjoyed and making it again a central player in the drama of gradual human self-improvement.” Lachs has in mind here both the professoriate in academe, and the thoughtful lay contingent of serious-minded people who actually take philosophical problems critically. In fact, it is with the latter that Lachs tends to place the greater stress on, as he anticipates Philosophy departments in colleges and universities dwindling in infl uence and prestige, both within the realm of higher education and without. On the whole, however, Lachs is optimistic notas críticas 170 Charles Padrón as to philosophy’s future role and its contribution to our collective well-being and the social fabric’s enhancement. In taking a couple of lines from the “Epilogue,” these pragmatist proclivities, his own, are confi rmed: “Th e activist element in American philosophy seems to fi t well with my temperament. I value the sort of robust engagement with the world that evokes personal activity and aims at social improvement” [Lachs 2012, p. 193]. Only the future’s actual eventualities will unveil to us how these tensions and questions play out. What Lachs is trying to convince others to be aware of is, as in other periods of history when philosophical thought was suff used throughout the entirety of a culture, a country, a nation, or a society, that for philosophy as a possibility to become and remain relevant, to thrive in vital, general everydayness, then it needs to be freed from any form of institutional, appropriative exclusivity, and any idea of it (philosophy) adhering to a singular kind of activity or belonging to a specifi c group of people. Is this a feasible idea? I am not so sure. Philosophy can be a great leveler. Th e pragmatist outlook historically, on the whole, has always championed this supposition. No artifi cially erected barriers by individuals with professional interests should ever be able to contain it, and thereby artifi cially control its on-turnings and off -turnings. Th is is a Lachsian version of philosophy for all serious adults, similar to the Cavellian notion of philosophy “as the education of grownups.” Considerate, decent, humane awareness that we are all in this thing called life together, fraught with highly serious issues and threats, challenges and confusions, compels us, as Lachs understands it, to be attentive to the shared, social commonweal. Dewey’s opening line in Th e Quest for Certainty is relevant here: “Man who lives in a world of hazards is compelled to seek for security” [Dewey 1960, p. 3]. Th is external facet to pragmatist concerns, more than any epistemological or metaphysical ones, is what stands out as the pragmatist undergirding of Lachs’ arguments. Again, lift ing lines from the “Epilogue,” Lachs asserts: “I am interested in ordinary people and their problems because I see myself as no diff erent from Th e Lachsian Version of San ta ya na 171 them… In the end, I do not want to be absorbed in the technical details of the problems of philosophy” [Lachs 2012, p.193]. Stoic Pragmatism consists of fi ve chapters. Apart from the above- mentioned fi rst one, they are the following: 2) “Stoic Pragmatism”; 3) “Infi nite Obligations”; 4) “An Ontology for Stoic Pragmatism”; and 5) “Epilogue: Th e Personal Value and Social Usefulness of Philosophy”. As my intent is to concentrate on chapters 2 (delineating the concept behind the title of the book, stoic pragmatism) and 4 (the one containing Lachs’ discussion of how San ta ya na’s ontology provides a skeleton to his own stoic pragmatism), I will now turn my attention presently to chapters 3 and 5. Lachs delves into and dissects two instances of interesting psychological/philosophical phenomena, among others, in chapter 3: forms of blindness and moral holidays, both discussions stemming from the insights of William James.
Recommended publications
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, XII-2 | 2020 Santayana’S Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy XII-2 | 2020 Democracy as a Form of Life Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered Robin Weiss Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/2138 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.2138 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Robin Weiss, « Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], XII-2 | 2020, Online since 14 December 2020, connection on 15 December 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/2138 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ ejpap.2138 This text was automatically generated on 15 December 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered 1 Santayana’s Epiphenomenalism Reconsidered Robin Weiss 1 Recently, it has become increasingly common to question the extent to which Santayana’s philosophy of mind can and should be identified as a kind of epiphenomenalism, as has traditionally been the case. Most scholars take Santayana’s epiphenomenalism for granted, and either assert or deny that he gives an argument to support it.1 However, others have questioned whether the evident similarities between Santayana’s own views and those of modern-day epiphenomenalists obscure more significant differences. I will argue that, indeed, Santayana’s views are potentially inaccurately captured by the term “epiphenomenalism.” However, I shall argue that this is true for reasons other than other scholars have given for this view. 2 The issue turns on what Santayana means by a “cause” when he denies that ideas are causes of action.
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Hodgesand John Lachs. the Vanderbilt
    PJHU on Thinking in the Ruins:Wittgenstein and Santayana Contingency. Michael Hodges and John Lachs. The Vanderbilt Libraryof American Philosophy. Herman J. Saatkamp, Jr., ed. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 2000. Pp. xiii + 129. $29.95 h.c. 0-8265-1341-7. Anyone acquainted withWittgenstein's and Santayana's work should be aware of a number of obvious differences between the two philoso phers.While both were praised for their literary style,Wittgenstein's compact aphorisms and Santayana's flowing prose were radically dif ferent, and while Santayana seemed to unapologetically engage in systematic metaphysics, Wittgenstein's philosophy seems both anti systematic and antimetaphysical. Nevertheless, Hodges and Lachs attempt to argue thatwhile Santayana's andWittgenstein's "resources, tools, and strategies are different, the philosophical goals theywish to achieve by means of them are remarkably similar" (93). The opening chapter presents both as responding to the perceived collapse of the "comfortable certainties ofWestern civilization" (xii) that followed the FirstWorld War. The authors contrastWittgenstein's and Santayana's "conservative" and "ironically accepting" reactions to "the twentieth century's painful discovery of contingency" (3) with "Cartesian," "Neitzschean," "Pragmatist," and "Postmodernist" responses to the problem. The second chapter argues that both Santayana andWittgenstein think that"persistent and unallayable doubt shows that something has gone wrong in the intellectual enterprise," and thatwhile skepticism cannot be defeated on its own terms, those terms are irrelevant to the actual processes of inquiry.Consequently, "both reject absolute certainty as the standard of cognition and want to return the criteria of knowledge to the looser practices of ordinary life" (32).
    [Show full text]
  • Fiala American Philosophy Fall 2019.4
    10/23/19 American Values and Philosophy Dr. Andrew Fiala [email protected] www.andrewfiala.com @PhilosophyFiala American Values and Philosophy Oct. 2, 9, 16, 23 • This course will explore the question of what it means to be an American from a philosophical perspective, with a special focus on philosophers in the American tradition: Ralph Waldo Emerson, Henry David Thoreau, John Muir, William James, John Dewey, Jane Addams, and others. Topics will include questions about immigration and identity, justice and inclusion, nature and technology, and hope for progress. Contemporary affairs will be discussed from a philosophical perspective. 1 10/23/19 Course Plan • Oct. 2: The Problem of American Philosophy • Who are we? What do we value? What unites and divides us? • Oct. 9: Individualism, Polarization, and Division • Problems: Monism, Pluralism, Relativism and Moral Anarchism • Oct. 16: Science, Religion, and Secularism • Problems: Empiricism, Mysticism, and Fundamentalism • Oct. 23: Pragmatism, Experimentation, and the Future • Problems: Change/Progress, Fear, Meliorism, Hope Democracy and Education • The devotion of democracy to education is a familiar fact. The superficial explanation is that a government resting upon popular suffrage cannot be successful unless those who elect and who obey their governors are educated. • Democracy is more than a form of government; it is primarily a mode of associated living, of conjoined communicated experience. • John Dewey, Democracy and Education (1916), p. 87 2 10/23/19 Progress, Science, and Education • Intelligence properly used can do away with evils once though inevitable. To subjugate devastating disease is no longer a dream; the hope of abolishing poverty is not utopian.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in Digital Culture: Images and the Aestheticization of the Public Intellectual’S Narratives
    volume 4 no. 1 (2020) DOI:10.14394/eidos.jpc.2020.0003 Krzysztof Piotr Skowroński Institute of Philosophy University of Opole, Poland; Berlin Practical Philosophy International Forum e.V., Germany https://orcid.org/0000-0003-3814-1346 Philosophy in Digital Culture: Images and the Aestheticization of the Public Intellectual’s Narratives Abstract: The present paper deals with the problem of thedigital-culture-public-philosophy as a possible response of those philosophers who see the need to face the challenges of the Internet and the visual culture that constitutes an important part of the Internet cultural space. It claims that this type of philosophy would have to, among many other things, modify and broaden philosophers’ traditional mode of communication. It would have to expand its textual, or mainly text-related, communication mode into the aesthetic and visual communication mode. More precisely, philosophers would have to learn how to aestheticize and visualize their ethical (epistemic, ontological, social) narratives by using some digital tools – YouTube clips for example. Keywords: philosophy, digital culture, Internet, narratives, aestheticization, ethics, stoic pragmatism Henryk Elzenberg (1887–1967), one of the central figures of Polish philosophy of culture, understood culture as a value-creation activity or a set of efforts that aim at valuable states of affairs.1 To explore his view he referred, among others, to ancient Stoics;2 they understood philosophy as predominantly a practical attitude 1) Skowroński, “Axiocentrism in
    [Show full text]
  • On the Practical Joys of Lachs's Stoic Pragmatism
    Chapter 12 ‘Raisins in the Bread of Life’: On the Practical Joys of Lachs’s Stoic Pragmatism Shannon Sullivan The goal of this paper is twofold: (i) to build bridges between John Lachs’s recent books In Love with Life (1998) and Stoic Pragmatism (2012), thinking through the complex connections and tensions that run through them, espe- cially with regard to his use of stoicism, and (ii) to understand the philosophi- cal influences on Lachs’s culminating work, which as Lachs (2012, 1) explains is found in Stoic Pragmatism in particular. I also choose to concentrate on these books since in many ways they showcase why practical philosophy is important to Lachs: on his account, the purpose of philosophy is to enhance the down-to-earth practices and experiences of human beings. As readers of Lachs know, virtually all of his philosophical work, especially The Relevance of Philosophy to Life (1995) and most recently Meddling (2014), values practi- cal philosophy. In that respect, In Love with Life and Stoic Pragmatism are not unique. But these two books are distinctive in Lachs’s considerable body of work because they explicitly take up stoicism as a tool for practical philosophy. In doing so, these books help bring out what I believe is the centerpiece of the practical enterprise for Lachs: the experience of joy. Ameliorating human experiences and activities might involve increasing material comfort and al- leviating certain stresses and pains, as it surely does in Lachs’s view. But with- out joy, as Lachs also would agree, none of those improvements matter.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Pragmatist Ethics in the Time of Pandemic Krzysztof Piotr
    Ethics & Bioethics (in Central Europe), 2021, 11 (1–2), 82–91 DOI:10.2478/ebce-2021-0010 Stoic pragmatist ethics in the time of pandemic Krzysztof Piotr Skowroński1 Abstract The present paper is a response, of sorts, to the challenges of the coronavirus pandemic (COVID) and lockdown that we all must face. We have an idea of what doctors, nurses, teachers, among many of the other professions, do for the general public, but one may ask whether there is something substantial that philosophers and ethicists can offer in these circumstances. The thesis of this paper is that the stoic attitude towards times of trouble and the pragmatist way of finding out what is possible to elevate the Quality of living against all odds, if skilfully interwoven, could be an important tool in keeping mental health in good shape and, additionally, could contribute to the cultural scene at large. If this is the case, stoic pragmatists can indeed offer an interesting example of practical philosophy for many audiences, especially during the pandemic lockdown and, perhaps, for other serious difficulties or problems. To be effective in delivering their message, stoic pragmatists, as most with philosophers today, should enrich their textual and oral modes of traditional transmission of knowledge and become digital- culture public intellectuals that can recognize and reach more general audiences by, among other things, visual modes of digital communication. Keywords: stoic pragmatism, ethics, pandemic, digital culture Stoic ethics and pragmatist ethics: Any points in common? There must be something exceptional in Stoic ethics (in this text, capital “S” refers to the historical Stoicism, small “s” to its contemporary trajectories, and “SP” to stoic pragmatism).
    [Show full text]
  • “Stoic Pragmatism”
    Philosophy Bakes Bread, Episode Five with Dr. John Lachs “Stoic Pragmatism” Transcription by Kevin Dotson, February 2017. For those interested, here's how to cite this transcript or episode for academic or professional purposes: Weber, Eric Thomas, Anthony Cashio, and John Lachs, "Stoic Pragmatism," Philosophy Bakes Bread, Transcribed by Kevin Dotson, WRFL Lexington 88.1 FM, Lexington, KY, February 9, 2017. Announcer: This podcast is brought to you by WRFL, radio free Lexington. Find us online at http://WRFL.FM. Catch us on your FM radio while you’re in Central Kentucky at 88.1 FM, all the way to the left. Thank you for listening, and please be sure to subscribe. Dr. Eric Weber: As I said folks, this is WRFL Lexington, I am Dr. Eric Thomas Weber, and I am here to share with you episode five of Philosophy Bakes Bread. Without further ado. [Intro Music]. Dr. Weber: Hello and welcome to philosophy bakes bread, food for thought about life and leadership, a production of the society of philosophers in America, aka: SOPHIA. I am Dr. Eric Thomas Weber. Dr. Anthony Cashio: And I am Dr. Anthony Cashio. A famous phrase says that philosophy bakes no bread, that it’s not practical. But we in Sophia and on this show aim to correct that misperception. Dr. Weber: Philosophy Bakes Bread airs on WFRL Lexington 88.1 and is recorded and distributed as a podcast next, so if you can’t catch us live on the air, subscribe, and be sure to reach out to us. You can find us online at http://philosophersinamerica.com/philosophy-bakes- bread.
    [Show full text]
  • Capps CV January 2021
    JOHN CAPPS ADDRESS Department of Philosophy E-MAIL [email protected] Rochester Institute of Technology WEB johncapps.net Rochester, NY 14623 USA EMPLOYMENT 2015- Professor 2011-2014 Chair, Department of Philosophy 2006-2015 Associate Professor 2008-2010 Senior Associate Dean, College of Liberal Arts 2007-2008 Associate Dean, College of Liberal Arts 2000-2006 Assistant Professor, Rochester Institute of Technolgy 1998-2000 Assistant Professor, University of North Florida 1998-2000 Visiting Assistant Professor, College of Charleston AREAS AOS Epistemology, American Philosophy AOC Logic, History of Philosophy (especially 20th century Anglo-American) EDUCATION 1997 Northwestern University: Ph.D in Philosophy Dissertation: Context and Inquiry: Justification in Naturalized Epistemology Committee: Thomas Ryckman, Arthur Fine, Michael Williams 1994 Northwestern University: MA in Philosophy 1991 St. John’s College, Annapolis: BA PUBLICATIONS Articles and Book Chapters 1. Forthcoming. What we talk about when we talk about truth: Dewey, Wittgenstein, and the pragmatic test. International Journal of Philosophical Studies. John Capps | 1 2. Forthcoming 2021. The less said the better: Dewey, Neurath, and mid- century theories of truth. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. 3. 2020. Pragmatic accounts of belief and truth: A response to Aaron Zimmerman’s Belief: a Pragmatic Picture. William James Studies. 16: 39-56. 4. 2020. Democracy, truth, and understanding: an epistemic argument for democracy. In M.C. Navin and R. Nunan (Eds.), Democracy, Populism, and Truth. New York: Springer. 5. 2020. A common-sense pragmatic theory of truth. Philosophia. 48: 463-481. DOI: 10.1007/s11406-019-00099-z 6. 2020. Truth and the Goldilocks principle. Think. 19: 65-74.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, X-2 | 2018 Krzysztof Piotr Skowronski (Ed.), John Lachs’S Practical Philosophy: Critical
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy X-2 | 2018 Pragmatism and Idealism Krzysztof Piotr SKOWRONSKI (ed.), John Lachs’s Practical Philosophy: Critical Essays on His Thought with Replies and Bibliography Leiden-Boston, Brill/Rodopi, 2018. pp. XXX + 336 Glenn Tiller Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1426 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.1426 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Glenn Tiller, « Krzysztof Piotr SKOWRONSKI (ed.), John Lachs’s Practical Philosophy: Critical Essays on His Thought with Replies and Bibliography », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], X-2 | 2018, Online since 11 January 2019, connection on 24 September 2020. URL : http:// journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1426 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.1426 This text was automatically generated on 24 September 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Krzysztof Piotr Skowronski (ed.), John Lachs’s Practical Philosophy: Critical... 1 Krzysztof Piotr SKOWRONSKI (ed.), John Lachs’s Practical Philosophy: Critical Essays on His Thought with Replies and Bibliography Leiden-Boston, Brill/Rodopi, 2018. pp. XXX + 336 Glenn Tiller REFERENCES Krzysztof Piotr SKOWRONSKI (ed.), John Lachs’s Practical Philosophy: Critical Essays on His Thought with Replies and Bibliography, Leiden-Boston, Brill/Rodopi, 2018. pp. XXX + 336 1 Few if any contemporary philosophers have done more to promote American philosophy and philosophy in America than John Lachs. The creativity and sheer industriousness that characterize his sixty-year career as a producer and advocate of both professional and public philosophy are extraordinary, while his reputation as a teacher of philosophy, especially his work with undergraduate students, is described as “legendary” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • John Lachs Stoic Pragmatism. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press 2012
    Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 6 John Lachs Stoic Pragmatism. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press 2012. 193 pages $70.00 (cloth ISBN 978–0–253–35718–2); $25.00 (paper ISBN 978–0– 253–22376–0) John Lachs has long been one of pragmatism’s best defenders. His work is inspired by the writings of John Dewey, William James, Josiah Royce, and especially George Santayana. Stoic Pragmatism is distinguished from his previous books in its attempt to unite several long-held views into a general philosophy of life. In the introduction, he tells us that “[a]ge clarifies” and that many years of reflection have but recently brought the author to “take delight in thinking that I have now discovered my beliefs about some of the deepest problems, beliefs I think I have acted upon all my life” (1). The leading principle in Lachs’s philosophy is the normative stance of pragmatism. “Whatever specific beliefs pragmatists share concerning experience, knowledge, value, and meaning,” he writes, “they generally agree that a central part of the business of life is to make life better” (40). Stoicism, by contrast, emphasizes the rational limits of human striving. At first glance, it appears “these two great philosophical traditions” promote “incompatible values.” However, Lachs believes that the “radical distinction between the stoic and the pragmatist is misleading and inaccurate” (41). Over the course of four chapters and an autobiographical epilogue, he provides reasons for thinking that, as he puts it, “‘stoic pragmatism’ is not only possible but also desirable, and that it provides a better attitude to life than either of the two views alone” (42).
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Last revised: 1/18/21 David Louis Hildebrand, Ph.D. Professor and Chair, Department of Philosophy University of Colorado Denver Box 179, P.O. Box 173364, Denver, CO 80217-3364 (303) 315-7223, [email protected] http://www.davidhildebrand.org Education 1997 Ph.D. in Philosophy, University of Texas at Austin, Austin, TX 1987 B.A. in Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA Professional Experience 2013-2021 Chair, Philosophy Department, University of CO Denver, Denver, CO 2019- Professor, University of CO Denver, Denver, CO 2009-2019 Associate Professor, University of CO Denver, Denver, CO 2004-09 Assistant Professor, University of CO Denver, Denver, CO 2003-04 Visiting Assistant Professor, University of CO Denver, Denver, CO 2001-03 Lecturer, University of Memphis and Christian Brothers University, Memphis, TN 2000-01 Lecturer, Rice University and University of Houston, Houston, TX 1999-2000 Lecturer, University of Texas at Austin and St. Edward's University, Austin, TX 1999 Lecturer, Austin Community College, Austin, TX 1997-98 Lecturer, University of Texas at Austin 1997 Adjunct Professor, St. Edward’s University, Austin, TX 1997 Instructor, Austin Community College, Austin, TX 1995-96 Assistant Instructor, full teaching duties, University of Texas at Austin 1991-95 Teaching Assistant, University of Texas at Austin 1988-90 Director of Education and Public Relations, Washington Project for the Arts, Washington, D.C. Refereed Publications Books 2008 John Dewey: A Beginner's Guide. Oxford, UK: Oneworld Press, 2008. 2003 Beyond Realism and Antirealism: John Dewey and the Neopragmatists. Vanderbilt University Press, 2003. Articles 2019 "Pihlström’s Pragmatist Metaphysics: Transcendence and Meliorism." Refereed.
    [Show full text]
  • Scott Forrest Aikin
    Scott F. Aikin, Ph.D. Curriculum Vitae (Fall 2020) Associate Professor of Philosophy, Vanderbilt University Director of Undergraduate Studies in Philosophy AOS: Epistemology, Ancient Philosophy, Pragmatism AOC: Argumentation Theory, Philosophy of Religion Ph.D. in Philosophy, Vanderbilt University (2006) M.A. in Philosophy, University of Montana (1999) A.B. in Classics, Washington University in St. Louis (1994) Single-Authored Books • Evidentialism and the Will to Believe. Bloomsbury (2014). • Epistemology and the Regress Problem. Routledge (2011). Co-Authored Books • Political Argument in a Polarized Age. With Robert B. Talisse. Polity (2020). • Pragmatism, Pluralism, and the Nature of Philosophy. With Robert B. Talisse. Routledge (2018). • Why We Argue (And How We Should). With Robert B. Talisse. Routledge (2014). o Second Edition (2019) • Reasonable Atheism. With Robert B. Talisse. Prometheus Books (2011). • Pragmatism: A Guide for the Perplexed. With Robert B. Talisse. Continuum Books (2008). Edited Volumes • Epistemology’s Ancient Origins and Contemporary Development. Special issue of Logos and Episteme (2019) 10:1. • Skeptical Issues in Political Epistemology. Special issue of Symposion (2018) 5:2. Co-edited with Tempest Henning. • The Regress Problem: Meta-theory, Development, and Criticism. Special issue of Metaphilosophy. (2014) 45:2. Co-edited with Jeanne Peijnenburg. • The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce to the Present. Co-edited with Robert B. Talisse. Princeton University Press (2011). • Thinking about Logic: Classic Essays. Co-edited with Steven M. Cahn and Robert B. Talisse. Westview Press (2010). Professional Essays by Year Forthcoming • “Deep Disagreement and the Problem of the Criterion.” Topoi – Special Issue on Epistemology and Disagreement (Forthcoming). • “Does Metaphilosophically Pragmatist Anti-Skepticism Work?” Logos and Episteme (Forthcoming).
    [Show full text]