<<

Comparative Federalism Constitutional Arrangements and Case Law

Francesco Palermo and Karl K ö ssler

OXFORD AND PORTLAND, OREGON 2017 Hart Publishing An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc

Hart Publishing Ltd Bloomsbury Publishing Plc Kemp House 50 Bedford Square Chawley Park London Cumnor Hill WC1B 3DP Oxford OX2 9PH UK UK

www.hartpub.co.uk www.bloomsbury.com Published in North America (US and Canada) by Hart Publishing c/o International Specialized Book Services 920 NE 58th Avenue, Suite 300 Portland , OR 97213-3786 USA www.isbs.com HART PUBLISHING, the Hart/Stag logo, BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2017 © Francesco Palermo and Karl Kössler 2017 Francesco Palermo and Karl Kössler have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 to be identifi ed as Authors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. While every care has been taken to ensure the accuracy of this work, no responsibility for loss or damage occasioned to any person acting or refraining from action as a result of any statement in it can be accepted by the authors, editors or publishers. All UK Government legislation and other public sector information used in the work is Crown Copyright © . All and House of Commons information used in the work is Parliamentary Copyright © . This information is reused under the terms of the Open Government Licence v3.0 ( http://www. nationalarchives.gov.uk/doc/open-government-licence/version/3 ) except where otherwise stated. All Eur-lex material used in the work is © , http://eur-lex.europa.eu/ , 1998 – 2017. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-1-50990-149-4 ePDF: 978-1-50990-151-7 ePub: 978-1-50990-150-0 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Names: Palermo, Francesco, author. | Kössler, Karl, 1979-, author. Title: Comparative federalism : constitutional arrangements and case law / Francesco Palermo and Karl Kössler. Description: Portland, Oregon : Hart Publishing, 2017. | Series: Hart studies in comparative public law ; volume 19 | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifi ers: LCCN 2017025633 (print) | LCCN 2017027012 (ebook) | ISBN 9781509901500 (Epub) | ISBN 9781509901494 (hardback : alk. paper) Subjects: LCSH: Federal government—Europe. | Constitutional law—Europe. | Regionalism—Europe. | —Europe. | International and municipal law—Europe. Classifi cation: LCC KJC5048 (ebook) | LCC KJC5048 .P35 2017 (print) | DDC 342.24/042—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017025633 Typeset by Compuscript Ltd, Shannon Printed and bound in by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY To fi nd out more about our authors and books visit www.hartpublishing.co.uk . Here you will fi nd extracts, author information, details of forthcoming events and the option to sign up for our newsletters. Contents

Preface ...... v Table of Cases ...... xiii

Introduction ...... 1 0.1 Why This Book and What to Expect from it ...... 1 0.2 Understanding Federalism—Understanding of Federalism ...... 3 0.3 Methodology and Terminology ...... 5 0.3.1 The Comparative Method ...... 5 0.3.2 Terminology ...... 8 0.4 Structure ...... 10 Part I: Foundations 1. Concepts ...... 13 1.1 Federalism ...... 13 1.1.1 Traditions in Conceptualising Federalism ...... 14 1.1.2 Federalism and Federation—Towards Common Ground ...... 17 1.2 Regionalism ...... 20 1.2.1 Regionalisation vs Regionalism ...... 22 1.2.2 New Regionalism, Multilevel Governance and the ‘Europe of the Regions’ ...... 25 1.2.3 The Proliferation of Regionalisms ...... 30 2. Manifestations ...... 34 2.1 Confederation ...... 35 2.1.1 Defi nition ...... 35 2.1.2 Are Confederations Transitional? ...... 36 2.2 Federal State ...... 38 2.2.1 The Compact as the Traditional Defi nition: The ‘Federal Big Bang’ ...... 38 2.2.2 Form Follows Function: The Role of History in Shaping Federal Manifestations ...... 42 2.2.3 Defi nition by Means of Institutional Elements ...... 47 2.3 Regional State and Related Manifestations ...... 50 2.3.1 Defi nition and Relation to the Federal State ...... 50 2.3.2 Rationale and Cases ...... 51 2.3.3 ...... 55 2.3.4 Autonomy and Similar Manifestations ...... 58 2.4 The EU: Federalism Beyond the State? ...... 61 2.5 Living Without Defi nitions ...... 64 viii Contents

3. History ...... 67 3.1 Ancient Unions ...... 67 3.2 The Age of Confederations ...... 68 3.2.1 Classical European Confederations ...... 68 3.2.2 The United States of America under the Articles of Confederation ...... 70 3.3 Archetypes of the Federal State ...... 72 3.3.1 The United States of America (1787) ...... 72 3.3.2 Switzerland (1848) ...... 76 3.3.3 Germany (1867/1871) ...... 79 4. Debates ...... 83 4.1 Sovereignty in Federal Systems: Indivisible or Shared? ...... 83 4.1.1 The Theory of Indivisible Sovereignty and Its Contestation ...... 84 4.1.2 Divided Sovereignty in the United States and Beyond ...... 88 4.1.3 The Sovereignty Question in the European Union ...... 92 4.2 Federalism in Diverse Societies: Cure or Curse? ...... 97 4.2.1 Multinational Federalism as a Concept ...... 98 4.2.2 The Legal Status of Internal Minorities ...... 101 4.2.3 Secession under Federal Constitutions ...... 105 4.3 Federalism and Participatory in an Era of Pluralism ...... 111 4.3.1 Federalism and Participatory Democracy: Two Faces of Pluralism ...... 111 4.3.2 The Crisis of Democracy: An Opportunity for Federalism? .....114 Part II: Self-Rule and Shared Rule 5. Autonomy of Subnational Entities ...... 125 5.1 The Constitutional Dimension: Constitutional Autonomy ...... 126 5.1.1 Defi nition and Scope ...... 126 5.1.2 Limits to Constitutional Autonomy: Supremacy and Homogeneity Clauses ...... 130 5.1.3 Practical Use of Constitutional Autonomy ...... 136 5.2 The Legislative Dimension: Distribution of Legislative Powers ...... 139 5.2.1 Distribution of Powers and the Residual Clause ...... 139 5.2.2 Dual vs Cooperative Systems ...... 146 5.2.3 Flexibilisation and Centralisation: Implied Powers ...... 149 5.3 The Administrative Dimension: The Relationship between Legislative and Administrative Powers ...... 156 5.4 The Judicial Dimension: The Court Systems ...... 159 6. Participation of Subnational Entities at the National Level ...... 164 6.1 Scope, Institutions and Procedures for Participation ...... 164 6.2 Institutional Forms of Participation ...... 165 6.2.1 Second Chambers ...... 165 6.2.1.1 Origins and Constitutional Entrenchment ...... 167 6.2.1.2 The Senate Model: Variations, Appointment and Composition ...... 169 Contents ix

6.2.1.3 The Council (or Ambassadorial) Model: A Germany Legacy ...... 172 6.2.1.4 Hybrid Second Chambers ...... 176 6.2.2 Intergovernmental Bodies ...... 177 6.3 Procedural Forms of Participation ...... 178 6.3.1 Constitutional Amendment ...... 178 6.3.1.1 Direct Participation by the Legislatures or Electorates of Subnational Entities ...... 179 6.3.1.2 Indirect (or Absence of) Participation Through Second Chambers ...... 183 6.3.2 Territorial Changes ...... 186 6.3.3 Legislative (and Administrative) Functions ...... 190 6.3.4 Appointments ...... 193 6.3.5 Other Functions ...... 199 7. Financial Relations ...... 201 7.1 Financial Relations: Signifi cance, Scope and Regulation ...... 201 7.1.1 Signifi cance ...... 201 7.1.2 Scope: Local and Supranational Dimensions ...... 202 7.1.3 Regulation: Legal Sources and (A)Symmetrical Design ...... 205 7.2 Revenue Powers ...... 210 7.2.1 Types of Subnational Entities’ Own Revenues ...... 210 7.2.2 Taxing Powers ...... 211 7.2.3 A Trend Towards Tax Centralisation? ...... 222 7.3 Spending Power ...... 228 7.3.1 Spending Power and Conditional Grants ...... 228 7.3.2 Legal Basis and Limits of the General Spending Power ...... 229 7.3.3 Spending Power and Fiscal Discipline ...... 235 7.4 Equalisation ...... 240 8. Prevention and Resolution of Confl icts ...... 246 8.1 Intergovernmental Relations ...... 246 8.1.1 Principles: Federal Loyalty and Similar Precepts ...... 249 8.1.2 Institutions: The Predominance of the Executive Branch ...... 253 8.1.3 Instruments: Delegation and Intergovernmental Agreements ...... 257 8.2 Ex ante Scrutiny of Subnational Law ...... 261 8.2.1 Judicial Scrutiny of Draft Legislation ...... 261 8.2.2 Political or Judicial Scrutiny of Subnational Constitutions ...... 263 8.3 Constitutional Adjudication ...... 266 8.3.1 Signifi cance, Scope and Impact ...... 266 8.3.2 Constitutional Review and Other Functions ...... 272 9. Local Government ...... 281 9.1 Local Government in a Changed Factual and Legal Context ...... 281 9.2 Legal Recognition of Local Self-Government ...... 284 9.2.1 Source of Recognition ...... 285 x Contents

9.2.2 Scope and Quality of Recognition ...... 286 9.2.3 The Problem of (Over)Regulation ...... 287 9.3 Powers of Local Governments ...... 290 9.3.1 Assignment of Local Powers ...... 290 9.3.2 Restrictions of the Exercise of Local Powers ...... 295 9.3.2.1 Overburdening with Delegated Tasks ...... 295 9.3.2.2 Supervision Prevailing over Intergovernmental Collaboration ...... 297 9.3.2.3 Limited Financial Resources ...... 300 9.4 Structure of Local Government ...... 305 9.4.1 Amalgamation ...... 305 9.4.2 Inter-municipal Cooperation ...... 309 9.4.3 Umbrella Entities ...... 312 9.5 Local Government as a Genuine Third Level? ...... 314 Part III: Powers and Policies: Between Autonomy and Homogeneity 10. Fundamental Rights...... 321 10.1 United States of America ...... 322 10.2 Switzerland ...... 327 10.3 Canada ...... 330 10.4 Germany ...... 333 10.5 Spain ...... 338 10.6 Comparative Conclusions ...... 341 11. Social Welfare and Healthcare ...... 346 11.1 United States ...... 349 11.2 Canada ...... 355 11.3 Belgium ...... 361 11.4 Spain ...... 365 11.5 ...... 370 11.6 Comparative Conclusions ...... 376 12. Environmental Protection ...... 382 12.1 United States ...... 383 12.2 Switzerland ...... 387 12.3 Germany ...... 391 12.4 Italy ...... 393 12.5 United Kingdom ...... 396 12.6 Comparative Conclusions ...... 398 13. Immigration and Migrant Integration ...... 403 13.1 Switzerland ...... 404 13.2 Canada ...... 407 13.3 Australia ...... 411 13.4 Germany ...... 412 13.5 Belgium ...... 415 13.6 Comparative Conclusions ...... 418 Contents xi

14. External Relations ...... 423 14.1 United States ...... 425 14.2 Switzerland ...... 428 14.3 Canada ...... 431 14.4 Belgium ...... 436 14.5 Spain ...... 439 14.6 Comparative Conclusions ...... 443 15. Concluding Remarks ...... 448 15.1 Federalism in the Twenty-First Century ...... 448 15.2 A Federal Research Agenda: The Four ‘Ps’ ...... 449

Index ...... 453

Table of Cases

Note that judgments presented in greater detail in the case law boxes are in bold.

Australia High Court of Australia Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd (1920) 28 CLR 129 (Engineers’ case) ...... 268 Attorney-General (Cth) v Colonial Sugar Refi ning Co Ltd (1913) 17 CLR 644 ...... 127 Austin v Commonwealth (2003) 215 CLR 185 ...... 127 Australian Communist Party v Commonwealth (1951) 83 CLR 1 ...... 132 Clayton v Heffron (1960) 105 CLR 214 ...... 127 Judiciary and , Re (1921) 29 CLR 257 (Advisory Opinions case) ...... 277 New South v Commonwealth (2006) 229 CLR 1 (Work Choices case) ...... 232 Pape v of Taxation (2009) 238 CLR 1 ...... 268 Queensland v Commonwealth (1977) 139 CLR 585 (Second Territories Representation case) ...... 172 R v Hughes (2000) 202 CLR 535 ...... 257 South Australia v Commonwealth (1942) 65 CLR 373 (First Uniform Tax case) ...... 223 Streets v Queensland Bar Association (1989) 168 CLR 461 ...... 132 Thomas v Mowbray (2007) 233 CLR 307 ...... 257 Victoria v Commonwealth (1957) 99 CLR 575 (Second Uniform Income Tax case) ...... 223 , 232 Wakim, Re (1999) 198 CLR 511 ...... 257 Western Australia v Commonwealth (1975) 134 CLR 201 (First Territories Representation case) ...... 172 Western Australia v Commonwealth (1995) 183 CLR 373 (Native Title Act case) ...... 132 Williams v Commonwealth (2012) 248 CLR 156 (School Chaplains case) ...... 231 Williams v Commonwealth (2014) 252 CLR 416...... 232

Austria Constitutional Court VfSlg 8/1921 ...... 158 VfSlg 206/1923 ...... 158 VfSlg 2455/1952 ...... 39 , 166 VfSlg 3055/1956 ...... 263 VfSlg 5676/1968 ...... 134 VfSlg 6944/1972 ...... 294 VfSlg 8719/1979 ...... 294 VfSlg 8831/1980 ...... 250 VfSlg 9886/1983 ...... 260 VfSlg 10292/1984 ...... 133 , 250 xiv Table of Cases

VfSlg 10510/1985 ...... 158 VfSlg 11403/1987 ...... 39 VfSlg 11669/1988 ...... 39 VfSlg 13500/1993 ...... 288 VfSlg 14534/1996 ...... 251 VfSlg 15552/1999 ...... 250 VfSlg 16241/2001 ...... 134 VfSlg 17173/2004 ...... 191 VfSlg 19782/2013 ...... 170 VfSlg 19868/2014 ...... 297 VfSlg 19894/2014 ...... 308

Belgium Constitutional Court No 33/1992 ...... 439 No 49/1994 ...... 249 No 42/1997 ...... 249 No 04/1998 ...... 214 No 33/2001 ...... 363 No 100/2003 ...... 214 No 166/2003 ...... 146 No 5/2004 ...... 417 No 51/2006 ...... 363 No 101/2008 ...... 417 No 33/2011 ...... 247 No 67/2014 ...... 247

Bosnia and Herzegovina Constitutional Court Partial Decision U5/98 III of 1 July 2000 (Constituent Peoples case) ...... 99 , 104 Partial Decision U5/98 IV of 18 August 2000 ...... 147 U 25/00 of 23 March 2001 ...... 105 U 37/01 of 3 November 2001 ...... 105 Partial Decision U44/01 of 27 February 2004 ...... 99 Partial Decision U4/04 of 31 March 2006 ...... 99 U3/13 of 26 November 2015 ...... 99

Canada Judicial Committee of the Privy Council (JCPC) and Supreme Court of Canada Angers v MNR [1957] Ex CR 83 ...... 379 Anti-Infl ation Act, Reference Re [1976] 2 SCR 373 ...... 149 Authority of the in Relation to the Upper House, Reference Re [1980] 1 SCR 54 ...... 168 Bank of Toronto v Lambe [1887] 12 AC 575 (JCPC) ...... 215 BC Motor Vehicle Act, Reference Re [1985] 2 SCR 486 ...... 145 Table of Cases xv

Bell Canada v Quebec (Commission de la santé et de la sé curit é du travail) [1988] 1 SCR 749 ...... 145 , 357 Boucher v Stelco Inc [2005] 3 SCR 279 ...... 259 Bruker v Marcovitz [2007] 3 SCR 607 ...... 333 Canada Assistance Plan (BC), Reference Re [1991] 2 SCR 525 ...... 233 , 261 , 358 , 379 Canada (AG) v Ontario (AG) [1937] AC 326 (JCPC) ...... 145 , 435 Canada (AG) v Ontario (AG) [1937] AC 355 (JCPC) ...... 270 , 356 , 376 Citizens Insurance Co v Parsons [1881] 7 AC 96 ...... 144 Edwards v Canada (AG) [1930] AC 124 ...... 145 , 272 Eldridge v British Columbia (AG) [1997] 2 SCR 624 ...... 360 Employment Insurance Act , ss 22 and 23, Reference Re [2005] 2 SCR 669 ...... 357 Finlay v Canada (Minister of Finance) [1986] 2 SCR 607 ...... 231 Ford v Quebec (AG) [1988] 2 SCR 712 ...... 331 , 342 Godbout v Longueuil (City of) [1997] 3 SCR 844 ...... 333 Hodge v The Queen (Ont) [1883] 9 AC 117 (JCPC) ...... 145 Initiative and Referendum Act, Reference Re [1919] AC 935 (JCPC) ...... 120 , 331 Law Society of British Columbia v Mangat [2001] 3 SCR 113 ...... 410 Lovelace v Ontario [2000] 1 SCR 950 ...... 235 Manitoba (AG) v Forest [1979] 2 SCR 1032 ...... 127 Multiple Access Ltd v McCutcheon [1982] 2 SCR 161 ...... 133 Nova Scotia (AG) v Canada (AG) [1951] SCR 31 ...... 257 Objection by Quebec to Resolution to Amend the Constitution, Reference Re [1982] 2 SCR 793 ...... 181 Ontario (AG) v Ontario Public Service Employees’ Union [1987] 2 SCR 2 ...... 127 Ontario (AG) v Canada (AG) [1912] AC 571 (JCPC) ...... 277 Ontario (AG) v Canada (AG) [1896] AC 348 (JCPC) ...... 132 Quebec (AG) v Blaikie [1979] 2 SCR 1016 ...... 127 R v Crown Zellerbach Canada Ltd [1988] 1 SCR 401 ...... 149 R v Nat Bell Liquors Ltd [1922] 2 AC 128 (JCPC) ...... 120 , 331 Resolution to Amend the Constitution, Reference Re [1981] 1 SCR 753 ...... 180 , 277 Same-Sex Marriage, Reference Re [2004] 3 SCR 698 ...... 145 Schneider v British Columbia [1982] 2 SCR 112 ...... 360 , 378 Secession of Qué bec, Reference Re [1998] 2 SCR 217 ...... 38 , 109 , 277 Securities Act, Reference Re [2011] 3 SCR 837 ...... 269 Senate Reform, Reference Re [2014] 1 SCR 704 ...... 168 Solski (Tutor of) v Quebec () [2005] 1 SCR 201 ...... 342 Supreme Court Act, ss 5 and 6, Reference Re [2014] 1 SCR 433 ...... 196 Syndicat Northcrest v Anselem [2004] 2 SCR 551 ...... 333 The Queen (Ont) v Board of Transport [1968] SCR 118 ...... 235 Toronto (City of) Electric Commissioners v Snider [1925] AC 396 (JCPC) 412 ...... 360 UL Canada Inc v Quebec (AG) [2005] 1 SCR 143 ...... 259 Ward v Canada (AG) [2002] 1 SCR 569 ...... 144

European Union Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU)

Case 8/55 F é dé ration charbonniè re de Belgique v ECSC High Authority [1955] ECR 201 ...... 152 Case 26/62 Van Gend en Loos v Administratie der Belastingen [1963] ECR 3 ...... 63 , 93 xvi Table of Cases

Case 6/64 Costa v ENEL [1964] ECR 1194 ...... 63 , 93 Case 29/69 Stauder v City of Ulm [1969] ECR 419 ...... 63 Case 11/70 Internationale Handelsgesellschaft v Einfuhr- und Vorratsstelle fü r Getreide und Futtermittel [1970] ECR 1125 ...... 63 Case 22/70 Commission v Council [1971] ECR 263 (AETR) ...... 153 Case 8/73 Hauptzollamt Bremerhaven v Massey Ferguson [1973] ECR 897 ...... 152 Case 294/83 Les Verts v Parliament [1986] ECR 1339 ...... 63 Joined Cases 281, 283, 284, 285 and 287/85 Germany & Ors v Commission [1987] ECR 3203 ...... 152 Case 45/86 Commission v Council [1987] ECR 1493 ...... 152 Case 103/88 Fratelli Costanzo [1989] ECR 1839 ...... 425 Case C-376/98 Germany v Parliament [2000] ECR I-8419 ...... 144 , 424 Case C-103/01 Commission v Germany [2003] ECR I-5369 ...... 424 Case C-212/06 Government of the French Community and Walloon Government v Flemish Government [2008] ECR I-1683 ...... 363

France

Council of State Case Nicolo (1989) ...... 63

Germany Federal Constitutional Court 1 BVerfGE 14 S ü dweststaat (Southwest State) ...... 186 , 275 , 280 1 BVerfGE 117 Finanzausgleichsgesetz (Financial Equalization Act) ...... 243 – 44 1 BVerfGE 167 Kommunales Selbstverwaltungsrecht (Local Self-Governance) ...... 286 1 BVerfGE 299 Wohnungsbauf ö rderung (Housing Funding)...... 250 2 BVerfGE 237 Hypothekensicherungsgesetz (Mortgage Security Act) ...... 336 4 BVerfGE 178 Landesgesetz ü ber die Verwaltungsgerichtsbarkeit (State Law on Administrative Jurisdiction) ...... 128 5 BVerfGE 34 Baden-Abstimmung (Baden Home Association) ...... 187 6 BVerfGE 32 Elfes-Urteil (Elfes case) ...... 338 6 BVerfGE 309 Reichskonkordat (Concordat case) ...... 250 8 BVerfGE 122 Volksbefragung Hessen (Hesse Referendum case) ...... 250 9 BVerfGE 268 Bremer Personalvertretung (Bremen Civil Servant case) ...... 135 12 BVerfGE 205 1. Rundfunkentscheidung (First Broadcasting case) ...... 280 22 BVerfGE 267 Einheitliches Grundrecht (Uniform Fundamental Right) ...... 336 26 BVerfGE 228 Sorsum ...... 299 27 BVerfGE 71 Leipziger Volkszeitung (Leipzig Daily Newspaper) ...... 336 32 BVerfGE 333 Erg ä nzungsabgabe (Supplemental Tax) ...... 229 33 BVerfGE 303 Numerus Clausus I ...... 260 34 BVerfGE 9 Besoldungsvereinheitlichung (Federal– State Salary) ...... 91 36 BVerfGE 342 Niedersä chsisches Landesbesoldungsgesetz (Remuneration Law of Lower Saxony) ...... 91 , 259 , 336 37 BVerfGE 363 Bundesrat ...... 173 , 192 49 BVerfGE 89 Kalkar I ...... 393 Table of Cases xvii

49 BVerfGE 168 Vertrauensschutz bei Verlä ngerung der Aufenthaltsgenehmigung (Legitimate Expectation Regarding the Renewal of Residence Permits) ...... 413 52 BVerfGE 95 Schleswig-Holsteinische Ä mter ( Ä mter of Schleswig-Holstein) ...... 311 53 BVerfGE 185 Hessisches Gesetz ü ber die Neuordnung der gymnasialen Oberstufe ...... 336 55 BVerfGE 274 Berufsausbildungsabgabe (Vocational Training Act) ...... 192 61 BVerfGE 149 Amtshaftung (State Liability) ...... 250 72 BVerfGE 330 Finanzausgleich I (Financial Equalization I) ...... 241 , 243 – 44 , 250 73 BVerfGE 339 Solange II ...... 63 79 BVerfGE 127 Rastede ...... 293 81 BVerfGE 310 Kalkar II ...... 250 , 393 , 400 83 BVerfGE 37 Ausl ä nderwahlrecht I (Foreign Voters I) ...... 135 , 415 86 BVerfGE 148 Finanzausgleich II (Financial Equalization II) ...... 239 89 BVerfGE 155 Maastricht ...... 64 , 94 92 BVerfGE 203 EG-Fernsehrichtlinie (EC-Television-Directive) ...... 250 93 BverfGE 1 Kruzifi x im Klassenzimmer II (Classroom Crucifi x II) ...... 334 101 BVerfGE 158 Finanzausgleich III (Financial Equalization III) ...... 243 106 BVerfGE 310 Zuwanderungsgesetz (Immigration Act) ...... 174 116 BVerfGE 327 Berliner Haushalt (Budget of Berlin) ...... 239 122 BVerfGE 342 Bayerisches Versammlungsgesetz (Bavarian Assembly Act) ...... 335 123 BVerfGE 267 Lissabon (Lisbon) ...... 64 , 94 125 BVerfGE 141 Gewerbesteuer (Trade Tax) ...... 303 128 BVerfGE 1 Gentechnikgesetz (Genetic Engineering Act) ...... 391 134 BVerfGE 366 OMT-Beschluss (Outright Monetary Transactions) ...... 64 , 204 135 BVerfGE 317 ESM-Vertrag (European Stability Mechanism) ...... 64 , 204 BVerfG 21 March 2012, 1 BvR 2492/08 ...... 335 BVerfG 21 June 2016, 2 BvR 2728/13 ...... 204 BVerfG 16 December 2016, 2 BvR 349/16 ...... 91 Staatsgerichtshof fü r das Deutsche Reich (25 October 1932) ...... 81 StGH Hess 30 December 1981, PSt 880 ...... 336

India Supreme Court of India Ganga Ram Moolchandani v State of Rajasthan , 2001 AIR 2616 ...... 39 Golaknath v State of Punjab , 1967 AIR 1643 ...... 41 His Holiness Kesavananda Bharati Sripadagalvaru v State of Kerala, 1973 AIR 1461 ...... 41 , 185 , 276 , 291 Indira Nehru Gandhi v Raj Narain, 1975 AIR 2299 ...... 41 International Tourist Corporation v State of Haryana, 1981 AIR 774 ...... 213 ITC Limited v Agricultural Produce Market, 2002 AIR 852 ...... 276 Minerva Mills Ltd v Union of India , 1980 AIR 1789 ...... 185 , 276 Rai Sahib Ram Jawaya Kapur v State of Punjab, 1955 AIR 549 ...... 154 SR Bommai v Union of India , 1994 AIR 1918 ...... 41 , 155 , 200 State of Bihar v Bal Mukund Sah, 2000 AIR 1296 ...... 41 State of Karnataka v Union of India , 1978 AIR 68 ...... 279 State of Rajasthan v Union of India , 1977 AIR 1361 ...... 154 xviii Table of Cases

State of West Bengal v Union of India , 1963 AIR 1241...... 39 , 279 State of West Bengal v Kesoram Industries , 2005 AIR 1646 ...... 276 Western Coalfi elds Ltd vs Special Area Development , 1982 AIR 697 ...... 146

Italy Constitutional Court No 49/1958 ...... 251 No 170/1984 ...... 63 No 219/1984 ...... 251 No 358/1985 ...... 251 No 359/1985 ...... 396 , 401 No 151/1986 ...... 396 , 401 No 153/1986 ...... 251 No 273/1998 ...... 394 No 382/1999 ...... 394 No 42/2001 ...... 251 No 106/2002 ...... 121 No 274/2003 ...... 275 No 379/2004 ...... 120 No 365/2007 ...... 7 , 51 No 367/2007 ...... 394 No 378/2007 ...... 394 No 61/2009 ...... 394 , 400 No 74/2009 ...... 210 No 225/2009 ...... 395 , 401 No 282/2009 ...... 395 No 119/2010 ...... 395 No 186/2010 ...... 394 No 234/2010 ...... 394 No 44/2011 ...... 394

Malaysia Judicial Committee of the Privy Council (JCPC) and Federal Court of Malaysia Mamat bin Daud v Government of Malaysia [1986] 2 MLJ 192 ...... 271 Petroliam Nasional Bhd v State Government of Terengganu [2004] 1 MLJ 8 ...... 211 Stephen Kalong Ningkan v Tun Abang Haji Openg and Tawi Sli [1966] 2 MLJ 187 ...... 130 Stephen Kalong Ningkan v Government of Malaysia [1968] 2 MLJ 238 ...... 130

Mexico Supreme Court of Justice Constitutional Controversy 31/1997 ...... 279 Constitutional Controversy 29/2000 ...... 147 Constitutional Controversy 5/2004 ...... 301 Table of Cases xix

Nigeria Supreme Court of Nigeria Attorney General of the Federation v Attorney General of Abia State SC 28/2001 of 5 April 2002 ...... 221 Attorney General of Ondo State v Attorney General of the Federation SC 6/2002 of 7 June 2002 ...... 275

Russian Federation Constitutional Court Judgment of 18 January 1996, no 2-P, Vestnik Konstitutionnogo Suda RF 1996 no 1 ..... 130 Judgment of 1 February 1996, no 3-P, Vestnik Konstitutionnogo Suda RF 1996 no 1...... 160 Judgment of 7 June 2000, no 10-P, Vestnik Konstitutionnogo Suda RF 2000 no 5 ...... 128 Judgment of 21 December 2005, no 13-P, Vestnik Konstitutionnogo Suda RF 2006 no 3 ...... 130

South Africa Constitutional Court Cape Bar Council v Judicial Services Commission 2012 (4) BCLR 406 (WCC) ...... 195 CDA Boerdery (Edms) Bpk v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality 2007 SCA 1 (RSA) ...... 286 Certifi cation of the Amended Text of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1997 (2) SA 97 ...... 313 Certifi cation of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC) ...... 265 , 312 Certifi cation of the Constitution of the Western Cape 1998 (1) SA 655 ...... 265 Certifi cation of the Kwazulu-Natal Constitution 1996 (4) SA 1098 ...... 136 , 264 City of Cape Town v Robertson 2005 (2) SA 323 (CC)...... 286 Constitutionality of the Liquor Bill 2000 (1) SA 732 ...... 147 Executive Council of the Province of the Western Cape v Minister for Provincial Affairs and Constitutional Development, Executive Council of KwaZulu-Natal v President of the Republic of South Africa 2000 (1) SA 661 ...... 147 , 306 Judicial Service Commission v Cape Bar Council 2013 (1) SA 170 (SCA) ...... 195 Liebenberg NO v Bergrivier Municipality 2013 (5) SA 246 (CC) ...... 203 Matatiele Municipality v President of the Republic of South Africa 2006 (5) SA 47 (CC) ...... 188 MEC, Mpumalanga v Imata 2002 (2) SA 76 (SCA) ...... 304 Premier, Western Cape v President of the Republic of South Africa 1999 (3) SA 657 ...... 147 , 220 Premier: Limpopo Province v Speaker of the Limpopo Provincial Legislature 2012 (4) SA 58 (CC) ...... 254 Premier: Limpopo Province v Speaker: the Limpopo Provincial Legislature 2011 (6) SA 396 (CC) ...... 254 The National Education Policy Bill 1996 (3) SA 289 ...... 92 , 264 Uthukela District Municipality v President of the Republic of South Africa 2003 (1) SA 678 ...... 252 xx Table of Cases

Spain Constitutional Court STC 4/1981 ...... 299 , 302 , 339 , 341 STC 32/1981 ...... 92 , 147 , 289 , 314 STC 18/1982 ...... 251 , 442 STC 26/1982 ...... 441 STC 44/1982 ...... 440 – 41 STC 84/1982 ...... 288 STC 76/1983 ...... 53 STC 89/1984 ...... 339 STC 66/1985 ...... 339 STC 11/1986 ...... 251 STC 146/1986 ...... 367 , 377 STC 37/1987 ...... 214 STC 179/1987 ...... 224 STC 252/1988 ...... 442 STC 124/1989 ...... 377 STC 137/1989 ...... 440 STC 153/1989 ...... 440 STC 214/1989 ...... 288 STC 46/1990 ...... 442 STC 96/1990 ...... 302 STC 13/1992 ...... 224 , 232 , 234 , 258 STC 135/1992 ...... 224 STC 80/1993 ...... 440 STC 165/1994 ...... 440 – 41 STC 109/1998 ...... 289 STC 289/2000 ...... 214 , 224 STC 62/2001 ...... 236 STC 159/2001 ...... 294 STC 48/2004 ...... 299 STC 58/2004 ...... 289 STC 13/2007 ...... 209 STC 247/2007 ...... 224 , 339 , 341 STC 49/2008 ...... 198 STC 31/2010 ...... 139 , 209 , 244 , 339 , 341 STC 134/2011 ...... 236 STC 42/2014 ...... 110 STC 31/2015 ...... 110 STC 32/2015 ...... 110 STC 259/2015 ...... 110

Switzerland Federal Court BGE 101 Ia 67 ...... 328 BGE 104 Ia 215 ...... 328 BGE 116 Ia 359 ...... 122 Table of Cases xxi

BGE 116 Ib 265 ...... 389 BGE 118 Ia 124 ...... 265 BGE 121 I 267 ...... 329 BGE 121 I 334 ...... 389 , 399 BGE 121 I 367 ...... 328 BGE 125 I 458 ...... 227 BGE 129 I 217 ...... 406 – 07 BGE 130 I 140 ...... 406 BGE 132 I 291 ...... 307 BGE 139 I 16 ...... 78

UK House of Lords, High Court of Justice and Supreme Court of the United Kingdom Agricultural Sector (Wales) Bill — Reference by the Attorney General for and Wales [2014] UKSC 43 ...... 262 AXA General Insurance Ltd v () [2011] UKSC 46 ...... 278 Martin & Miller v Lord Advocate [2010] UKSC 10 ...... 278 Rothwell v Chemical & Insulating Co Ltd [2007] UKHL 2 ...... 278 R (Miller) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union [2016] EWHC 2768 (Admin) ...... 57 R (on the application of Miller and Dos Santos) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union [2017] UKSC 5 ...... 57 Thoburn v Sunderland City Council [2002] EWHC 195 (Admin), (Metric Martyrs case) ...... 56

USA Supreme Court of the United States ALA Schechter Poultry Corp v United States 295 US 495 (1935) ...... 349 Arizona State Legislature v Arizona Redistricting Commission 576 US ___ (2015) ...... 266 Atkin v Kansas 191 US 207 (1903) ...... 281 , 292 Baker v Carr 369 US 186 (1962) ...... 136 Baker v Nelson 291 Minn 310, 191 NW 2d 185 (1971) ...... 326 – 27 Baker v Vermont 744 A 2d 864 (Vt 1999) ...... 324 Baldwin v GAF Seelig Inc 294 US 511 (1935) ...... 143 Barron v Baltimore 32 US (7 Pet) 243 (1833) ...... 322 Bowers v Hardwick 478 US 186 (1986) ...... 325 , 327 Brown v Board of Education 347 US 483 (1954) ...... 131 Brushaber v Union Pacifi c Railroad Co 240 US 1 (1916) ...... 216 Carter v Carter Coal Co 298 US 238 (1936) ...... 143 , 349 Chicago, Burlington & Quincy Railroad Co v Chicago (City of) 166 US 226 (1897) ...... 322 Chisholm v Georgia 2 US (2 Dall) 419 (1793) ...... 90 , 270 Clark v Des Moines (City of) 19 Iowa 199 (1865) ...... 291 Clinton (City of) v Cedar Rapids & Missouri River Railroad Co 24 Iowa 455 (1868) ...... 291 Collector v Day 78 US (11 Wall) 113 (1870) ...... 216 xxii Table of Cases

Comptroller of the Treasury of Maryland v Wynne 575 US ___ (2015) ...... 227 Cooley v Board of Wardens 53 US (12 How) 299 (1852) ...... 142 – 43 Cooper v Aaron 358 US 1 (1958) ...... 131 Crosby v National Foreign Trade Council 530 US 363 (2000) ...... 426 DaimlerChrysler Corp v Cuno 547 US 332 (2006) ...... 426 Di Santo v Pennsylvania 273 US 34 (1927) ...... 143 Erie Railroad Co v Tompkins 304 US 64 (1938) ...... 161 – 62 Ex Parte Young 209 US 123 (1908) ...... 91 Field v Clark 143 US 649 (1892) ...... 156 Garcia v San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority 469 US 528 (1985) ...... 166 , 273 Gibbons v Odgen 22 US (9 Wheat) 1 (1824) ...... 142 Gitlow v New York 268 US 652 (1925) ...... 322 Gonzales v Raich 545 US 1 (2005) ...... 143 , 384 Goodridge v Department of Public Health 798 NE 2d 941 (Mass 2003) ...... 324 Graves v New York ex rel O’ Keefe 306 US 466 (1939) ...... 216 Gregg v Georgia 428 US 153 (1976) ...... 323 Hammer v Dagenhart 247 US 251 (1918) ...... 143 Helvering v Davis 301 US 619 (1937) ...... 226 , 230 , 234 , 349 , 376 Home Building & Loan Association v Blaisdell 290 US 398 (1934) ...... 349 Jacobellis v Ohio 378 US 184 (1964) ...... 3 Lawrence v Texas 539 US 558 (2003) ...... 325 , 327 Lichter v United States 334 US 742 (1948) ...... 156 Lloyd Corp v Tanner 407 US 551 (1972) ...... 324 Loving v Virginia 388 US 1 (1967) ...... 326 Luther v Borden 48 US (7 How) 1 (1849) ...... 136 Marbury v Madison 5 US (1 Cranch) 137 (1803) ...... 75 , 272 , 274 – 75 Massachusetts v Environmental Protection Agency 549 US 497 (2007) ...... 386 , 400 Massachusetts v Mellon 262 US 447 (1923) ...... 234 , 350 McCulloch v Maryland 17 US (4 Wheat) 316 (1819) ...... 150 , 272 McDonald v Chicago (City of) 561 US 742 (2010) ...... 322 Medell í n v Texas 552 US 491 (2008) ...... 427 Memorial Hospital v Maricopa County 415 US 250 (1974) ...... 350 – 51 , 379 Michigan v Long 463 US 1032 (1983) ...... 325 Missouri v Holland 252 US 416 (1920) ...... 272 , 428 National Federation of Independent Business v Sebelius 567 US ___ (2012) ...... 151 , 234 , 355 National Labor Relations Board v Canning 573 US ___ (2014) ...... 198 National League of Cities v Usery 426 US 833 (1976) ...... 273 Nebbia v New York 291 US 502 (1934) ...... 349 New State Ice Co v Liebmann 285 US 262 (1932) ...... 318 New York v United States 505 US 144 (1992) ...... 273 Norman v Baltimore & Ohio Railroad Co 294 US 240 (1935) ...... 349 Obergefell v Hodges 576 US ___ (2015) ...... 326 Oregon Waste Systems Inc v Department of Environmental Quality of Oregon 511 US 93 (1994) ...... 384 Pacifi c States Telephone & Telegraph Co v Oregon 23 US 118 (1912) ...... 136 Pennhurst State School and Hospital v Halderman 451 US 1 (1981) ...... 234 Pennsylvania v Nelson 350 US 497 (1956) ...... 132 People v Anderson 493 P 2d 880, 6 Cal 3d 628 (Cal 1972) ...... 324 Pollock v Farmers’ Loan & Trust Co 158 US 601 (1895) ...... 216 , 270 Table of Cases xxiii

Printz v United States 521 US 898 (1997) ...... 151 Pruneyard Shopping Center v Robins 447 US 74 (1980) ...... 324 Roe v Wade 410 US 113 (1973) ...... 323 Schuette v Coalition to Defend Affi rmative Action 572 US ___ (2014) ...... 266 Shapiro v Thompson 394 US 618 (1969) ...... 350 , 379 South Dakota v Dole 483 US 203 (1987) ...... 234 Southern Pacifi c Co v Arizona 325 US 761 (1945) ...... 143 Steward Machine Co v Davis 301 US 548 (1937) ...... 349 , 376 Swift v Tyson 41 US (16 Pet) 1 (1842) ...... 161 Texas v New Mexico 482 US 124 (1987) ...... 279 Texas v White 74 US (7 Wall) 700 (1869)...... 40 , 90 , 105 – 06 United States v Butler 297 US 1 (1936) ...... 230 , 349 United States v Leon 468 US 897 (1984) ...... 323 United States v Lopez 514 US 549 (1995) ...... 143 , 273 , 384 , 398 United States v Morrison 529 US 598 (2000) ...... 384 United States v Windsor 570 US ___ (2013 ) ...... 326 West Coast Hotel Co v Parrish 300 US 379 (1937) ...... 349 Wilson v Black-Bird Creek Marsh Co 27 US (2 Pet) 245 (1829)...... 142

2 Manifestations

Federalism is a natural constitution for a body of states which desire union and do not desire unity … 1 … but, it could be added, the form such a ‘ natural ’ constitution takes is deeply infl uenced by the process that led to its formation. As described in the previous chapter, federalism is a manifold concept which may have several institutional manifestations and often means different things to differ- ent people in different contexts. Nearly all states, with very few exceptions (usually the so-called micro-states) encompass some form of vertical division of powers. 2 At the same time, countless attempts have been made in literature to defi ne the federal state as something opposed to other forms of vertical division of pow- ers and functions. Daniel Elazar and Ronald Watts have tried to capture all these diverse manifestations by using, respectively, the broad umbrella terms ‘ varieties of federal arrangements’ and ‘ federal political systems’ . Both scholars list within these overarching categories different forms of organisation such as unions, federations, confederations, federacies, associated states, condominiums, leagues and joint functional authorities; plus — needless to say— hybrids, ie, combinations of two or more categories.3 The fact that the manifestations of federalism are extremely diverse and diffi cult to distinguish was known long before the times of Elazar and Watts. Indeed, some scholars observed as early as 1940 that ‘ it is not always possible to draw clear and incontestable distinctions … alliance shades into league, league into confederation, confederation into federal state, federal state into unitary state. ’ 4 This chapter looks at how the toolkit of federalism can be used for very different consti- tutional purposes and shows that federal and regional states differ essentially in their historical origins, the former being the fi rst manifestation of the federal principle, the latter representing a more recent way in which this principle is used to accommodate territorial pluralism. The historical turning point is represented by the paradigm: when the creation of nation states was the overall trend in order to create bigger, militarily and economically more competitive countries, smaller sovereign

1 AV Dicey , Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution , 6th edn ( London , Macmillan & Co , 1902 ) lxxv. 2 See M Frenkel , Federal Theory ( Canberra , Australian National University, 1986 ) 389 . 3 Beyond these manifestations mentioned by both authors, Elazar also lists consociations and Watts constitutionally decentralised unions. See DJ Elazar , Federal Systems of the World : A Handbook of Federal, Confederal and Autonomy Arrangements ( Harlow , Essex , Longman , 1991 ) XVI; R Watts , Comparing Federal Systems , 3rd edn ( Montr é al , McGill – Queen ’ s University Press, 2008 ) 8f . 4 H Greaves , Federal Union in Practice ( London , G Allen & Unwin , 1940 ) 10 . Confederation 35 entities were pushed by historical and political circumstances to pool together in a bigger polity; conversely, when the age of nation states came to an end, the driv- ing forces of federalism shifted from military and economic – industrial supremacy towards a more effective administration and/or accommodation of ethno-cultural or other kinds of differences, thus promoting decentralisation of existing countries. Further, the chapter describes the most recurrent institutional forms of the vertical division of power. It explores the legally and historically most relevant manifesta- tions of what is to be considered a common phenomenon (confederations, federal states, regional states), and it deals with other, less recurrent forms (associations of states, federacies, devolution), as well as with some important conceptual challenges (the legal meaning of autonomy, the nature of the European Union). Finally, it con- cludes by warning against simplistic or formalistic defi nitions of federalism and its manifestations.

2.1 CONFEDERATION

2.1.1 Defi nition

In times when federations were established by the coming-together of sovereign states, the fi rst aggregative form was the confederation of states.5 A confederation is a union of independent states that transfer only limited parts of their sovereignty (eg, some defence powers) to a government with an enumerated and rather limited scope of responsibilities. The limitation of scope, however, cannot go as far as to comprise only one goal; thus, it would not be appropriate, for example, to call a defence organisation, such as NATO, a confederation. Three legal elements are needed for a confederation to exist. First, a confederation is a union of independent states ruled by international law rather than by constitu- tional law. Second, and consequently, fundamental decisions require unanimity, and each participating state thus has a veto power on every single decision of the con- federation. Third, the confederation is fi nancially dependent on funds transferred by the participating states, meaning that it lacks its own revenues. These fundamental elements of a confederation are generally uncontested, and for this reason there is no ambiguity in literature and in political practice as to the irrelevance of the nomen iuris : when these conditions are not met, there is no confederation regardless of the name of the polity. Conversely, even if Switzerland, for historical reasons, still calls itself a ‘ confederation’ in Article 1 of its 1999 Constitution, 6 its status as a prototype of the federal state7 is uncontested.

5 See M Forsyth , Unions of States : The Theory and Practice of Confederation ( Leicester , Leicester University Press, 1981 ) . See GJ Ebers , Die Lehre vom Staatenbunde ( Breslau , M & H Marcus , 1910 ) . 6 For example, as mentioned in box 0.B, similarly, Australia is still called a Commonwealth (Art 1 of the Constitution of 1901), but it is a federal state, as was the Soviet Union, at least nominally, in spite of being called a union. 7 See ch 3.3.2 . 36 Manifestations

One of the prototypes of modern confederations was the United States of America between independence in 1776 and the entry into force of its federal Constitution in 1789. 8 More precisely, after the independence of the 13 former colonies, the Articles of Confederation and Perpetual Union were drafted in 1777 and entered into force on 1 March 1781. For the eight years they were in force, the Articles of Confedera- tion created a confederation of American states called the United States of America. The system of government was based on a permanent Congress of the Confedera- tion, more formally called ‘ the United States in Congress assembled’ , in which each state had one vote. The Congress was in charge of a limited number of functions, including common defence, setting weights and measures (including currency) and serving as an arbitration court for disputes between states. When the Congress was not in session, a Committee of the States, based on the same principle of equal rep- resentation of each state with a rotating presidency, performed the functions of the Government.

2.A The Articles of Confederation In the Articles of Confederation, the confederal nature clearly comes to the fore: Article 2 stated that ‘ [e]ach state retains its sovereignty, freedom, and independence, and every power, jurisdiction, and right, which is not by this confederation expressly delegated to the United States, in Congress assembled’ . Moreover, any change in the Articles of Confedera- tion required unanimity (Article 13). Article 3 further clarifi ed the nature of the Union, affi rming that the states formed a ‘ fi rm league of friendship with each other, for their com- mon defense, the security of their , and their mutual and general welfare, binding themselves to assist each other, against all force offered to, or attacks made upon them, or any of them, on account of religion, sovereignty, trade, or any other pretense whatever’ . The Union was called upon to guarantee to the citizens of each state ‘ all privileges and immunities of free citizens in the several States; and the people of each State shall have free ingress and regress to and from any other State, and shall enjoy therein all the privileges of trade and commerce’ (Article 4). The functions attributed to the Congress were limited to war powers, other important issues of foreign policy (Articles 6 and 9) and a few in the domestic arena (Article 4). Article 8 established that the common treasury had to be supplied by the states ‘ in proportion to the value of all land within each State ’ , by taxes to be ‘ laid and levied by the authority and direction of the legislatures of the several States’ .

2.1.2 Are Confederations Transitional?

The second most relevant historical example of a confederation, the Swiss confed- eration, was also eventually replaced by a federal constitution. 9 While its history was much longer as compared to the American case — the origins of the confederation date back to the ‘ eternal confederal compact’ of 1291 among the original cantons as a military and trade alliance— it was nevertheless replaced by a federal constitution

8 See on this transition, chs 3.2.2 and 3.3.1 . 9 See ch 3.2.1 and 3.3.2 . Confederation 37 with a stronger national government in 1848 after the Civil War. The evolution of the two most relevant historical confederations towards a federal state 10 raises the question as to whether confederations are doomed to fail and will necessarily end up centralising in a federal setting that represents, using the terminology of the drafters of the US Constitution, ‘ a more perfect union’ . Such an approach, however, does not entirely explain confederations and their importance for the federal theory. Like most of the traditional readings of federal- ism, this approach is biased by the excessive attention paid to certain important historical experiences that tend to be generalised. 11 Following more careful obser- vation, however, it must be noted that, fi rst, no form of government is eternal (in spite of the terminology normally used by constitution drafters), and second, the ‘ inevitable evolution’ from a confederation into a federation tends to be rather common when federal states come together through ever deeper integration of pre- viously sovereign entities, such as in the case of the United States or Switzerland. Furthermore, confederation is not a transitional step from an imperfect to a more perfect union when it is established as the consequence of the of a pre- viously more unitary state. One could take the examples of the Commonwealth of Nations (previously known as the British Commonwealth) or of the Common- wealth of Independent States, which are loose and rather non-political associa- tions of sovereign states originating from, respectively, the and the Soviet Union— although not all former members of these two entities participate in these organisations, and some members of the Commonwealth of Nations were never British colonies.12 Another recent example is the evolution of Serbia and Montenegro, fi rst established in 1992 as a federation called the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia following the break-up of Yugoslavia, then reconstituted in 2003 as a confederation. The State Union was a very loose confederation, even with separate currencies and economic policies (Montenegro adopted the euro, while Serbia kept the dinar as its currency). Strongly promoted by the EU in an attempt to stave off further confl ict in the Balkans, this transitional stage was decided while waiting for a referendum on Montenegro’ s independence that would determine whether to fi nally establish two separate countries.13 The referendum was held in 2006, with the majority of Montenegrin voters opting for independence, and the State Union offi cially came to an end with the formal declaration of independence of both Serbia and Montenegro that same year. A counter-example is the European Union, which includes elements of a feder- ation and others of a confederation. 14 While the EU has certainly developed the

10 The trajectory of the Republic of the Seven United Netherlands was rather different for historical reasons, see ch 3.2.1 . 11 See A Gamper , ‘ A “ Global Theory of Federalism” : The Nature and Challenges of a Federal State ’ ( 2005 ) 6 German Law Journal 1297, 1297ff . 12 See KC Wheare , The Constitutional Structure of the Commonwealth ( Oxford , Clarendon Press, 1960 ) . 13 See M Suksi , ‘ On the Voluntary Re-defi nition of the Status of a Sub-state Entity: The Histori- cal Example of Finland and the Modern Example of Serbia and Montenegro ’ ( 2004 ) 4 Faroese Law Review 33 . 14 On the nature of the EU, see section 2.4 below. 38 Manifestations former in the course of its history, it has also clearly refused to become a fully-fl edged federal state, as epitomised by the rejection of the Constitutional Treaty in 2005. In sum, it would be misleading to see confederations as just a transitional step towards the establishment of federal states. Throughout history, this has been the case for some confederal experiences but clearly not for all of them. Like federal states, confederations also do not all look the same, nor did they originate in the same way, nor is their destiny predetermined. However, they generally carry little political weight vis-a-vis the individual countries and the international community and are often weak in terms of decision-making and effectiveness.15

2.2 FEDERAL STATE

2.2.1 The Compact as the Traditional Defi nition: The ‘ Federal Big Bang’

As mentioned earlier in this book, to defi ne federalism in abstract terms is not only impossible but also futile. Every scholar tends to advocate a specifi c understanding of what constitutes a federal state, and nearly every constitutional or supreme court in countries that defi ne themselves as federal has provided some defi nition of the essential elements of a federal state. Quite recently, the Canadian Supreme Court, for instance, provided a very much democracy-focused defi nition. The judges regarded as the essence of the federal state its function ‘ to enable citizens to participate con- currently in different collectivities and to pursue goals at both a provincial and a federal level ’ .16 What many of the apex court defi nitions have in common is that they look at the domestic experience and, not unlike academic classifi cations, natu- rally tend to generalise the essential elements of one particular experience in order to subsume a general rule. This approach is refl ected, for instance, in the defi nitions provided by the Indian Supreme Court and the Constitutional Court of Austria.

2.B India 1963– 2001 and Austria 1952– 88: Can Court Defi nitions of the Federal State be Generalised? Since the adoption of its national Constitution in 1949, India has always been termed a federation and/or a union. For clarifi cation, it is useful, in this regard, to go back to the explanations of terminology and concepts by BR Ambedkar, the Chairman of the Draft- ing Commission. In his words, ‘ India was to be a federation’ , but not one that the states had joined through an original act of union and could, therefore, leave in a reciprocal act of disunion. The term union was a deliberate choice to refl ect a unitary penchant17 and a specifi c ratio essendi : ‘ Though the country and the people may be divided into different States for convenience of administration the country is one integral whole, its people a

15 See ch 3.2.1 . 16 Reference Re Secession of Qué bec [ 1998 ] 2 SCR 217 , para 66. See box 4.E. 17 This unitary penchant is refl ected, for example, in the Indian Constitution’ s emergency clauses to the benefi t of the national government, see ch 5.2.3 . Federal State 39

single people living under a single imperium derived from a single source.’ 18 Even though the Supreme Court, in its early jurisprudence, sometimes affi rmed, in contrast to Ambed- kar ’ s defi nition, that India ’ s Constitution ‘ is not truly federal in character ’ , 19 it has in its more recent case law tended to recognise the country’ s federal nature more unequivocally. In 2001, it stated that the ‘ Indian Constitution is basically federal in form and is marked by the traditional characteristics of a federal system, namely, supremacy of the Constitution, division of power between the Union and States and existence of an independent judiciary. From Kashmir to Kanyakumari, the country is one and there is no intelligible differentia which distinguishes advocates practising within the State of Rajasthan and those practicing outside Rajasthan but within the territory of India.’ 20 By contrast, the Constitutional Court of Austria has provided a partially divergent defi - nition. According to this court, elements of the federal state are the division of competences and the participation of the L ä nder in the federal legislative process,21 the constitutional autonomy of the L ä nder22 and the responsibility of the L ä nder for the implementation of national law, the so-called indirect federal administration.23 It is evident that the defi ni- tions of the two courts emphasise beyond some commonalities certain country-specifi c elements, ie, in the Indian case, an independent judiciary and identical requirements for the exercise of a legal profession and, in the Austrian case, the indirect federal administration. But both these characteristics are far from typical of all federal states so that these court defi nitions may not serve as bases for a generally applicable defi nition.

However defi ned, the federal state presents some common elements, which can be described as necessary but not suffi cient. In other words, they must exist in each federally organised state, but are not enough, alone, to identify a federal state as opposed to other, similar state organisations. 24 The ‘ skeleton ’ of a federal state is represented by: a) the division of state functions between at least two different orders of government both enjoying political autonomy; b) the supremacy of the federal/ national constitution; and c) a system of cooperation among the levels, including the judicial adjudication of disputes between and among the entities over the respective constitutional powers. Put differently, federally organised states fi nd (different) ways to divide public powers among different spheres of government, combine (in differ- ent ways) self-rule and shared rule and (in different ways) unite without merging and divide without separating. As with federalism, the literature also often refers to federation in relation to the origins of the term foedus (compact) in order to consider that federal states are only those established by the coming-together of previously independent entities. Such an approach is too narrow and is inherently wrong, because it looks at only one of the origins of federalism. First, some states, whose federal nature is uncontested,

18 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates , vol VII, 4 November 1948, 43. 19 State of West Bengal v Union of India , 1963 AIR 1241 . 20 Ganga Ram Moolchandani v State of Rajasthan , 2001 AIR 2616 . 21 VfSlg 2455/1952. 22 VfSlg 11669/1988. 23 VfSlg 11403/1987. On the indirect federal administration, see ch 5.3 . 24 On the futility of a defi nition, see section 2.2.2 below. 40 Manifestations have been formed by the transfer of powers from a previously unitary entity, such as in the case of Belgium and to some extent Austria, India, Nigeria and others. Second, and more importantly, the difference between ‘ coming-together ’ , ‘ holding- together’ and ‘ putting- or forced-together’ federations25 is only historical, not legal, in nature. In coming-together federations, the member units were originally both historically and legally sovereign, while the federal government is historically derived. However, when the ‘ federal big bang’ takes place, ie the federal constitution enters into force, the federal government becomes legally sovereign and the member units legally derived.26 The federal big bang turns the original sovereignty of member units into autonomy, due to the primacy of the federal constitution. This is confi rmed by the so-called homogeneity clauses included, not by chance, in all federal constitutions of coming-together federal states, such as Article 4, Clause 4 of the US Constitution (the Republican Clause), Articles 5 and 6 of the Swiss Constitution, Article 28 of the German Basic Law, etc. 27 In some cases, the impact of the federal big bang is even more profound as it entrenches the federal system so fi rmly that it is even protected against the power of constitutional amendment. While several federal countries have declared the federa- tion, in their constitutional texts 28 or jurisprudence,29 as indissoluble, Germany’ s so-called ‘ eternity clause’ is a particularly notable example. Article 79(3) of the Basic Law stipulates that amendments ‘ affecting the division of the federation into L ä nder ’ on principle in the legislative process ’ shall be inadmissible. Even if this provision does not guarantee the individual existence of each Land ,30 it entrenches both the country ’ s territorial division as such into (at least two) L ä nder and their participa- tion. Whereas the fi rm entrenchment of the federal system has been an integral part of Germany ’ s constitutional order from its outset in 1949, a similar rule was belat- edly introduced in India by the case law of the Supreme Court.

25 This threefold distinction goes back to A Stepan , ‘ Federalism and Democracy: Beyond the US Model ’ ( 1999 ) 10 Journal of Democracy 19 . While Alfred Stepan’ s term ‘ putting-together’ was supposed to capture the unique character of federal states that were formed through coercion, Nancy Bermeo’ s similar term ‘ forced-together’ aims to place particular emphasis on the infl uence of external actors and the element of system frailty. See N Bermeo , ‘ The Import of Institutions ’ ( 2002 ) 13 Journal of Democracy 96, 108 . 26 The expression ‘ federal big bang ’ to describe the entry into force of a supra-ordinated federal constitution is sometimes used in the discourse on European integration. See N Walker , ‘ The Shifting Foundations of the European Union Constitution ’ (2012 ) University of , School of Law, Europa Working Papers 2012/1 . For a more contextual use in the theory of federalism, see R Toniatti , ‘ Federalismo e potere costituente ’ in Regionalismo e federalismo in Europa ( Trento , Giunta della Provincia Autonoma di Trento, 1997 ) 171 . 27 See ch 5.1.2 . 28 For instance, Art 1 of the Brazilian Constitution states the federal republic is ‘ formed by the indissoluble union of the states and municipalities and of the federal district’ . The Preamble to the Australian Constitution underscores explicitly that the people of the colonies ‘ have agreed to unite in one indissoluble Federal Commonwealth’ . 29 Texas v White 74 US (7 Wall) 700, 725 ( 1869 ) . On this seminal ruling, see box 4.D. 30 See box 6.F. Federal State 41

2.C India 1973: The Federal Character as Part of the Constitution’ s Basic Structure? In 1970, the religious guru Sri Kesavananda Bharati challenged attempts of the state of Kerala to impose certain restrictions, under land reform acts of that state, on the man- agement of his community’ s property. While in its ruling the Supreme Court overruled previous decisions implying that the right to property could not be restricted, the case is today more known for its development of the ‘ basic structure doctrine’ . In their early juris- prudence after 1949, the judges had asserted that any provision of the Indian Constitution would be amendable, including fundamental rights (Part III) and the procedure of consti- tutional amendment itself (Article 368). Already in 1967, the Supreme Court had initiated a change of course in the Golaknath case. 31 In this decision it ruled that an act of amend- ment under Article 368 was also a ‘ law ’ within the meaning of Article 13(2) of the Consti- tution and thus, according to this provision, subject to constitutional fundamental rights. In the Kesavananda Bharati judgment of 1973, the Court overruled the Golaknath deci- sion, as it affi rmed that a constitutional amendment was not a ‘ law ’ for the purposes of the above-mentioned Article 13(2), but at the same time established certain limits.32 Confi rming the constitutionality of the Twenty-Fourth, Twenty-Fifth and Twenty-Ninth Amendment, the Court famously held that an amendment could not damage, abrogate or alter what it called the ‘ basic structure’ of the Constitution. The fact that the parliament only had the power to amend would indicate implied limits. Whereas changes would be admissible in order to adapt the Constitution to changing conditions, they would have to leave intact its very foundations and basic institutional pattern. Regarding the concrete elements of the Constitution’ s basic structure, there has been a certain ambiguity and fl ex- ibility from the beginning, as even several of the judges adopting the majority opinion laid them out separately. However, most of them shared the view that the federal character of the Constitution constitutes such an element which was reiterated in the Bommai ruling of 1993.33 Although the Court introduced the basic structure doctrine in a 7 – 6 decision and has tended in subsequent judgments to determine elements on a case-by-case basis, the doctrine has gained broad acceptance. To a considerable extent, this is due to its role dur- ing the state of emergency declared by Indira Gandhi in 1975 based on Article 352(1) of the Constitution.34 The basic structure doctrine was used by the Supreme Court to strike down the Thirty-Ninth Amendment,35 which was supposed to prevent Indira Gandhi’ s prosecution, and is thus widely credited with restoring Indian democracy.36

It appears to be clear that the sovereignty debate, although key, cannot provide defi nite answers to the phenomenon of federal states. While in legal terms it seems incontestable that the prevalence of the federal constitution turns original subna- tional sovereignty into legal autonomy, in broader terms it seems that sovereignty

31 Golaknath v State of Punjab , 1967 AIR 1643 . 32 His Holiness Kesavananda Bharati Sripadagalvaru v State of Kerala , 1973 AIR 1461 . 33 SR Bommai v Union of India , 1994 AIR 1918 . 34 On this provision, see ch 5.2.3 . 35 Indira Nehru Gandhi v Raj Narain , 1975 AIR 2299 . 36 Another seminal ruling that further developed this doctrine is State of Bihar v Bal Mukund Sah , 2000 AIR 1296 . 42 Manifestations simply does not explain the whole issue and remains the subject of controversial debates.37 As Scottish scholar Neil MacCormick effectively put it, sovereignty is rather like ‘ virginity: something that can be lost by one without another ’ s gaining it ’ . 38 In his view, sovereignty has been lost within the European Union by its Member States without the European level gaining it.39 While the supremacy of the national constitution legally strips sovereignty from the member units, the historical formation of federal states has, however, normative consequences for the institutional setting of each federal system. In coming-together federal countries, the reduction of sovereignty of member units into autonomy is compensated by the units ’ participation in the exercise of sovereign powers at the national level: this occurs especially by means of guaranteed representation in pow- erful second chambers, such as the US Senate, the Swiss Council of States (St ä nderat ) or the German Federal Council ( Bundesrat ) and by retaining some control over the constitutional amendment power, up to a veto right of each individual member unit as to some essential elements of the federal compact. 40 One may think of Article 5 of the US Constitution, which prescribes, inter alia, that ‘ no State, without its consent, shall be deprived of its equal in the Senate ’ . 41 In other words, before agree- ing to the federal big bang, future member units must accept the predominance of the federal government in exchange for maintaining some infl uence on national poli- cies (both collectively through the second chamber or other mechanisms of partici- pation and, more rarely, individually). 42 Conversely, in holding-together federations, such institutional representation of member units is either non-existent or extremely weak: there is usually no strong involvement of member units in the procedure for amending the constitution, no veto right as to essential elements of it and usually the national government retains the power to legislate instead of the member units when legal or economic unity is at stake.43

2.2.2 Form Follows Function: The Role of History in Shaping Federal Manifestations

Federal states are created in different ways, and the origins usually infl uence the institutions of each federation and ultimately the understanding of federalism that is behind any attempt to defi ne a federal state. From a historical perspective, it must be noted that the era of coming-together federations had momentum that lasted up to, roughly, World War I: before, basically all federations were created by

37 See ch 4.1 . 38 N MacCormick , Questioning Sovereignty : Law, State and Nation in the European Commonwealth ( Oxford , Oxford University Press, 1999 ) 126 . 39 For details regarding sovereignty in the EU context, see ch 4.1.3 . 40 See H Wechsler , ‘ The Political Safeguards of Federalism: The Role of States in the Composition and Selection of the National Government ’ ( 1954 ) 54 Columbia Law Review 543 . 41 For details, see ch 6.3.1 . 42 See ch 6 . 43 Examples of this are Art 120 of the Italian Constitution or Art 150(3) of the Spanish Constitution. For further details, see ch 5.2.3 . Federal State 43 uniting previously sovereign entities, sometimes experimenting with a looser union (a confederation) during the process. One may think of the classical federations such as the USA, Switzerland and Germany.44 Also other coming-together federa- tions were established before World War I, although with some peculiarity from the legal point of view: formally, Canada and Australia obtained their (federal) constitutions, respectively, in 1867 and 1901 as acts of the British Parliament and acquired de iure sovereignty only with the Statute of Westminster of 1931. Yet, they can be considered coming-together federations in the material sense, since in both countries federations were established, in the Canadian case at least for the most part, on top of existing quasi-sovereign units. 45 The process of the establish- ment of coming-together federations is very much linked to nation state formation: especially during the nineteenth century, nation states represented the winning model, and countries that had not yet achieved this type of statehood were push- ing for it. In some cases, for historical, political, ethnic/religious or other reasons, the formation of nation states was carried out by the coming-together of sovereign entities. At the same time, however, in some circumstances the federal state was created after the establishment of the nation state, like in the case of nearly all Latin American federations. After World War I, especially due to the reconfi guration of the geopolitical land- scape in Europe after the dissolution of the Habsburg Empire, as well as of the Russian and Ottoman Empires, the process towards the formation of nation states essentially came to an end. Some historically hybrid federations were created by reuniting, under a federal umbrella, entities that were previously parts (with differ- ent statuses) of bigger empires, as in the case of Austria, Czechoslovakia or even, mutatis mutandis , the Soviet Union. For all these federal experiences, it is debatable whether they represent coming-together or holding-together types of federations, and it is probably correct to consider them to be both. Certainly, the vast majority of all federal systems, however defi ned, established after the 1920s are holding-together federal systems that resulted from a transfer of power from a unitary state. 46 One may think of Belgium, Spain (both the constitutions of 1931 and 1978), Italy, the United Kingdom, and most recently Nepal, but, for the most part, also the cases of India47 and Bosnia and Herzegovina. In other words, historical origins are indeed

44 See ch 3.3 . 45 Having regard to the historical facts, the situation is of course more complex, as many states/prov- inces were formed by separation from existing entities. One may think, for example, of the establishment of the states of Victoria and Queensland in Australia in 1851 and 1859, respectively, whose territories were previously part of New South Wales. See ACV Melbourne , Early Constitutional Development in Australia: New South Wales 1788– 1886, Queensland 1859– 1922 , RB Joyce (ed), 2nd edn ( St Lucia , University of Queensland, 1963 ) esp 443f. What was before 1867 the United Province of Canada came to be split up at the founding of the federal state into the two separate provinces Ontario and Quebec. The provinces of Manitoba, Alberta and Saskatchewan and the territories of Yukon and Nunavut were over the years carved out from the vast Northwest Territories. 46 In the few cases when federations were established according to the old system, they usually collapsed. One may think of the confederation (which never became a federation) of Senegambia (1982– 89), of the federation of the West Indies (1958– 62), of French West Africa (which started prior to World War I and formally ended in 1958) or of the Federation of Rhodesia and Nyasaland (1953– 64), etc. 47 India was established as a federal state by the Constitution of 1950 and cannot be considered a coming-together federal system, since the states and territories of the Indian Union were not fully-fl edged 44 Manifestations very relevant in shaping the constitutional features of federal states. History, how- ever, should not be seen as the only defi ning element of a federal or regional state. Rather, it is important to identify historical cycles that have determined the ways of forming federations. Such a clear shift in the historical formation of federal states has to do with the changing meaning of the foedus . In both the past and the present, the foedus has indicated nothing other than the will to be together. Such a will evolves over time and takes on different constitutional forms. Sometimes it is even imposed, by force (such as in the American Civil War) or by international pressure (such as in Bosnia and Herzegovina, where it has been largely replaced by the international community),48 and its evolutions are part of the physiology of federalism. One may wonder, for instance, whether such a compact is still present in today ’ s Belgium, even though, constitutionally, it clearly exists. For all these reasons, the historical perspective seems much more effective than the formalistic sovereignty approach in explaining the legal nature and the political dynamics of federalism in its various manifestations. History and the political– societal functions to be achieved at the time of the estab- lishment of the federal compact (both in terms of coming-together and holding- together) also defi ne the intrinsic elements and the institutional character of the various federal states. Put differently, the form each federation takes and even its ideological underpinnings are determined by the historical and political motives behind each case. This is why several dichotomies are highlighted in the literature depending on such intrinsic and largely pre-institutional factors. The fi rst and perhaps most common distinction is the one between mature and emergent federal systems.49 A distinction based essentially on time (mature federal countries are older, emergent ones are younger), but also on institutional features (only mature ones exhibit certain characteristics of many federations such as typi- cally residual powers of subnational entities, a second chamber, etc) and on the

sovereign states but were more or less autonomous under British, French or Portuguese colonial rule, although most subnational entities were modelled according to the existing provinces established by the British Government of India Act of 1935. Moreover, at the time of independence, a huge number of more than 500 formally independent small territories remained out of the British Raj, and most of them subsequently voluntarily joined the Union (in the cases of Hyderabad and Jammu and Kashmir, they were annexed by force), and a few joined Pakistan. In sum, while not established by the coming-together of previously existing sovereign entities, the Indian Union is also partly the outcome of a union of provinces, states and territories. India should thus also be considered a hybrid federal system as to its origins. See G Austin , The Indian Constitution : Cornerstone of a Nation ( Oxford , Clarendon Press, 1966 ) 186ff . Further, see B Ray , Evolution of Federalism in India ( Calcutta , Progressive Publishers, 1967 ) ; and N Mukarji and B Arora (eds), Federalism in India : Origins and Development ( New Delhi , Vikas Pub , 1992 ) . 48 The fact that the High Representative for Bosnia and Herzegovina, appointed by the international community, was granted in 1997 the power to impose constitutional amendments (see box 4.C on the ‘ Constituent Peoples Case’ ) has arguably changed the role of this offi cial ‘ from that of a supervisor of the peace implementation process to its main actor’ , J Woelk , ‘ Bosnia-Herzegovina: Trying to Build a Fed- eral State on Paradoxes ’ in M Burgess and GA Tarr (eds), Constitutional Dynamics in Federal Systems : Sub-national Perspectives ( Montreal , McGill – Queen ’ s University Press, 2012 ) 119 . 49 See RL Watts , ‘ Typologies of Federalism ’ in J Loughlin et al (eds), The Routledge Handbook of Regionalism and Federalism ( Abingdon , Routledge , 2013 ) 25 ; Watts, Comparing Federal Systems (2008) 24f, 29f. Federal State 45

‘ adaptability ’ over time of mature federal systems when facing changing conditions. For Watts, the United States (1789), Switzerland (1848), Canada (1867), Australia (1901), Austria (1945), Germany (1949) and India (1950) match the criteria and therefore are mature federations. 50 By contrast, emergent federal countries were created in the second half of the twentieth century, and are still looking for their equilibrium.51 Further, they do not present all the characteristics of mature federal systems; Watts calls these ‘ quasi-federations’ . Most emergent federal countries are then considered ‘ fragile ’ , 52 because they experienced long periods of non-democratic regimes. Among them, Watts includes Spain (1978), Belgium (1993), Russia (1993), Bosnia and Herzegovina (1994), the Latin American federations (Brazil, Mexico, Venezuela, Argentina), Nigeria (1960), Ethiopia (1995), Pakistan (1973), as well as the ethno-federalisms of the Soviet era and four micro-federations (Comoros, Saint Kitts and Nevis, Micronesia, Belau). However, the category of ‘ emergent’ federal systems especially lacks homogeneity: it is diffi cult to group Spain and Belgium together with Pakistan, Venezuela or the micro-federations since the former are consolidated multilevel , whereas the latter ’ s federal arrangements have mainly remained on paper. Furthermore, both Germany and Austria — two classic prototypes of mature federations — experienced a long period of authoritar- ian regime under Nazi rule. Finally, the classifi cation does not take into account that the Latin American federations are vital and long-lasting and that Italy — a regional state that is surely ‘ quasi-federal’ — has also proved to be long-lasting. Precisely for the historical reasons mentioned above, the further distinction between aggregative (or integrative) and devolutionary federal systems also has a strong historical dimension. Aggregative systems are, as a matter of fact, older than devolutionary ones. The focus in this distinction is on the origin of the (federal) compact. Nicholas Aroney points out that aggregative federal countries are those in which the rationale was, at least predominantly, that ‘ previously independent political communities have been integrated into a federal system ’ (such as the United States,53 Switzerland, Canada, Germany and Australia), whereas devolutionary ones are ‘ those in which a formerly unitary state has devolved governmental powers upon a number of regions within that state’ (such as Spain, Belgium, Italy and South Africa and, for the most part, India). 54 In aggregative federal systems, pre-existing units must have been independent states (in the United States, Switzerland, Germany) or must have enjoyed a high degree of autonomy before their aggregation into the new federal structure, such as in Canada, Australia and Malaysia, dominions and

50 See Watts (n 3) 25. 51 ibid. 52 See N Steytler and J de Visser , ‘ “ Fragile Federations” and the Dynamics of Devolution ’ in F Palermo and E Alber (eds), Federalism as Decision-Making : Changes in Structures, Procedures and Policies ( Leiden , Brill – Nijhoff, 2015 ) 80 . 53 In fact, even in the United States only the original 13 states came together. The subsequent states were formed from territory originally governed by the federal government, which had to approve their formation into states. 54 N Aroney , ‘ Formation, Representation and Amendment in Federal Constitutions ’ (2006 ) 54 The American Journal of Comparative Law 277, 282 ; N Aroney , The Constitution of a Federal Common- wealth : The Making and Meaning of the Australian Constitution ( Cambridge , Cambridge University Press , 2009 ) 40f . 46 Manifestations colonies enjoying autonomy and self-government within the former British Empire. Again, the distinction is helpful but not all-encompassing. It does not explain, for instance, why some devolutionary federal systems such as Spain and Belgium present structures that are similar to those of integrative federations, nor it can respond to the question as to how to classify borderline cases, such as Argentina and Austria. And some federations, such as Canada and Australia, while materially aggregative, were legally created by an act of the British Parliament. Be that as it may, the aggre- gative or devolutionary origin of a federal system may have ‘ a vital infl uence on the way in which a federal constitution can be interpreted’ .55 When it comes to the institutional features of federal systems, a common distinc- tion is made between dual and cooperative systems. 56 Dual federalism is typical of the oldest federations (such as the United States, Canada, Switzerland, Aus- tralia), which adopted a distribution of powers, often explicitly based on a divided model of sovereignty: 57 the powers allocated at different levels of government were separated as if they were watertight compartments. 58 Further, laws enacted by each government level are, according to the model of ‘ legislative federalism’ , 59 as a rule ‘ implemented and administered by their own separate civil services and departments of states ’ .60 Such an approach was more frequent in older federations (with the notable exception of Germany), as it refl ects the idea of two separate and parallel legal orders, while history has proven that this is practically impossible, as coopera- tion and coordination are inherent to federal structures. Even in the United States, initially dual federalism has given way to more entanglement between governments by becoming over time cooperative or, as some put it, rather coercive.61 Dual federal- ism, famously described due to the distinct and separate layers (of government) also as ‘ layer cake’ federalism, has been replaced since the New Deal era by ‘ marble cake’ federalism.62 Cooperative systems, on the contrary, are based on the institutional assumption that, in most areas, decision-making and implementation require action by both levels of government and thus their integration to a certain degree, in order to reduce confl icts, to increase effi ciency and avoid duplication. At the same time, too much integration is likely to create confusion and reduce accountability, as well as ‘ competition and autonomous action and initiative of each level of government ’ .63

55 See Aroney, The Constitution (2009) 40. 56 For details, see ch 5.2.2 . 57 On divided sovereignty in the US and Switzerland, see ch 4.1.2 . 58 On the watertight compartments doctrine, see ch 5.2.1 . 59 See ch 5.3 . 60 TO Hueglin and A Fenna , Comparative Federalism : A Systematic Inquiry ( Peterborough , Broadview Press , 2006 ) ; P de Vos and W Freedman (eds), South African Constitutional Law in Context ( Oxford , Oxford University Press, 2014 ) 268 . 61 See J Kincaid , ‘ From Cooperative Federalism to Coercive Federalism ’ ( 1990 ) 509 The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 139 . 62 On these metaphors, see M Grodzins , ‘ The Federal System ’ in Goals for Americans: The Report of the President’ s Commission on National Goals ( New York : Columbia University Press, 1960 ) . 63 Watts (n 3) 122. Critical approaches to cooperative federalism are discussed in RL Watts , ‘ Origins of Cooperative and Competitive Federalism ’ in SL Greer (ed), Territory, Democracy and Justice: Regionalism and Federalism in Western Democracies ( London , Palgrave Macmillan, 2005 ) 121f . Federal State 47

A further distinction is occasionally made between calm and restless federations.64 The rationale of this distinction is primarily sociological, as it indicates the attitude when it comes to the accommodation of ethnic groups. In general, federal states in the context of diverse societies are likely to be restless, whereas countries that are more homogeneous in terms of population tend to be calm(er). However, history and political considerations do play a fundamental role in this distinction too. It occurs, in fact, that long-lasting (therefore mature and thus older) federal systems are indeed calm even if they operate in the context of diverse societies, such as in the case of Switzerland or Canada, and it is diffi cult to determine whether this attitude depends on the fact that the federation is long-lasting or if the federation is long-lasting because of a generally calm, cooperative attitude. Furthermore, as most federal systems in the context of diverse societies have been established more recently, ie, after the Cold War,65 and defi nitely after World War I, there is a certain historical overlap between these (as a rule, restless) systems and those that follow a devolutionary pattern. The same also goes for the last recurrent distinction, ie, between symmetrical and asymmetrical federations which concerns differences between subnational entities in terms of institutional elements such as fi nancial relations and representation in a second chamber. Having regard specifi cally to the element of the distribution of powers, symmetrical systems are those in which (legislative) powers are distributed uniformly, whereas asymmetry occurs when certain units are provided with more powers than the others. 66 In fact, the historical element largely also covers this dis- tinction, as usually older, aggregative federal systems are based on the principle of the same powers for the subnational units, whereas younger, devolutionary federal countries often provide some specifi c areas with a different status in order to accom- modate specifi c differences, be they ethno-cultural or territorial.67

2.2.3 Defi nition by Means of Institutional Elements

Many valuable attempts have been made in the literature to defi ne the federal state (rather, according to the terminology adopted in this book, federal systems) based on institutional elements. The idea behind such an approach is simple and meaningful. While federalism always entails political and ideological elements and is thus also subjective,68 federal systems are concrete, constitutional manifestations of the fed- eral principle; thus, a comparative observation should make it possible to determine the common elements, those that are essential in order to identify a federal system.

64 See G Poggeschi , Language Rights and Duties in the Evolution of Public Law ( Baden-Baden , Nomos , 2013 ) 152 . 65 See ch 4.2.1 . 66 See ch 5.1.1 . 67 See R Agranoff (ed), Accommodating Diversity : Asymmetry in Federal States ( Baden-Baden , Nomos , 1999 ) . 68 See chs 0.2 and 1.1 . 48 Manifestations

2.D Institutional Defi nitions of Federal States (or Systems) Such an approach has indeed inspired several attempts to defi ne federal states (or systems) by means of institutional elements. Among the most convincing institutional defi nitions are those provided by Ronald Watts and Peter Pernthaler. Watts proceeds from a political perspective and fi rst distinguishes between federalism, federal political systems and federations. Federalism ‘ refers to the advocacy of multi-tiered government combining elements of shared rule and regional self-rule’ .69 ‘ Federal politi- cal systems’ and ‘ federations’ are instead descriptive terms: the former being broader and referring to a ‘ political system in which … there are two (or more) levels of government’ , thus encompassing the whole spectrum of non-unitary manifestations (confederations, fed- erations, etc); the latter are a particular species of the genus ‘ in which neither the federal nor the constituent units are constitutionally subordinated to the other, ie each has sover- eign powers derived from the constitution rather than another level of government, each is empowered to deal directly with its citizens in the exercise of the legislative, executive and taxing power and each is directly elected by its citizens’ . 70 Based on this assump- tion, Watts lists six institutional elements that, in his view, are common to all federations: ‘ 1) two orders of government each acting directly on their citizens; 2) a formal constitu- tional distribution of legislative and executive authority and allocation of revenue resources between the two orders of government ensuring some areas of genuine autonomy for each order; 3) provision of the designated representation of distinct regional views within the federal policy-making institutions, usually provided by the particular form of the federal second chamber; 4) a supreme written constitution not unilaterally amendable and requir- ing the consent of a signifi cant proportion of the constituent units; 5) an umpire (in the form of courts or provisions for referendums) to rule on disputes between governments; 6) processes and institutions to facilitate intergovernmental collaboration for those areas where governmental responsibilities are shared or inevitably overlap.’ 71 Pernthaler takes instead a more legal perspective, which handles concepts like sover- eignty, citizenship and constitutional subordination more carefully.72 For him, the insti- tutional minimum common denominator includes four elements: 1) division of statehood (sovereignty) mirrored by a constitutionally guaranteed division of powers that can only be changed with the consent of the member units; within the respective competences, the federation and member units are independent and equally sovereign (dual government); 2) effective participation of subnational entities in the decision-making process at the central level, especially with regard to the procedure to amend the constitution, to adopt national laws and to be represented in common institutions, such as the constitutional court or in the election of the head of the state; 3) constitutional autonomy of the subna- tional entities, ie, their power to autonomously make their fundamental choices within the limits of the national constitution; 4) a federal fi nancial arrangement, ie, a division of taxa- tion and spending powers that corresponds to the division of competences and includes solidarity among all members of the federation. For Pernthaler, these four elements are of an existential, functional nature: if they are not given in a polity, the latter cannot be considered to be federal.

69 Watts (n 3) 6. 70 Watts (n 3) 7. 71 Watts (n 3) 7. See also RL Watts , ‘ Comparative Conclusions ’ in A Majeed et al (eds), Distribution of Powers and Responsibilities in Federal Countries ( Montreal , McGill – Queen ’ s University Press, 2006 ) . 72 P Pernthaler , Ö sterreichisches Bundesstaatsrecht ( Wien , Verlag Ö sterreich, 2004 ) 299ff . Federal State 49

All such defi nitions are extremely valuable and certainly useful from a comparative perspective as an orientation in the complex fi eld of federal studies. From a com- parative point of view, however, two aspects need to be considered as caveats against a possible all-encompassing institutional defi nition of a federal system. First, each defi nition based on a comparative analysis presupposes the selection of case studies and thus strongly infl uences the outcome of the research. Put differently, if certain countries are pre-identifi ed as federal and thus only their constitutions are analysed, this leads to a very different outcome than if other cases are included too. For example, Watts considered in 2008 that there were 25 fully fl edged federations, and these were considered as a comparative basis for his analysis,73 while Anderson listed 28 federations the year before. 74 Such an approach is rather amphibolic, as it is likely to prove that the countries matching the defi nition are precisely those taken as the basis for the analysis. Second, federal constitutional arrangements are very peculiar to each and every country, while pursuing similar goals. Therefore, upon closer observation, each com- mon element has in fact some exceptions. For example, the constitutional autonomy of subnational units is not given in some uncontested federations like Canada or Belgium and, except for Jammu and Kashmir, India, whose member units do not have their own codifi ed constitutions in the sense of both formally and materially qualifi ed acts of autonomous legislation. 75 Typical constitutional matters are then essentially regulated by the national constitution and/or by national special laws. 76 Conversely, in some regional states such as Italy, the regions adopt their own con- stitutions by means of entrenched laws. And in any case, the national constitution prevails over the constitutions of the subnational units. Another example is the effective participation of the subnational units in the deci- sion-making process at the national level, often considered as a main institutional indicator of federal statehood. 77 It is often argued, for example, that the adoption of the Seventeenth Amendment to the US Constitution, which mandated the popu- lar election of senators in each state, transformed the representation from federal into democratic, de facto eliminating the genuine representation of the states. 78

73 Austria, Belgium, Germany, Russia, Spain and Switzerland in Europe; Canada, the Federation of Saint Kitts and Nevis, Mexico and the United States in North America; Argentina, Brazil and Venezuela in South America; the Union of the Comoros, Ethiopia, Nigeria and South Africa in Africa; India, Pakistan and Malaysia in Asia; the United Arab Emirates in the Middle East; Australia, Palau and the Federated States of Micronesia in Oceania. See Watts (n 3) 9. 74 Argentina, Australia, Austria, Belau (Palau), Belgium, Bosnia and Herzegovina, Brazil, Canada, Comoros, the Democratic Republic of Congo, Ethiopia, Germany, India, Iraq, Malaysia, Mexico, Micronesia, Nigeria, Pakistan, Russia, St Kitts and Nevis, South Africa, Spain, Sudan, Switzerland, the United Arab Emirates, the United States of America and Venezuela. See G Anderson , Federalism : An Introduction ( Oxford , Oxford University Press, 2007 ) 3 . 75 See chs 5.1.1 and 5.1.2 . 76 See C Saunders , ‘ The Relationship between National and Subnational Constitutions ’ in Konrad- Adenauer-Stiftung (ed), Subnational Constitutional Governance ( Pretoria , KAS South Africa, 1999 ) 29 . 77 For this assumption, see M Moushkeli , La thé orie juridique de l’ É tat fé d é ral ( Paris , Pedone , 1931 ) 229ff . 78 See B Ackerman , ‘ The New Separation of Powers ’ (2000 ) 113 Harvard Law Review 633 , and G Doria , ‘ The Paradox of Federal Bicameralism ’ ( 2006 ) 5 European Diversity and Autonomy Papers 1 . 50 Manifestations

And while some established federations have experienced severe problems with the effectiveness of their second chambers, especially in terms of the representative- ness of the subnational entities (Belgium, Canada, India, Mexico, Austria, etc — Venezuela even abolished the Senate in 1999), some regional states have developed more effective forums for the institutional representation of the subnational units via intergovernmental conferences (Spain, Italy, to some extent even France), which are common also to some classical federal states such as Canada.79 This means, in turn, that institutional defi nitions are also incomplete because they are related to, and determined by, the historical evolution of each country. Not only federalism80 but also the federal system is a process, and any picture of it taken at a given moment cannot refl ect the movement or the dynamic of the process. If federal- ism and the federal system were movies, any defi nition would be just a screenshot, thus inevitably partial and ultimately doomed to fail, although defi nitions are no doubt extremely useful for orientation and for knowing what the rule is in general. Defi nitions, in other words, only matter if they are taken critically, knowing that not only federalism, but also the federal state (and system), are abstract categories that should defi ne very concrete phenomena. Thus, the only possible use of a defi nition is to provide a very general indication of what the phenomena entail.

2.3 REGIONAL STATE AND RELATED MANIFESTATIONS

2.3.1 Defi nition and Relation to the Federal State

A regional state can thus somehow be defi ned a contrariis : the easiest and probably most precise defi nition is that it is neither a unitary nor a federal state. To say precisely what a regional state is, however, is not that simple, and it is even more diffi cult to draw a clear line between federal and regional states. In this respect, an effective description has been put forward by Peter Hä berle. Noting that a difference exists between federal and regional states, although it is hardly possible to fi nd decisive qualitative elements, he wrote that regionalism is the ‘ little brother’ of federalism.81 This expression makes clear that both typologies produce the same phenomenon: vertically dividing power according to the rules pro- vided by the national constitution. At the same time, due to the different historical origins (at least between regional states and classical coming-together federations), the different aims and the different traditions of the two categories, they are not entirely the same, while sharing the same genes. ‘ Little brother ’ is to be understood not only in quantitative terms, but — in addition to Hä berle ’ s intuition— also in a time perspective: as a matter of principle, it is fair to say that subnational entities of regional states enjoy a lower degree of autonomy as compared to those of federal

79 See ch 6.2 . 80 CJ Friedrich , Trends of Federalism in Theory and Practice ( New York , Praeger , 1968 ) . 81 P H ä berle , ‘ F ö deralismus, Regionalismus und Kleinstaaten in Europa ’ in Europ ä ische Rechtskultur: Versuch einer Annä herung in zw ö lf Schritten ( Baden-Baden , Nomos , 1994 ) 257ff . Regional State and Related Manifestations 51 states, although, as always, there are signifi cant exceptions: there is no doubt, for instance, that Spanish autonomous communities or (some of the) Italian regions enjoy many more powers than, for instance, subnational units in countries such as Mexico, Venezuela, Russia, Austria and others. And certainly, the regional state is a far more recent creation (younger brother) than the federal state. In any event, whatever (if any) the difference between federal and regional states, in recent decades there has undoubtedly been a convergence between them: while federal states usually experience centripetal tendencies, with an increase in the power of the centre, in regional states the trend is towards further decentralisation. 82 As a matter of fact, the qualitative difference, if one exists, is also being considerably reduced.

2.E Italy 2007: Autonomy and Sovereignty of the Sardinian People? It would be wrong to infer from the above that categories do not matter. An interest- ing example is provided by a judgment of the Italian Constitutional Court in 2007. In 2006, the regional Parliament of Sardinia initiated the procedure for the adoption of a new regional constitution, setting up a special commission called the Commission for Drafting the New Basic Law on Autonomy and Sovereignty of the Sardinian People. The name sug- gested, on the one hand, the existence of a Sardinian people as different from the Italian people. On the other hand, it indicated that the Sardinian people could enjoy ‘ sovereignty ’ , ie, that the autonomy of the region does not derive from the constitution but from a free determination of the sovereign Sardinian people, which could also decide differently if they so wish. The terminology used was clearly aimed at provoking a debate. As expected, the national government immediately challenged the Sardinian law, and the Constitutional Court found it in breach of the constitution.83 The Court offered a formalistic defi nition of the qualitative difference between a federal and a regional system, pointing out that, in the latter, subnational entities are autonomous and not sovereign. Even the most signifi cant degree of decentralisation does not alter the unity and indivis- ibility of sovereignty, which cannot but be vested in the state and in its unitary people. Defi nitions, thus, sometimes matter, even though it might be contended that in federal states there would have been the same outcome (although maybe not the same reasoning).

2.3.2 Rationale and Cases

Like the federal states, so-called regional states are also very diffi cult to defi ne. Precisely like the federal state, the regional state is an umbrella term used to describe the same phenomenon with a different intensity. From a historical perspective, the very idea of a regional state developed much later and to some extent in opposition to that of the federal state. When the age

82 According to L Hooghe et al, The Rise of Regional Authority: A Comparative Study of 42 Democracies (1950– 2006) ( New York , Routledge, 2010 ) , between 1970 and 2005 only two states became more centralised, while many experienced an increase in what the authors call ‘ regional authority ’ . 83 Italian Constitutional Court No 365/2007. 52 Manifestations of coming-together federations came to an end, after World War I, regionalisation processes started by means of the decentralisation of unitary polities. Such decen- tralisation, in the mind of its advocates, should precisely not go as far as to create a federation. Instead, it should help establish a polity in between the federation — which was considered too decentralised and was historically maybe no longer fea- sible — and the unitary state, which was far too centralised and could no longer accommodate the ethno-cultural, geographical, political, social and economic diver- sities. In most cases, such a middle ground between the unitary and the federal state was an experiment with the main aim of accommodating ethno-cultural differences, such as in the case of Spain and of (pre-federal) Belgium. In other cases, the accom- modation of ethno-cultural differences was just one out of many other reasons for the establishment of a regional state, like in Italy. In any case, these countries, how- ever defi ned, have experimented with ‘ innovative federal and quasi federal forms’ that refl ect different ‘ degrees of centralization or decentralization’ .84 Spain is usually considered the main laboratory of the regional state. In fact, during the nineteenth century, several attempts were made to break the centrali- sation of the Napoleonic system. However, the prototype of a regional state, in between a federation and a unitary state, aimed in particular at guaranteeing ethno- cultural differences, was developed by the Republican Constitution of 1931. Then, the idea was that of an ‘ integral state’ (this was the terminology of the Constitu- tion), compatible with a substantial autonomy of municipalities and regions. The Constitution of 1931 was trumped by the Franco regime, which repressed all forms of autonomy, but it served as an essential precedent (together with the German and the Italian models) for the democratic Constitution of 1978, adopted after the death of Franco. In response to the strong nationalistic movements in the Basque Country, Catalonia and Galicia, a form of so-called pre-autonomic regime was extended to the whole Spanish territory between 1977 and 1978. The Constitution of 1978 reached a diffi cult compromise between unitary and nationalistic instances, by defi n- ing a process but not a clear end: the process of decentralisation was left open, and only a procedural framework was established in which different forms of autonomy could be realised according to the needs and specifi cities of each territory. 85 While proclaiming the indissoluble unity of the nation, the constitution ‘ recognizes and guarantees the right to autonomy of the nationalities and regions ’ (Article 2 of the Spanish Constitution). The regionalising process set up by the constitution moves from the bottom up and provides two procedures for achieving regional autonomy: Article 143 out- lines the so-called ‘ slow track’ to form regions (autonomous communities), by stat- ing that neighbouring provinces with common historical, cultural and economic elements, the islands and the provinces of historical regional relevance can form autonomous communities. The ‘ fast track’ outlined in Article 151 was instead

84 Watts (n 3) 5. 85 See JJ Gonz á lez Encinar , El Estado unitario– federal ( Madrid , Tecnos, 1985 ) . Regional State and Related Manifestations 53 reserved for the territories where historical nationalities were settled 86 and those, in fact only Andalusia, that completed a complex and lengthy procedure, including a referendum. These territories were allowed to proceed immediately to the estab- lishment of autonomous communities. The difference between these autonomous communities and those on the slow track, lies not only in the procedure for their establishment, but also in the attribution of powers: fast-track autonomous commu- nities could immediately seize from the centre all powers foreseen in Article 149 of the Spanish Constitution, while other autonomous communities were for the initial fi ve years limited to the competences listed in Article 148. Such a strongly asym- metrical design of the Spanish regional state was progressively reduced, although the autonomous communities of the historical nationalities still enjoy wider powers than the others in several fi elds, including local policing and, for the Basque Country, fi nancing.87

2.F Spain 1983: The State of Autonomies and the LOAPA Decision Following the attempted coup in February 1981, the process of regionalisation was put under stricter control by means of a controversial Organic Law on the Harmonisation of the Autonomy Process (LOAPA). This law, based on Article 150(3) of the Spanish Consti- tution,88 stipulated, inter alia, that the slower way of regionalisation was to be preferred, and it introduced strong elements of oversight by the central authorities. The law was scru- tinised by the Constitutional Court in 1983, and the future development of the just-born state of autonomies (Estado de las autonomí as ) depended on the decision. The ruling struck down signifi cant parts of the LOAPA (14 out of 38 Articles) and affi rmed that the law in fact did not achieve the goal of harmonising the autonomy process and that the national government is not allowed to unilaterally reshape the distribution of powers.89 Among the provisions declared unconstitutional were those stipulating that the state ’ s norms should take automatic precedence over those of the autonomous communi- ties and that civil servants in the regions should be seconded by the state rather than being recruited locally. The ruling had the effect of setting the autonomy process in motion.

While decentralisation in Spain has gone as far as to suggest that it might already be a federal state, although a ‘ federation in disguise ’ ,90 Italy is another classical example of a regional state. 91 Since the achievement of national unity, completed in

86 According to the constitutional terminology, these were those territories ‘ which in the past approved by referendum their autonomy statutes and that at the time of entry into force of this constitution enjoy provisional autonomy regimes’ , Spanish Constitution, Transitional Provision No 2. 87 See ch 7.1.3 . 88 On this provision, see ch 5.2.3 . 89 STC 76/1983. 90 L Moreno , ‘ Federalization in Multinational Spain ’ in M Burgess and J Pinder (eds), Multinational Federations ( London , Routledge, 2007 ) 86 – 107 . 91 For an overview, see F Palermo , ‘ Italy : A Federal Country without Federalism ? ’ in Burgess and Tarr , Constitutional Dynamics ( 2012 ) . 54 Manifestations the 1860s, the Italian state has been modelled according to the French blueprint of a centralised and bureaucratic state. It was only with the Republican Constitution of 1948 that an innovative, but at the same time feeble, experiment with regionalisa- tion was carried out. Not unlike Spain, but for different reasons, Italian regionalism is characterised by its asymmetrical design, both as a matter of constitutional law and in terms of the effective use of powers transferred to the regions. Despite the constitutional provisions for a general regional design for the whole country, at fi rst, only fi ve special, or autonomous, regions were established, all situated in the periphery (three in the Alpine arch in the north, with consistent minority groups, Aosta Valley, Trentino-South Tyrol, Friuli-Venezia Giulia, and the two main islands of Sicily and Sardinia). Their differentiated treatment was mainly a reaction to the complex problems of regional diversity: international obligations imposed by the peace treaty and fears regarding the secession of these peripheral areas. Each of them is guaranteed by a special statute, a basic law with constitutional rank. As an innovative experiment, the regionalisation of the whole country, a third way between a federal and a unitary system, was aimed at avoiding too strong an asym- metry between the special regions and the rest of the territory. However, the regional design was only fully developed in the 1970s, when the ordinary regions were estab- lished and legislative powers effectively devolved. Since then, a permanent increase in the regional powers gradually narrowed the gap between ordinary and special regions. The path has been anything but straightforward, infl uenced by shifting political priorities and very much determined by constitutional adjudication. After a series of reforms in the 1980s and 1990s, two constitutional amendments were approved in 1999 and 2001 that considerably increased the powers of the (ordinary) regions. The fi rst reform introduced the direct election of regional presidents in order to enhance political stability in the ordinary regions. It also strengthened their constitutional autonomy, as the regional basic laws are now to be adopted by the ordinary regions themselves in a special procedure (double approval and a possible referendum). The second reform of 2001 completely reshaped the constitutional provisions on relations between the state and the regions. It drastically changed the distribution of legislative and administrative powers between the state and the regions: Article 117 of the Italian Constitution now lists all legislative powers of the state, as well as the fi elds of concurrent legislation (ie, those in which the regions can legislate only within the framework of general guidelines determined by a national law). By contrast with the situation before, the residual powers lie with the regions according to classic federal schemes. Administrative powers are no longer connected with legislative ones but are distributed in a fl exible manner according to the criteria of ‘ subsidiarity, differentiation and proportionality’ (Article 118). The new provi- sion on fi scal federalism provides for the partial fi nancial autonomy of subnational entities (Article 119), and preventive state control over regional legislation was abol- ished, although the state retained the power to replace regional norms with a view to guaranteeing the legal and economic unity of the system (Article 120). There are several other relevant examples of regional states, although, quite interestingly, nearly all of them are in Europe. Among them, some vest subnational units with legislative powers, and others only with (albeit broad) administrative Regional State and Related Manifestations 55 powers. The former include Belgium with subnational entities having had the power to enact (quasi)laws 92 even before 1993 — when it offi cially became, by constitutional denomination, a federal state — and, to a more limited extent, Serbia (the autono- mous province of Vojvodina can pass legislation). The latter range from the case of France after the constitutional reform of 2003, when the principle of the ‘ unitary decentralized state ’ was introduced in the Constitution (Article 1) and the regions were given very broad administrative powers, including in important fi elds that are usually regulated by law. Further, usually temperate examples of regional states are to be found in some Central, Eastern and South-eastern European countries.93 From a comparative perspective, some elements common to all regional states can be identifi ed. First, power also historically proceeds from the centre and is gradually devolved to the periphery. Second, the distribution of powers and fi nancial preroga- tives among the regions is asymmetrical: such asymmetry may vary over the course of time but it remains a structural factor of regional states. Third, the regionalising process is often prompted by the need to accommodate ethno-cultural differences: while this is not the only reason for the regionalisation of a state, it is defi nitely one of the main ones. Other motives are linked with the complexity of modern govern- ance and the factual impossibility for one single level of government to cope with such complexity. Fourth, being the regional state initially conceived as a compromise between two categories with longer traditions — the unitary and the federal state— it is more dynamic overall, and it undergoes processes of reform of the territorial setting more often. Fifth, from a terminological point of view, while many constitu- tions defi ne the respective state as ‘ federal ’ (even when this is all but uncontested), no constitution defi nes itself as ‘ regional’ .

2.3.3 Devolution

The term ‘ devolution ’ is becoming more commonly used in contemporary consti- tutional and political jargon. As a general phenomenon, it indicates the transfer of public functions from the centre to subnational elected authorities. However, it is also used especially in the peculiar context of the United Kingdom, where it has been part of the constitutional discourse since at least the 1970s. In the UK context, ‘ devolution’ describes the process of the decentralisation of powers from the central government. According to the probably most cited defi nition provided by Vernon Bogdanor, devolution means ‘ the transfer of powers from a superior to an inferior political authority ’94 and it consists of three elements: a transfer to a subordinate but

92 These acts of the subnational legislatures are called decrees and have the same legal force as laws passed by the federal parliament. Only in the case of the Brussels Parliament these acts are referred to as ordinances which have a slightly inferior legal status. The federal government may suspend ordinances if it regards them as compromising the role of Brussels as the capital of Belgium or its international role. 93 See F Palermo and S Parolari (eds), Regional Dynamics in Central and Eastern Europe : New Approaches to Decentralization ( Leiden , Brill – Nijhoff , 2013 ) . 94 V Bogdanor , Devolution in the United Kingdom ( Oxford , Oxford University Press, 2001 ) 2 — a defi nition that was provided for the process in the UK but would also suit the phenomenon in general. 56 Manifestations elected body, a territorial/geographical basis and functions previously exercised by ministers and parliament. The parts of the UK covered by such a transfer of powers include Scotland, and Wales, while attempts to extend devolu- tion to England proper failed after a referendum in the north-east in 2004. This has sparked the still unanswered ‘ English question’ , which refers to the interrelated issues of England’ s place in the Union and of decentralisation within it.95 In the 1970s, the idea of devolution was developed by nationalists as an update of the nineteenth century ’ s ‘ home rule all round’ , ie, a fully developed self- government. 96 Under the Labour Government of 1974 – 79, two bills were proposed (the Scotland Bill and the Wales Bill) but were rejected by referendums held in the affected areas. When Labour returned to power in 1997, devolution was an essential part of the electoral agenda, and in 1998 four bills were adopted by Westminster and confi rmed in local referendums: the Scotland Act, the Government of Wales Act, the Northern Ireland Act and the Greater London Authority Act. Albeit with successive, signifi cant amendments, these acts are still in force. In terms of the entrenchment of these acts, some scholars even assume that they could be repealed and amended only by a law supported by a referendum.97 While procedurally entrenched, devolution is legally speaking a reversible process: like any national law in the UK, in theory the Westminster Parliament could, at any time, withdraw it by simple majority. As unlikely as that would be, this is an essen- tial element that distinguishes (British) devolution from other forms of the regional state. This aspect should, however, not be overestimated. It has to do mostly with the essential elements of British constitutionalism, which presupposes unlimited sover- eignty of the parliament. 98 Yet, British courts have affi rmed the existence of so-called ‘ constitutional statutes’ , among them the devolution acts.

2.G United Kingdom 2002: Devolution and Factual Limits on the Sovereignty of Parliament ? In Thoburn v Sunderland City Council , the Divisional Court advanced the existence of ‘ constitutional statutes’ .99 In particular, Lord Justice Laws writing for the Court identi- fi ed the 1215, the , the , the Reform Acts, the , the , the Government of Wales Act 1998 and the Act 1972 as constitutional acts that are, because of their constitutional importance, to be protected from the implied repeal rule, according to which later acts of legislation take precedence over earlier acts and result in the confl icting

95 See M Burch et al, ‘ Devolution, Change and European Union Policy-making in the UK ’ ( 2005 ) 39 Regional Studies 465 ; R Hazell (ed), The English Question ( Manchester , Manchester University Press, 2005 ) . 96 See K Robbins , Great Britain : Identities, Institutions and the Idea of since 1500 (The Present and the Past) ( London , Routledge, 1998 ) 206ff . 97 See B Hadfi eld , ‘ Devolution : A National Conversation? ’ in J Jowell and D Oliver (eds), The Changing Constitution ( Oxford , Oxford University Press, 2011 ) 218 . 98 See AV Dicey , The Law of the Constitution , 10th edn ( London , Macmillan , 1965 ) 39 . 99 Thoburn v Sunderland City Council [ 2002 ] EWHC 195 (Admin), (Metric Martyrs case). Regional State and Related Manifestations 57

parts of the earlier act being repealed. In other words, ‘ constitutional statutes’ can only be repealed explicitly. What is uncontested, in any case, is the supremacy of the British institutions over the devolved ones. Since the establishment of the UK Supreme Court under the Constitutional Reform Act 2005 and the start of its work in 2009, this judicial body has the power to adjudicate confl icts regarding devolution.

Parliamentary sovereignty and devolution were also, in the context of so-called ‘ ’ , an issue for the courts. The High Court ruled in November 2016 that the UK Secretary of State does not have power under the Crown ’ s foreign affairs pre- rogative to formally notify the Council of the EU about the country ’ s withdrawal (Article 50 of the Treaty on European Union), but required an authorising act by the sovereign UK Parliament, not by the devolved legislatures. 100 The Supreme Court upheld this judgment in January 2017, albeit with a partially different reasoning,101 and after the adoption of the European Union (Notifi cation of Withdrawal) Bill 2017 the United Kingdom eventually invoked Article 50 on 29 March 2017. Another essential element of devolution is its inherent asymmetrical character: each affected area has its own institutional system, its own powers and its own cooperation procedures with the central government. 102 This depends on the very different reasons behind each individual devolution process. In the UK, Scottish devolution is the product of autonomous historical constitutional traditions that have never ceased to exist; Welsh devolution is the constitutional answer to ethno- cultural claims; the devolution in Northern Ireland is an attempt to provide an insti- tutional and constitutional answer to dramatic social and political cleavages; and even the ‘ quasi-devolution ’ of the Greater London Authority is aimed at providing solutions to complex governmental issues common to many big cities. 103 At the same time, asymmetry is largely compensated by the unity of the civil service: apart from in Northern Ireland, there is a single and unitary civil service in the UK, which guarantees uniformity in interpretation and implementation of the rules and, even more importantly, a unifi ed administrative culture. This contributes signifi cantly to the effectiveness of the system in spite of this being largely regulated by conventional rules, including in sensitive matters such as fi nancial relations. As to the relationship between devolution and other concepts, some authors consider devolution as a functional element and sometimes a prerequisite to

100 R (Miller) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union [ 2016 ] EWHC 2768 (Admin). 101 R (on the application of Miller and Dos Santos) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union [ 2017 ] UKSC 5 . 102 Bogdanor, Devolution in the United Kingdom (2001); J Bradbury and J Mawson (eds), British Regionalism and Devolution : The Challenges of State Reform and European Integration ( London , Routledge, 1997 ) . 103 Greater London is, legally speaking, part of the local government and thus not included in devolution in the strict sense. The phenomenon, however, is similar and the debate as to whether the Greater London Authority (GLA) is to be considered part of devolution or not resembles the one as to whether federalism and regionalism are the same phenomenon or not. Interestingly, in 2011 the Greater Manchester Combined Authority (GMCA) was also established. 58 Manifestations federalisation,104 while others believe that devolution and federalisation are two antithetical constitutional processes. 105 From a comparative observation, it can be affi rmed that devolution very much resembles the process of regionalisation. The ‘ devolutionary state ’ is in some way the British version of the regional state, especially because devolved powers are delegated powers. Devolution has been effectively described as ‘ the delegation of central government powers to subordinate units, these powers being exercised with some degree of autonomy though with ulti- mate power remaining with the central government’ .106 Devolution is in sum an advanced form of territorial decentralisation, which nevertheless does not change the fundamental constitutional nature of the state. Especially in its most advanced Scottish form, devolution goes as far as possible without crossing the border of national sovereignty. 107

2.3.4 Autonomy and Similar Manifestations

‘ It is fair to claim that no clear account of the concept of autonomy is available. ’ 108 Another slippery issue is the demarcation between regional/devolved states and autonomy. The latter is a very broad concept that appears in different branches of scholarship, not only in law and politics, but also in philosophy and the natural sciences. In law, Ruth Lapidoth identifi es four conceptions of autonomy: a) the right to act upon one ’ s own discretion in certain matters; b) a synonym of independence; c) a synonym of decentralisation; d) the exclusive power of legislation, adminis- tration and adjudication in specifi c areas of an autonomous entity. 109 Moreover, autonomy has different meanings if used with regard to constitutional law or inter- national law or if attributed to territorial entities or to groups of people (territorial or personal autonomy).110 For our purposes, (territorial) autonomy (of a territorial entity) can be considered a synonym of decentralisation, ie: [G]ranting internal self-government to a region … thus recognizing a partial independ- ence from the infl uence of the national or central government. This independence can be determined primarily by the degree of actual as well as formal independence enjoyed by the autonomous entity in its political decision-making process.111

104 See J Kendle , Federal Britain : A History ( London , Routledge, 1997 ) . 105 See MA Fazal , A Federal Constitution for the United Kingdom : An Alternative to Devolution ( Aldershot , Dartmouth Publishing , 1997 ) . 106 P Norton , ‘ Devolution : A Threat to the UK? Or a Reinforcement? ’ in P Norton (ed), The Constitu- tion in Flux ( Oxford , Blackwell Publishers, 1982 ) 174 . 107 See C Himsworth and CR Munro , The Scotland Act 1998 ( Edinburgh , Sweet & Maxwell , 1999 ) . 108 M Wiberg , ‘ Political Autonomy: Ambiguities and Clarifi cations ’ in M Suksi (ed), Autonomy : Appli- cations and Implications ( The Hague , Kluwer Law International, 1998 ) 43 . 109 See R Lapidoth , ‘ Autonomy : Potential and Limitations ’ ( 1993 ) 1 International Journal of Minority and Group Rights 269 , esp 277. 110 See TH Malloy and F Palermo (eds), Minority Accommodation through Territorial and Non- Territorial Autonomy ( Oxford , Oxford University Press, 2015 ) . 111 H-J Heintze , ‘ On the Legal Understanding of Autonomy ’ in Suksi , Autonomy ( 1998 ) 7 .