Copyright by Scott Matthew Truelove 2012

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Copyright by Scott Matthew Truelove 2012 Copyright by Scott Matthew Truelove 2012 The Dissertation Committee for Scott Matthew Truelove Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Plato and Thucydides on Athenian Imperialism Committee: T.K. Seung, Supervisor Aloysius Martinich H.W. Perry Jeffrey Tulis Paul Woodruff Plato and Thucydides on Athenian Imperialism by Scott Matthew Truelove, B.A., M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2012 To my family Acknowledgements I would not have been able to complete this project without the support of many people to whom I am very grateful. Shelby Barnett graciously granted me extended leave so that I could finish without worry. Todd Young and Pat Burger each provided frequent and friendly “reminders” that I was forgetting to finish something important. Each member of my committee helped me over the course of my obscenely long graduate career. H.W. Perry encouraged me to think seriously about the attraction and dangers of idealism. Jeffrey K. Tulis taught me to consider how regimes shape the souls of those who live under them. Al Martinich is partially responsible for the topic of the dissertation by introducing me to Hobbes’ translation of Thucydides. Paul Woodruff showed me the richness of Thucydides scholarship by recommending I read Adam Parry’s dissertation Logos and Ergon in Thucydides. T.K. Seung guided me through my graduate career. Those of us fortunate enough to know him understand that Dr. Seung’s genius lies in his ability to see thematic connections that elude nearly everyone else. However, it is his insatiable passion for knowledge and for his students that has most profoundly affected me (though I’m also grateful for his forgiveness). I remain in his debt for his willingness to tolerate my many shortcomings. By nature or custom, everyone has a family. The “birth lottery,” as many call it, reflects the fact that we have no agency over what family we are born into—it is purely a matter of chance or luck. I am well aware that I am one lucky guy. My sister Robin patiently listened to my concerns, even though as a scientist she must be confounded about why I would be interested in studying political philosophy. My wife Rosie provided constant encouragement and gave me the two most precious gifts I’ll ever v receive in our sons Isaac and Adam. I never fully appreciated the power and seriousness of the challenge that the love of one’s own poses to justice until their births. Finally, I will never be able to repay my parents for the love and support they’ve given me through my whole life. During the writing of this dissertation, my mother reminded me what courage looks like in deeds. And my father reminded me that even though speech sometimes seems impotent in the face of deeds, it is not. I dedicate this to all of them. vi Plato and Thucydides on Athenian Imperialism Scott Matthew Truelove, Ph.D. The University of Texas at Austin, 2012 Supervisor: T.K. Seung For over two thousand years, Plato’s superiority to Thucydides was taken as an article of faith in Western philosophy. Nietzsche was the first to challenge this verdict by asserting his view—on philosophical grounds—that Thucydides was the more penetrating analyst of the human condition. Other than Nietzsche’s consideration of the two thinkers, surprisingly little has been done to investigate the connections between the two greatest Greek prose writers. My purpose in this dissertation is to rekindle this debate in light of new evidence to see what—if anything—can be gained by examining the relationship between how Plato and Thucydides treat the problem of Athenian imperialism. More specifically, I believe and attempt to show that: (1) Plato silently but explicitly directs his readers to different parts of the History through the use of textual references and thematic patterns; (2) Plato uses these textual allusions to highlight the common ground between the two thinkers, and that Plato understands Thucydides to be an ally to his philosophic aims; (3) Plato and Thucydides agree that the underlying cause of Athenian imperialism can be attributed to a combination of greed (pleonexia) and the internalization of specific sophistic teachings that, whether intended by the sophists or not, support unbridled appetitiveness as the best way of life; and (4) Plato and Thucydides largely agree on the solution to the problem—that pleonexia must be extirpated from the ruling order. vii Table of Contents Introduction ..............................................................................................................1 Chapter 1: Thucydides on the Foundations of Imperialism ...................................33 Chapter 2: Plato on the Moral Foundation of Politics ...........................................67 Chapter 3: Thucydides’ Pericles and Plato’s Protagoras ....................................108 Chapter 4: Thucydides’ Archaeology and Plato’s Republic ................................160 Bibliography ........................................................................................................215 viii Introduction For over two thousand years, Plato’s superiority to Thucydides was taken as an article of faith in Western philosophy. It is not terribly difficult to understand why this was the case. The majesty of Plato’s corpus is nearly impossible to deny.1 Plato’s dialogues are littered with insights about such weighty things as the human soul and its composition, the nature of knowledge and reality, and the relationship between virtue and community. Unlike Thucydides, whose work appears at first blush to focus only on a particular, historically situated event, Plato is the avatar for what it means to be a philosopher. Through his dialogues, Plato weaves a comprehensive and interconnected web of ideas that take in the whole of human life.2 Nietzsche was the first to challenge this verdict by asserting his view—on philosophical grounds—that Thucydides was the more penetrating analyst of the human condition. For Nietzsche, Thucydides’ analytic superiority is due to his more astute and synoptic presentation of human motivation and his clear-eyed “scientific” method, in contrast to Plato’s moralism.3 Other than Nietzsche’s consideration of the two thinkers, surprisingly little has been done to investigate the connections between the two greatest Greek prose writers. As R. B. Rutherford observes, it is “astounding that more has not 1 Even Nietzsche testifies to Plato’s greatness in the frequency, vehemence, and often outlandishness with which he attacks Plato. Among other things, Nietzsche criticizes Plato’s ability as a prose stylist in 2 It is this comprehensiveness that led Whitehead to make his famous quip that the “safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.” Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality (New York: The Free Press, 1979), 39. 3 Nietzsche conveniently ignores the moral character of Thucydides’ judgments. For example, Thucydides says of the Athenian general Nicias that: “of all the Greeks in my time he was the one who least deserved such a misfortune, since he had regulated his whole life in the cultivation of virtue” (8.86). Translation from: Thucydides, On Justice, Power, and Human Nature: The Essence of Thucydides' History of the Peloponnesian War, trans. Paul Woodruff (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993). References to Thucydides are cited by book and chapter number. 1 been done to examine their [Plato and Thucydides’] relationship.”4 Writing in 2009, Simon Hornblower writes that the relation of Thucydides and “the Socratic corpus, has not been much studied since…the early part of the twentieth century.”5 While it is true that Plato does not mention Thucydides in his works, neither do any other fourth-century writers.6 And, though we remain uncertain as to both when Thucydides died and when his work was publically available, we do know that it was accepted as sufficiently authoritative for Socrates’ second most famous student, Xenophon, to begin his history (Hellenica) at 411, the point where Thucydides—in all likelihood involuntarily—breaks off mid-sentence.7 The most detailed comparison between Plato and Thucydides was done by Max Pohlenz nearly a century ago.8 Pohlenz highlights connections between Plato’s analysis of democracy in the Republic and Pericles’ Funeral Oration.9 Leo Strauss mentions, but does not thoroughly analyze, the similarity between Plato and Thucydides’ accounts of early history in Book III of the Laws and the beginning chapters of the History.10 However, as many commentators have observed in passing, there are many themes to 4 R. B. Rutherford, The Art of Plato: Ten Essays in Platonic Interpretation (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995), 66. 5 Simon Hornblower, "Intellectual Affinities," in Thucydides, ed. Jeffrey S. Rusten (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 63. 6 This very peculiar fact has yet to be adequately explained. 7 Thucydides certainly survived the end of the war (2.65), but we have no evidence that requires a date later than this. 8 Max Pohlenz, Aus Platos Werdezeit (Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1913). 9 Pohlenz also connects Pericles’ address with the Menexenus. In the past thirty years, the Menexenus is the only work that has generated much research on the relationship between the two thinkers. Stephen G. Salkever, "Socrates' Aspasian Oration: The Play of Philosophy and Politics in Plato's Menexenus," The American Political Science Review 87, no. 1 (1993). S. Sara Monoson, "Remembering Pericles: The Political and Theoretical Import of Plato's Menexenus," Political Theory 26, no. 4 (1998). 10 Leo Strauss, The City and Man (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), 237. As many have noticed, Thucydides’ work bears no official title and Thucydides himself never refers to his work as a history. Even if he did, in Greek the word history (historia) means “investigation” or “inquiry.” However, I follow standard convention and will refer to his work as the History.
Recommended publications
  • Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT PLATO Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT Series editors R AYMOND GEUSS Professor in Philosophy, University of Cambridge Q UENTIN SKINNER Professor of the Humanities, Queen Mary, University of London Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought is now firmly estab- lished as the major student textbook series in political theory. It aims to make available to students all the most important texts in the history of western political thought, from ancient Greece to the early twentieth century. All the familiar classic texts will be included, but the series seeks at the same time to enlarge the conventional canon by incorporating an extensive range of less well-known works, many of them never before available in a modern English edition. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each vol- ume contains a critical introduction together with chronologies, biographical sketches, a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and text- ual apparatus. When completed the series will aim to offer an outline
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: the Parent Analogy in Plato's Menexenus
    Dialogue http://journals.cambridge.org/DIA Additional services for Dialogue: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: The Parent Analogy in Plato's Menexenus Sandrine Berges Dialogue / Volume 46 / Issue 02 / March 2007, pp 211 - 230 DOI: 10.1017/S0012217300001724, Published online: 27 April 2009 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0012217300001724 How to cite this article: Sandrine Berges (2007). Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: The Parent Analogy in Plato's Menexenus. Dialogue, 46, pp 211-230 doi:10.1017/S0012217300001724 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/DIA, IP address: 139.179.91.52 on 03 Dec 2015 Articles Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: The Parent Analogy in Plato’s Menexenus SANDRINE BERGES Bilkent University ABSTRACT: Can virtue ethics say anything worthwhile about laws? What would a virtue-ethical account of good laws look like? I argue that a plausible answer to that question can be found in Plato’s parent analogies in the Crito and the Menexenus. I go on to show that the Menexenus gives us a philosophical argument to the effect that laws are just only if they enable citizens to flourish. I then argue that the result- ing virtue-ethical account of just laws is not viciously paternalistic. Finally, I refute the objection that the virtue-ethical account I am proposing is not distinct from a consequentialist account. RÉSUMÉ : Peut-on construire une théorie de la loi à partir de l’éthique de la vertu? Qu’est ce qu’une bonne loi?Je dis que l’on trouvera une réponse à la question dans l’analogie entre les lois et les parents présentée par Platon dans le Criton et le Ménéxène.
    [Show full text]
  • Citations in Classics and Ancient History
    Citations in Classics and Ancient History The most common style in use in the field of Classical Studies is the author-date style, also known as Chicago 2, but MLA is also quite common and perfectly acceptable. Quick guides for each of MLA and Chicago 2 are readily available as PDF downloads. The Chicago Manual of Style Online offers a guide on their web-page: http://www.chicagomanualofstyle.org/tools_citationguide.html The Modern Language Association (MLA) does not, but many educational institutions post an MLA guide for free access. While a specific citation style should be followed carefully, none take into account the specific practices of Classical Studies. They are all (Chicago, MLA and others) perfectly suitable for citing most resources, but should not be followed for citing ancient Greek and Latin primary source material, including primary sources in translation. Citing Primary Sources: Every ancient text has its own unique system for locating content by numbers. For example, Homer's Iliad is divided into 24 Books (what we might now call chapters) and the lines of each Book are numbered from line 1. Herodotus' Histories is divided into nine Books and each of these Books is divided into Chapters and each chapter into line numbers. The purpose of such a system is that the Iliad, or any primary source, can be cited in any language and from any publication and always refer to the same passage. That is why we do not cite Herodotus page 66. Page 66 in what publication, in what edition? Very early in your textbook, Apodexis Historia, a passage from Herodotus is reproduced.
    [Show full text]
  • FALL 2008 Columbia University in the City of New York Co
    FALL 2008 Columbia University in the City of New York CO 435 West 116th Street, Box A-2 L UM New York, NY 10027 BI A L RETURN SERVICE REQUESTED A W S C HO O L M ag azine www.law.columbia.edu/alumni fall 2008 BREAKING THE CODE NEW FACULTY MEMBER MICHAEL GRAETZ HAS AN INNOVATIVE PLAN FOR REVAMPING AMERICA’s TAX CODE TALKINGTALKING TETELECLECOM: TIM WU CHATS WITH JEFFREY TOOBIN SCOTUS ANALYSIS FROM BLASI, BRIFFAULT, GREENAWALT, HAMBURGER, AND PERSILY Opportunity The Future of Diversity and Opportunity in Higher dean Columbia Law School Magazine David M. Schizer is published three times annually for alumni and friends of associate dean Education: A National Columbia Law School by the for development and Office of Development and alumni relations Alumni Relations. Forum on Innovation and Bruno M. Santonocito Opinions expressed in Columbia Law Collaboration executive director School Magazine do not necessarily of communications reflect the views of Columbia Law and public affairs School or Columbia University. Elizabeth Schmalz This magazine is printed December 3-5, 2008 guest editor on FSC certified paper. Matthew J.X. Malady editorial director James Vescovi assistant editor Mary Johnson Change of address information should be sent to: copy editors Lauren Pavlakovich, Columbia Law School Joy Y. Wang 435 West 116 Street, Box A-2 New York, NY 10027 During the first week in December, design and art direction Attn: Office of Alumni Relations Empire Design Studio Alumni Office university presidents, provosts, and photography 212-854-2680 Peter Freed, Robyn Twomey, Magazine Notices Eric van den Brulle, Jon Roemer 212-854-2650 academic innovators will gather for David Yellen [email protected] an historic conference focused on new printing Copyright 2008, Columbia Maar Printing Service, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • DEMOCRITUS Democritus
    CHAPTER FOUR DEMOCRITUS Democritus (c. 460-396 B.C.) was a younger contemporary ofProtagoras; both were born in Abdera. 1 Although he had encyclopedic interests and was the author of many works, the 298 fragments ascribed to him in Diels-Kranz are at most all that has survived of his writings? Almost all of these fragments concern ethical matters. But despite this, Democritus has generally not been known for his moral theory. He has always, and rightly, been considered an important figure in the history of natural philosophy for his theory of atomism. Commentators on the ethical fragments have often found them to be of little or no philosophical importance3 and have sometimes questioned their authenticity. The issue of whether these fragments are authentic is not important in the context of the present study, which is only interested in these fragments insofar as they re­ present the views of an early Greek moral theorist concerned with the issue of the compatibility of self-interest and morality. Thus, it would make little difference here whether the fragments be attributed to Democritus or one of his contemporar­ ies, although my own view is that they probably should be assigned to Democri­ tus.4 On the other hand, it is a crucial question in the present context whether the fragments have philosophical importance. It is true, of course, that the ethical fragments are written in a style closer to the philosophically unrigorous fragments of Antiphon's On Concord than to those from On Truth. But it cannot be concluded from this fact that they are trivial.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Remembering Music in Early Greece
    REMEMBERING MUSIC IN EARLY GREECE JOHN C. FRANKLIN This paper contemplates various ways that the ancient Greeks preserved information about their musical past. Emphasis is given to the earlier periods and the transition from oral/aural tradition, when self-reflective professional poetry was the primary means of remembering music, to literacy, when festival inscriptions and written poetry could first capture information in at least roughly datable contexts. But the continuing interplay of the oral/aural and written modes during the Archaic and Classical periods also had an impact on the historical record, which from ca. 400 onwards is represented by historiographical fragments. The sources, methods, and motives of these early treatises are also examined, with special attention to Hellanicus of Lesbos and Glaucus of Rhegion. The essay concludes with a few brief comments on Peripatetic historiography and a selective catalogue of music-historiographical titles from the fifth and fourth centuries. INTRODUCTION Greek authors often refer to earlier music.1 Sometimes these details are of first importance for the modern historiography of ancient 1 Editions and translations of classical authors may be found by consulting the article for each in The Oxford Classical Dictionary3. Journal 1 2 JOHN C. FRANKLIN Greek music. Uniquely valuable, for instance, is Herodotus’ allusion to an Argive musical efflorescence in the late sixth century,2 nowhere else explicitly attested (3.131–2). In other cases we learn less about real musical history than an author’s own biases and predilections. Thus Plato describes Egypt as a never-never- land where no innovation was ever permitted in music; it is hard to know whether Plato fabricated this statement out of nothing to support his conservative and ideal society, or is drawing, towards the same end, upon a more widely held impression—obviously superficial—of a foreign, distant culture (Laws 656e–657f).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Foreigners As Liberators: Education and Cultural Diversity in Plato's
    1 Foreigners as Liberators: Education and Cultural Diversity in Plato’s Menexenus Rebecca LeMoine Assistant Professor of Political Science Florida Atlantic University NOTE: Use of this document is for private research and study only; the document may not be distributed further. The final manuscript has been accepted for publication and will appear in a revised form in The American Political Science Review 111.3 (August 2017). It is available for a FirstView online here: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055417000016 Abstract: Though recent scholarship challenges the traditional interpretation of Plato as anti- democratic, his antipathy to cultural diversity is still generally assumed. The Menexenus appears to offer some of the most striking evidence of Platonic xenophobia, as it features Socrates delivering a mock funeral oration that glorifies Athens’ exclusion of foreigners. Yet when readers play along with Socrates’ exhortation to imagine the oration through the voice of its alleged author Aspasia, Pericles’ foreign mistress, the oration becomes ironic or dissonant. Through this, Plato shows that foreigners can act as gadflies, liberating citizens from the intellectual hubris that occasions democracy’s fall into tyranny. In reminding readers of Socrates’ death, the dialogue warns, however, that fear of education may prevent democratic citizens from appreciating the role of cultural diversity in cultivating the virtue of Socratic wisdom. Keywords: Menexenus; Aspasia; cultural diversity; Socratic wisdom; Platonic irony Acknowledgments: An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 2012 annual meeting of the Association for Political Theory, where it benefitted greatly from Susan Bickford’s insightful commentary. Thanks to Ethan Alexander-Davey, Andreas Avgousti, Richard Avramenko, Brendan Irons, Daniel Kapust, Michelle Schwarze, the APSR editorial team (both present and former), and four anonymous referees for their invaluable feedback on earlier drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • Chthonic Restitutions: Madness and Oblivion
    Chthonic Restitutions: Madness and Oblivion Javier Berzal de Dios Abstract This essay theorizes madness as a chthonic emplacement to dishevel existentially insufcient and detached interpretations of disorder. Refecting on Nietzsche’s emphasis on poetry over systematic thought, I take up Lorca and Baudelaire’s visceral language on death and the earthly to revisit chthonic myths as expressing an underworld uncontrollable sphere beyond systematicity. Written from the phenomenologically precarious position of my own mental illness, this essay develops a sincere rhetoric to approach the chthonic from within rather than at sterilized distance. This positioning retains the indexicality of the intense and disorganized as a critical facet, in turn exploring the nuances of the experience without discursive reductions or romantic musings, from the ground down. Cassandra: ototototoi popoi da. – Aeschylus, Agamemnon 1072 Following the social turn of the 1960s, administrators and teachers of academic discourse began to replace “reason” and “rationality” with “critically,” or “critical thinking,” as their highest aim; however, the presumption of a rational subject remained stable. – Margaret Price, Mad at School 39 Am I mad now? In truth, the question of madness calls forth to a future memory: will I have been mad? Or really: how mad will I think I had been? Lucidity is anachronistic, an ex post facto verdict, casting out to madness what thought itself on mark… Madness itself voices the lan- guage of truth—this madness of mine—an eternally rational utterance, charts and graphs at hand. I picture philosophers terribly sane, so much they take for granted, so restrained and hygienic their connections… so reliable a language.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Socrates, Lysis, and Menexenus in Plato's
    FILOZOFIA Roč. 75, 2020, č. 3 DOI: https://doi.org/10.31577/filozofia.2020.75.3. 3 THE ROLE OF SOCRATES, LYSIS, AND MENEXENUS IN PLATO’S LYSIS GABRIEL EVANGELOU, University of Cyprus, Department of Classics and Philosophy, Nicosia, Cyprus EVANGELOU, G.: The Role of Socrates, Lysis, and Menexenus in Plato’s Lysis FILOZOFIA, 75, 2020, No 3, pp. 195 – 211 The aim of this study is to demonstrate that the value of the Lysis does not lie in Socrates’ puzzling treatment of φίλος and φιλία, but rather in the unique role that both Socrates and the other two main interlocutors, Lysis and Menexenus, assume in this Platonic dialogue. In the Lysis, Socrates plays the role of the so- phist who uses errant logic, but with whom the young men are so infatuated that they simply agree with his every statement. Their inability to display critical thinking by challenging his flawed arguments constantly forces Socrates to re- vert to the role of the philosopher who refutes the points that he, himself, had just raised. The dialogue thus functions as a warning against blindly trusting the education of youths to sophists and potentially as an exercise for Plato’s students to detect problematic argumentation and to practise arguing against it. Keywords: Plato – Socrates – Lysis – Philia – Sophists – Aporia – Deception The perplexity of the Lysis has been a topic of considerable debate. Throughout the dialogue, the reader is given the impression that Socrates is attempting to provide a definition of ‘φίλος’1 by asking the two teenagers, Lysis and Menexenus, a series of questions.2 Nevertheless, before reaching a conclusion, their philosophical discussion 1 The scope of the Lysis has been heavily contested.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic Love in a Colorado Courtroom: Martha Nussbaum, John Finnis, and Plato's Laws in Evans V
    Articles Platonic Love in a Colorado Courtroom: Martha Nussbaum, John Finnis, and Plato's Laws in Evans v. Romer Randall Baldwin Clark* I. RELEVANT FOR FIFTEEN MINUTES-OR THIRTY CENTURIES? To the ridicule of the highbrow popular press' and the surprise of classical scholars,2 Plato's Laws,3 a work which was mocked, even in * University of Virginia School of Law, Class of 2002. Ph.D., University of Chicago, 1998. Research Associate, Dartmouth College Department of Government, 1997-99. Author, THE LAW MOST BEAUTIFUL AND BEST: MEDICAL ARGUMENT AND MAGICAL RHETORIC IN PLATO'S LAWS (Rowman & Littlefield - Lexington Books, forthcoming 2001). This article has benefited from the comments of many friends, colleagues, and teachers. For their assistance, I would like to thank Danielle Allen, Larry Arnhart, Richard 0. Brooks, Robert A. Burt, Allison D. Clark, Andrew P. Clark, Elizabeth A. Clark, Glenn W. Clark, Matthew Crawford, Richard Dougherty, Martha A. Field, Shawntel R. Fugate, Martin P. Golding, L. Kent Greenawalt, A.E. Dick Howard, Leon R. Kass, Matthew Kutcher, Melissa S. Lane, Mark J. Lutz, Roger D. Masters, Lynn Mather, Angelia K. Means, Ted H. Miller, S. Sarah Monoson, David Peritz, Richard A. Posner, Christopher Rohrbacher, Ariel C. Silver, Nathan Tarcov, Bradley A. Thayer, Elizabeth E. Theran, Paul Ulrich, Eduardo A. Velasquez, Lloyd L. Weinreb, Martin D. Yaffe, and the members of my edit team at the Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities. I only regret that I was unable to address all of their criticisms. Particularly profound appreciation is owed to my friend and colleague, James B. Murphy, whose queries helped me conceive this work and whose encouragement brought it to light: aneu gar phil6n oudeis heloit' an zen.
    [Show full text]
  • Clitophon and Socrates in the Platonic Clitophon
    Ancient Philosophy 32 (2012) ©Mathesis Publications 1 Clitophon and Socrates in the Platonic Clitophon Christopher Moore The Clitophon shows us a man similar to Socrates in analytic skill, social ease, frankness, and avowed interest in justice. He praises Socrates for bringing people to desire to be just, but criticizes Socrates for not helping them be just, the object of their desire. H gives his experience as an example: having listened to Socrates he desires justice, but does not know how to be just. Readers have often accepted both the cogency of and warrant for Clitophon’s criticism. But details of the dia - logue undermine both. Its characterization of Socrates shows that desiring to be just, considered robustly—recognizing one’s ignorance, listening to other views, and trying to learn about the good—is much the same as being just, and so Socrates cannot be faulted for merely inculcating the desire. And though Cli - tophon has heard Scorates speak and is interested in justice—especially in find - ing some apt formula—he has not listened closely to Socrates, and therefore has not allowed himself to be brought fully into desiring to be just. Therefore, he fails, both theoretically and personally, to understand Socrates’ efforts, and so his criticism fails too. The dialogue begins with Socrates reporting a rumor. He heard that Clitophon disparaged their time together but raved about his time with Thrasymachus. Cli - tophon calls this rumor mistaken. Far from disparaging their time together, Cli - tophon says, he lauded much about Socrates. He asks leave to speak frankly. He wants to give a fuller report about what he actually said to Lysias, the source of the rumor.
    [Show full text]