Ucin1275915747.Pdf (2.08

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ucin1275915747.Pdf (2.08 UNIVERSITY OF CINCINNATI Date: 11-May-2010 I, Carrie Galsworthy , hereby submit this original work as part of the requirements for the degree of: Doctor of Philosophy in Classics It is entitled: Language and Intent in Empedocles' Cosmic Cycle Student Signature: Carrie Galsworthy This work and its defense approved by: Committee Chair: Holt Parker, PhD Holt Parker, PhD William Johnson, PhD William Johnson, PhD Susan Prince, PhD Susan Prince, PhD 5/28/2010 621 Language and Intent in Empedocles’ Cosmic Cycle A dissertation submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Cincinnati in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Classics of the College of Arts and Sciences by Carrie Galsworthy B.A. (Honours) The University of Western Ontario (Canada), 1994 M.A. The University of Western Ontario (Canada), 1996 May 2010 Abstract In this dissertation, I analyze how Empedocles uses language to present himself and his intent. Although Empedocles’ contemporaries and more modern readers present him as a scientist or magician, he portrays himself as a god and claims that he will teach others to become a god like him in order to manipulate the universe. In Chapter One, I examine the concept of science from an Aristotelian bias and from the standpoint of modern expectations of science to show that, despite verses that describe how the world works, Empedocles does not follow the patterns of active conversation with other thinkers that are available. His stated intent (fragment 111) is to teach others how to control the universe – cure disease and old age, affect the weather, and raise the dead – rather than learn about it theoretically. In Chapter Two, I will show that although the claims that he makes link him to magicians, he does not present himself as one. Magicians act as intermediaries between men and the gods (at least in the time contemporary with Empedocles); the gods do as the magicians ask them because the magicians have built up a successful relationship through sacrifices and incantations. Empedocles, on the other hand, accomplishes these feats on his own as a god. Chapter Three sets out what sort of god Empedocles is: he is a mortal, long-lived god in contrast with the immortal gods – Love, Strife, and the four roots (fire, water, air, and earth). Anyone can become a god, as I illustrate, as long as one is pure enough and wise enough. Chapter Four returns to Empedocles’ use of language to express his intent. Since controlling the world can be a dangerous lesson, Empedocles uses ambiguity and the model of initiation into a mystery intentionally to conceal the lessons from hoi polloi. The audience must decode Empedocles’ message before they can make further observations of the world on their way to meeting their goal. Following the model for initiation, the readers will come to the ultimate revelation on their own. Finally, Chapter Five focuses on what can be determined from Empedocles verses: the readers must learn how to emulate the actions of Love and Strife since they are the active agents of change in the world. By learning about how the world works from Empedocles’ verses and their own observation, his students, as gods themselves, will also influence the fabric of the universe to achieve whatever they wish. ii iii Acknowledgements A project this big is not done without support. My committee has been invaluable as I developed my own ideas and got my researcher’s legs under me. Holt Parker handled my questions with grace; William Johnson asked piercing questions of me and my text; Susan Prince provided much insight into where this project can go next. My greatest thanks go to Ann Michelini who started this project with me as I grappled with the material; this project would not be what it has become without her asking that I push myself and my ideas further. For research support, the staff of the John Miller Burnham Classical Library – Jacquie, Mike, David, and Jean – manage the best collection and have all been helpful personally. I have benefited from the generous financial support of the Classics Department with the Semple Fellowship, teaching assignments, and a summer term with the American School of Classical Studies at Athens. All the faculty have been supportive in and out of the classroom, contributing to my development as a scholar and a teacher. A doctoral fellowship from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRCC) has also assisted me in accomplishing my goals. My friends have contributed to the successful completion of this project. The members of the Dissertation Discussion Group over the years – Carol Hershenson, Kathleen Quinn, Julie Hruby, Shari Stocker, Joanne Murphy, Jim Newhard, Susan Wise, Anne Feltovich, and Allison Sterrett-Krause – have listened to my problems, helped me to solve them, and reminded me just how important friendship is. The same goes for other friends and colleagues who are too numerous to name – in the academic sphere and out – who have lightened the load with stories and laughter in the tearoom, in the classroom, and in the “real” world. I need especially to thank my colleagues at Miami University who have become my friends – Judith de Luce, Deborah Lyons, Denise McCoskey, Steve Nimis, Peter Rose, Zara Torlone, and Steve Tuck. Finally, I thank my family for their unwavering belief that I could do anything – my grandparents, my parents, Ken and Nancy, who helped in so many ways that it would take forever to list just a few, and my little boy, Nick, who tells me I’m awesome (until I say that we can’t have chocolate for supper). Who rocks, baby? That’s right, we do. iv Table of Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements iv Introduction 1 Chapter 1 – Empedocles the Scientist 7 Part 1: Looking for Reasons Why 11 1.1 Aristotle Judges the Presocratics 12 1.2 Modern Scholars on the Presocratics 16 1.3 Empedocles as Presocratic Scientist 18 Part 2: Communicating with Others 23 2.1 Competition and Debate 24 2.1.1 Presocratics Respond to Divine Explanations 29 2.1.2 Presocratics Respond to Other Presocratics 33 2.2 Empedocles’ Lessons 38 2.2.1 Empedocles’ Criticism – Fragment 2 39 2.2.2 Empedocles’ Criticism – Fragment 39 42 2.2.3 A Different Focus 46 2.3 Clarity and Persuasion 49 2.3.1 Aristotle on “Uncommon” Language and Science 54 2.4 Empedocles’ Intent 59 Chapter 2 – Empedocles the Magician 64 Part 1: Why Magic? 65 1.1 Atoning for Wrongs 69 1.1.1 Repercussions for Unavenged Murder 73 1.1.2 Helping the Souls of the Dead 79 1.2 Bewitching People 81 1.3 Curing Disease 84 1.4 Affecting the Environment 88 v Part 2: Was Empedocles a Magician? 91 2.1 Empedocles’ Claims against Magicians’ Claims 92 2.1.1 Atoning for Wrongs 93 2.1.2 Bewitching People 94 2.1.3 Curing Disease 95 2.1.4 Affecting Weather 96 2.2 Empedocles’ Presentation and Others’ Perceptions 97 Chapter 3 – Empedocles the God 105 Part 1: What are the Gods? 106 1.1 Unchanging and Immortal 107 1.1.1 The Roots 108 1.1.2 Love and Strife 112 1.2 Empedocles’ Mortal Gods 116 1.2.1 Empedocles’ model for the long-lived gods 117 1.2.2 The Composition of the Sphere 119 Part 2: Becoming a god 123 2.1 Transmigration 126 2.1.1 The daimones 128 2.1.2 The Necessity of Transmigration 132 2.2 Escaping the Cycle? 133 2.2.1 Being Pure 134 2.2.2 Being Wise 136 Chapter 4 – Empedocles’ Mystery 141 Part 1: Ambiguity 141 1.1 A Tradition of Ambiguity 143 1.1.1 Oracles and Ambiguous Language 144 1.1.2 Allegory and Mystery Relgion 146 1.2 Empedocles’ Ambiguity 153 1.2.1 Not a Tell-All 154 1.2.2 A Desire to Obscure 158 1.3 Empedocles’ Secret 163 Part 2: Empedocles’ Initiation 169 2.1 The Journey of Initiation 172 vi 2.1.1 Fragment 110 173 2.2 The παράδοσις in Empedocles’ Text 176 2.2.1 Fragment 6 – An Example 178 2.3 The Rest of the Journey – The ἐποπτεῖα 185 2.3.1 Sensation 187 2.3.2 Thinking 191 Chapter 5 – The Revelation 198 Part 1: The Nature of the Cosmic Cycle 199 1.1 Repetition in the Cycle 208 1.1.1 Fragment 17 209 1.1.2 Fragment 26 211 1.2 The Necessity of the Cycle 214 Part 2: How the Cosmic Cycle Operates 215 2.1 The Roots 217 2.1.1 How the Root Parts Fit Together 220 2.1.2 The Attraction of Like to Like 223 2.2 Love 226 2.2.1 Love Combines Unlike Things 227 2.2.2 The One 232 2.3 Strife 239 2.3.1 Strife Separates Unlike Things 240 2.3.2 Strife’s Ultimate Goal – The Many 243 Conclusion 254 Works Cited 256 vii Introduction Empedocles is an enigmatic figure. On the one hand, his efforts to explain how the world works link him with contemporaries, whom Aristotle calls natural philosophers (φυσικοί or φυσιολόγοι). On the other hand, he also writes about the nature of the soul and claims further that he could manipulate the world at his whim. Empedocles, however, does not present himself as a man who outlines how the world works for its own sake, nor does he present himself as a magician. Empedocles claims to be a god and his intent is to teach others how they, too, can become gods and control the universe.
Recommended publications
  • Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility John Robinson Windham College
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by The Open Repository @Binghamton (The ORB) Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The ocS iety for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-28-1953 Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility John Robinson Windham College Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Recommended Citation Robinson, John, "Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility" (1953). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 263. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/263 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. JOHN ROBINSON Windham College Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth’s Immobility* N the course of his review of the reasons given by his predecessors for the earth’s immobility, Aristotle states that “some” attribute it I neither to the action of the whirl nor to the air beneath’s hindering its falling : These are the causes with which most thinkers busy themselves. But there are some who say, like Anaximander among the ancients, that it stays where it is because of its “indifference” (όμοιότητα). For what is stationed at the center, and is equably related to the extremes, has no reason to go one way rather than another—either up or down or sideways.
    [Show full text]
  • Information to Users
    INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. Each original is also photographed in one exposure and is included in reduced form at the back of the book. Photographs included in the original manuscript have been reproduced xerographically in this copy. Higher quality 6" x 9" black and white photographic prints are available for any photographs or illustrations appearing in this copy for an additional charge. Contact UMI directly to order. University M crct. rrs it'terrjt onai A Be" 4 Howe1 ir”?r'"a! Cor"ear-, J00 Norte CeeD Road App Artjor mi 4 6 ‘Og ' 346 USA 3 13 761-4’00 600 sC -0600 Order Number 9238197 Selected literary letters of Sophia Peabody Hawthorne, 1842-1853 Hurst, Nancy Luanne Jenkins, Ph.D.
    [Show full text]
  • No. 40. the System of Lunar Craters, Quadrant Ii Alice P
    NO. 40. THE SYSTEM OF LUNAR CRATERS, QUADRANT II by D. W. G. ARTHUR, ALICE P. AGNIERAY, RUTH A. HORVATH ,tl l C.A. WOOD AND C. R. CHAPMAN \_9 (_ /_) March 14, 1964 ABSTRACT The designation, diameter, position, central-peak information, and state of completeness arc listed for each discernible crater in the second lunar quadrant with a diameter exceeding 3.5 km. The catalog contains more than 2,000 items and is illustrated by a map in 11 sections. his Communication is the second part of The However, since we also have suppressed many Greek System of Lunar Craters, which is a catalog in letters used by these authorities, there was need for four parts of all craters recognizable with reasonable some care in the incorporation of new letters to certainty on photographs and having diameters avoid confusion. Accordingly, the Greek letters greater than 3.5 kilometers. Thus it is a continua- added by us are always different from those that tion of Comm. LPL No. 30 of September 1963. The have been suppressed. Observers who wish may use format is the same except for some minor changes the omitted symbols of Blagg and Miiller without to improve clarity and legibility. The information in fear of ambiguity. the text of Comm. LPL No. 30 therefore applies to The photographic coverage of the second quad- this Communication also. rant is by no means uniform in quality, and certain Some of the minor changes mentioned above phases are not well represented. Thus for small cra- have been introduced because of the particular ters in certain longitudes there are no good determi- nature of the second lunar quadrant, most of which nations of the diameters, and our values are little is covered by the dark areas Mare Imbrium and better than rough estimates.
    [Show full text]
  • Glossary Glossary
    Glossary Glossary Albedo A measure of an object’s reflectivity. A pure white reflecting surface has an albedo of 1.0 (100%). A pitch-black, nonreflecting surface has an albedo of 0.0. The Moon is a fairly dark object with a combined albedo of 0.07 (reflecting 7% of the sunlight that falls upon it). The albedo range of the lunar maria is between 0.05 and 0.08. The brighter highlands have an albedo range from 0.09 to 0.15. Anorthosite Rocks rich in the mineral feldspar, making up much of the Moon’s bright highland regions. Aperture The diameter of a telescope’s objective lens or primary mirror. Apogee The point in the Moon’s orbit where it is furthest from the Earth. At apogee, the Moon can reach a maximum distance of 406,700 km from the Earth. Apollo The manned lunar program of the United States. Between July 1969 and December 1972, six Apollo missions landed on the Moon, allowing a total of 12 astronauts to explore its surface. Asteroid A minor planet. A large solid body of rock in orbit around the Sun. Banded crater A crater that displays dusky linear tracts on its inner walls and/or floor. 250 Basalt A dark, fine-grained volcanic rock, low in silicon, with a low viscosity. Basaltic material fills many of the Moon’s major basins, especially on the near side. Glossary Basin A very large circular impact structure (usually comprising multiple concentric rings) that usually displays some degree of flooding with lava. The largest and most conspicuous lava- flooded basins on the Moon are found on the near side, and most are filled to their outer edges with mare basalts.
    [Show full text]
  • Feature of the Month – January 2016 Galilaei
    A PUBLICATION OF THE LUNAR SECTION OF THE A.L.P.O. EDITED BY: Wayne Bailey [email protected] 17 Autumn Lane, Sewell, NJ 08080 RECENT BACK ISSUES: http://moon.scopesandscapes.com/tlo_back.html FEATURE OF THE MONTH – JANUARY 2016 GALILAEI Sketch and text by Robert H. Hays, Jr. - Worth, Illinois, USA October 26, 2015 03:32-03:58 UT, 15 cm refl, 170x, seeing 8-9/10 I sketched this crater and vicinity on the evening of Oct. 25/26, 2015 after the moon hid ZC 109. This was about 32 hours before full. Galilaei is a modest but very crisp crater in far western Oceanus Procellarum. It appears very symmetrical, but there is a faint strip of shadow protruding from its southern end. Galilaei A is the very similar but smaller crater north of Galilaei. The bright spot to the south is labeled Galilaei D on the Lunar Quadrant map. A tiny bit of shadow was glimpsed in this spot indicating a craterlet. Two more moderately bright spots are east of Galilaei. The western one of this pair showed a bit of shadow, much like Galilaei D, but the other one did not. Galilaei B is the shadow-filled crater to the west. This shadowing gave this crater a ring shape. This ring was thicker on its west side. Galilaei H is the small pit just west of B. A wide, low ridge extends to the southwest from Galilaei B, and a crisper peak is south of H. Galilaei B must be more recent than its attendant ridge since the crater's exterior shadow falls upon the ridge.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cosmic System of the Pre-Socratic Philosopher Anaximenes and Stars
    The cosmic system of the pre-Socratic philosopher Anaximenes and stars and their formation Konstantinos Kalachanis1, Evangelia Panou1, Efstratios Theodossiou1, Ioannis Kostikas1, Vassilios N. Manimanis1, Milan S. Dimitrijevi´c2,3 1 National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, School of Physics, Department of Astrophysics, Astronomy and Mechanics, Panepistimiopolis, Zographos 15784, Athens, Greece 2 Astronomical Observatory, Volgina 7, 11060 Belgrade, Serbia 3 IHIS Technoexperts, Beˇzanijska 23, 11080 Zemun, Serbia [email protected], [email protected], [email protected], [email protected], [email protected], [email protected] (Submitted on 03.12.2014; Accepted on 19.04.2015) Abstract. In the paper is presented Anaximenes theory of air as the initial cause of na- ture which is transcendental. We examine Anaximenes account on the formation of Earth and stars, which is based on the accumulations and ”thinning” of the primal substance, and discuss some similar characteristics with the scientific theory of star formation, while the philosopher’s reference to the fiery nature of stars reflects the theories of energy production in their interior. Key words: History of Astronomy, Anaximenes, Star formation Introduction The pre-Socratic period of Greek philosophy was undoubtedly the first ma- jor landmark in the history of philosophy and science; then for the first time the human intellect attempted to explain natural phenomena based on the relation between cause and effect. Pioneers in this attempt were the philosophers of Miletus, Thales, Anaximander and Anaximenes, who, in their effort to explain the origins of the world, expressed interesting as- tronomical views, which sometimes have similarities with results of modern science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Presocratic Philosophers 240
    XV The Ionian Revival (a) A few depressing facts If the Eleatics are right, scientists may as well give up their activities: a priori ratiocination reveals that the phenomena which science attempts to understand and explain are figments of our deceptive senses; the scientist has little or nothing to investigate—let him turn to poetry or to gardening. Fortunately few Greeks reasoned in that way; and some of the brightest gems of Greek philosophical science were polished in the generation after Parmenides. Empedocles, Anaxagoras, Philolaus, Leucippus, Democritus, Diogenes of Apollonia, all pursued the old Ionian ideal of historia despite the pressure of the Eleatic logos. And these neo-Ionian systems contain much of interest and much of permanent influence. How far they were genuine answers to the Eleatic metaphysics, and how far they were obstinate attempts to follow an out-moded profession, are questions which I shall later discuss. First, I shall offer a brief and preliminary survey of the main neo-Ionian systems which will, I hope, indicate the connexions between these men and their early models, show the respects in which their new systems must lead to conflict with Elea, and uncover the novelties of thought and argument by which they hoped to win that conflict. This section, however, will concern itself primarily with a few issues of chronology. I begin with Anaxagoras: his dates are remarkably well attested, and we know he lived from 500 to 428 BC (Diogenes Laertius, II.7=59 A 1); between his birth in Clazomenae and his death in Lampsacus he enjoyed a thirty-year sojourn in Athens, during which time he is said to have ‘taught’ Pericles and Euripides (e.g., Diogenes Laertius, II.10; 12=A 1) and to have been condemned on a charge of impiety brought against him by Pericles’ political opponents (e.g., Diogenes Laertius, II.
    [Show full text]
  • Seminar in Greek Philosophy Pyrrhonian Scepticism 1
    PHILOSOPHY 210: SEMINAR IN GREEK PHILOSOPHY 1 PYRRHONIAN SCEPTICISM Monte Johnson [email protected] UCSD Fall 2014 Course Description Pyrrhonian scepticism, as represented in the works of Sextus Empiricus, presents both a culmination and critique of the whole achievement of Greek philosophy, and was a major influence on the renaissance and the scientific revolutions of the seventeenth century, and continues to influence contemporary epistemology. In this seminar, we will get a general overview of Pyrrhonian scepticism beginning with the doxographies in Book IX of Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Famous Philosophers (including Heraclitus, Xenophanes, Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, Leucippus, Democritus, Protagoras, Diogenes of Apollonia, Anaxarchus, Pyrrho, and Timon). The core part of the course will consist of a close reading and discussion of the three books of the Outlines of Pyrhhonian Scepticism by Sextus Empiricus, along with a more detailed examination of the treatment of logic, physics, and ethics in his Against the Dogmatists VII-XI. The last three weeks of the seminar will be devoted to student presentations relating Pyrrhonian scepticism to their own interests in philosophy (whether topical or historical). Goals • Learn techniques of interpreting and criticizing works of ancient philosophy in translation, including fragmentary works. • Obtain an overview of ancient scepticism, especially Pyrrhonian scepticism, its textual basis, predecessors, and influence upon later philosophy and science. • Conduct original research relating ancient skepticism to your own philosophical interests; compile an annotated bibliography and craft a substantial research paper. • Develop skills in discussing and presenting philosophical ideas and research, including producing handouts, leading discussions, and fielding questions. Evaluation 10% Participation and discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-28-1953 Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility John Robinson Windham College Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Recommended Citation Robinson, John, "Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth's Immobility" (1953). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 263. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/263 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. JOHN ROBINSON Windham College Anaximander and the Problem of the Earth’s Immobility* N the course of his review of the reasons given by his predecessors for the earth’s immobility, Aristotle states that “some” attribute it I neither to the action of the whirl nor to the air beneath’s hindering its falling : These are the causes with which most thinkers busy themselves. But there are some who say, like Anaximander among the ancients, that it stays where it is because of its “indifference” (όμοιότητα). For what is stationed at the center, and is equably related to the extremes, has no reason to go one way rather than another—either up or down or sideways. And since it is impossible for it to move simultaneously in opposite directions, it necessarily stays where it is.1 The ascription of this curious view to Anaximander appears to have occasioned little uneasiness among modern commentators.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 24, Number 04 (April 1906) Winton J
    Gardner-Webb University Digital Commons @ Gardner-Webb University The tudeE Magazine: 1883-1957 John R. Dover Memorial Library 4-1-1906 Volume 24, Number 04 (April 1906) Winton J. Baltzell Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.gardner-webb.edu/etude Part of the Composition Commons, Ethnomusicology Commons, Fine Arts Commons, History Commons, Liturgy and Worship Commons, Music Education Commons, Musicology Commons, Music Pedagogy Commons, Music Performance Commons, Music Practice Commons, and the Music Theory Commons Recommended Citation Baltzell, Winton J.. "Volume 24, Number 04 (April 1906)." , (1906). https://digitalcommons.gardner-webb.edu/etude/513 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the John R. Dover Memorial Library at Digital Commons @ Gardner-Webb University. It has been accepted for inclusion in The tudeE Magazine: 1883-1957 by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Gardner-Webb University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. APRIL, 1906 ISO PER YEAR ‘TF'TnTT^ PRICE 15 CENTS 180.5 THE ETUDE 209 MODERN SIX-HAND^ LU1T 1 I1 3 Instruction Books PIANO MUSIC “THE ETUDE” - April, 1906 Some Recent Publications Musical Life in New Orleans.. .Alice Graham 217 FOR. THE PIANOFORTE OF «OHE following ensemb Humor in Music. F.S.Law 218 IT styles, and are usi caching purposes t The American Composer. C. von Sternberg 219 CLAYTON F. SUMMY CO. _la- 1 „ net rtf th ’ standard foreign co Experiences of a Music Student in Germany in The following works for beginners at the piano are id some of the lat 1905...... Clarence V. Rawson 220 220 Wabash Avenue, Chicago.
    [Show full text]
  • Water on the Moon, III. Volatiles & Activity
    Water on The Moon, III. Volatiles & Activity Arlin Crotts (Columbia University) For centuries some scientists have argued that there is activity on the Moon (or water, as recounted in Parts I & II), while others have thought the Moon is simply a dead, inactive world. [1] The question comes in several forms: is there a detectable atmosphere? Does the surface of the Moon change? What causes interior seismic activity? From a more modern viewpoint, we now know that as much carbon monoxide as water was excavated during the LCROSS impact, as detailed in Part I, and a comparable amount of other volatiles were found. At one time the Moon outgassed prodigious amounts of water and hydrogen in volcanic fire fountains, but released similar amounts of volatile sulfur (or SO2), and presumably large amounts of carbon dioxide or monoxide, if theory is to be believed. So water on the Moon is associated with other gases. Astronomers have agreed for centuries that there is no firm evidence for “weather” on the Moon visible from Earth, and little evidence of thick atmosphere. [2] How would one detect the Moon’s atmosphere from Earth? An obvious means is atmospheric refraction. As you watch the Sun set, its image is displaced by Earth’s atmospheric refraction at the horizon from the position it would have if there were no atmosphere, by roughly 0.6 degree (a bit more than the Sun’s angular diameter). On the Moon, any atmosphere would cause an analogous effect for a star passing behind the Moon during an occultation (multiplied by two since the light travels both into and out of the lunar atmosphere).
    [Show full text]
  • A HISTORY of the PELASGIAN THEORY. FEW Peoples Of
    A HISTORY OF THE PELASGIAN THEORY. FEW peoples of the ancient world have given rise to so much controversy as the Pelasgians; and of few, after some centuries of discussion, is so little clearly established. Like the Phoenicians, the Celts, and of recent years the Teutons, they have been a peg upon which to hang all sorts of speculation ; and whenever an inconvenient circumstance has deranged the symmetry of a theory, it has been safe to ' call it Pelasgian and pass on.' One main reason for this ill-repute, into which the Pelasgian name has fallen, has been the very uncritical fashion in which the ancient statements about the Pelasgians have commonly been mishandled. It has been the custom to treat passages from Homer, from Herodotus, from Ephorus, and from Pausanias, as if they were so many interchangeable bricks to build up the speculative edifice; as if it needed no proof that genealogies found sum- marized in Pausanias or Apollodorus ' were taken by them from poems of the same class with the Theogony, or from ancient treatises, or from prevalent opinions ;' as if, further, ' if we find them mentioning the Pelasgian nation, they do at all events belong to an age when that name and people had nothing of the mystery which they bore to the eyes of the later Greeks, for instance of Strabo;' and as though (in the same passage) a statement of Stephanus of Byzantium about Pelasgians in Italy ' were evidence to the same effect, perfectly unexceptionable and as strictly historical as the case will admit of 1 No one doubts, of course, either that popular tradition may transmit, or that late writers may transcribe, statements which come from very early, and even from contemporary sources.
    [Show full text]