The Symbolic Economy of the Hanfeizi

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Symbolic Economy of the Hanfeizi The Journal of School & Society 40 ISSN 2575-9922 6(1) 40–54 ©Author(s) 2019 ual efforts to cultivate virtue as the primary so- The Symbolic Economy of lution for the state’s most significant political, economic, and military challenges, Legalist the Hanfeizi thought was arguably more congruent with the bellicose and highly competitive political cli- Brandon King mate of its time. University of Pennsylvania This exceptional suitability most famously culminated in Legalism becoming the official state ideology of the Qin dynasty (221-207 B.C.), which unified the Chinese empire for the first The term “Legalism” has been generally used time. Even after the collapse of the Qin dynas- to refer to a group of Chinese thinkers who ty, however, the legacy of Legalist thought car- achieved some prominence during the Warring ried on. Although the Han dynasty adopted States period (481-222 B.C.). This group of Confucianism as its official state ideology, it thinkers typically includes, but is not necessarily nevertheless maintained much of the Qin em- limited to, Guan Zhong,1 Li Kui, Wu Qi, Shen pire’s governing infrastructure. Perhaps more Dao, Shen Buhai, Shang Yang, Li Si, and Han importantly was the ongoing legacy of structur- Fei. These figures and their contributions to al competition, along with a merit-based hierar- statecraft represented an opposing political vi- chical ranking system meant to reflect the re- sion from other competing schools of thought sults of this competition, being used as a meth- at the time—schools such as Confucianism, od of organizing the empire—a legacy that last- Mohism, and Daoism. ed throughout imperial Chinese history. My use of the term “Legalism,” however, is In this paper however, I will focus on Le- different. I use it to refer to a group of extant galist thought as revealed in the Hanfeizi texts that possess distinctly shared characteris- (HFZ)3—a text traditionally attributed to Legal- tics. More specifically, I use the term to refer to ist founder, “Master Han Fei.”4 In particular, the political visions expressed in Book of Lord much of the analysis in this piece comes from Shang, the “Shen Buhai fragments,” the “Shen the “Outer Compendium of Explanations, Dao fragments,” the Han Feizi, and even select 2 chapters in the Guanzi. 3 OCELL 33 uses Confucians (Ru ) and their behav- Regardless of how the term is used, the re- ioral rituals to illustrate a unique aspect of the HFZ’s markable success of the political philosophy political vision: a pedagogical mission. For a deeper dis- associated with it is impossible to ignore. cussion of the pedagogical quality of the Legalist political Known especially for its harsh criticisms of ear- vision, see: Brandon King, “The [Not So] Hidden Cur- riculum of the Legalist State in the Book of Lord Shang ly Confucian thought that championed individ- and the Han-Fei-Zi,” Comparative Philosophy 9, no. 2 (2018): 69-92. 4 The authorship of OCELL has been a subject of de- 1 It is important to note that Guan Zhong is the only bate, but the possibility of Han Fei’s authorship has not figure that is thought to have lived during the Spring and been ruled out. In fact, Lundahl saw enough justification Autumn period (770-482 B.C.). to consider the inner and outer “Compendium of Expla- 2 A longer discussion of the textual core, or distinctly nations” chapters “authentic.” See: Bertil Lundahl. Han shared characteristics, of Legalist texts can be found in Fei Zi: The Man and the Work.(Stockholm: Institute of Brandon King, Adapting with the Times: Fajia Law and State Oriental Languages, Stockholm University, 1992), 146- Development (Dissertation, Chinese University of Hong 153. Kong, 2015). The Journal of School & Society 41 ISSN 2575-9922 6(1) 40–54 ©Author(s) 2019 Lower Left” (OCELL),1 which is a subdivision and disadvantages of their promoted statecraft, within a larger unit of chapters in the Hanfeizi approaching Legalist governance as pedagogy (HFZ). Each subdivision begins with assertions requires more exploration of the shared experi- and advice about governance, followed by sto- ence of state subjects. Grounding itself on the ries or excerpts meant to illustrate them. distinctly shared conception of law found in Throughout, I will explore how rewards and Legalist texts, this methodology concentrates its state organization accomplish a state objective attention on rewards and what their associated beyond coordinating the interests of the ruler state institutions communicate to the populace. and his subjects.5 So, while there is an appreciation for the im- Typically, examinations of pedagogy are re- portance of punishment and its deterring ef- served for texts associated with the Confucian fects, I am most interested in the aspects of tradition. In contrast, Legalist texts,6 such as the statecraft that facilitate positive action common HFZ, the Book of Lord Shang (BLS), the “Shenzi amongst the populace. Fragments,” the “Shen Buhai Fragments,” and Additionally, I also appreciate the Legalist the Guanzi, are considered either anti- view of history—perhaps best articulated in the pedagogical or unconcerned with populace BLS and HFZ. In other words, Legalist peda- learning. gogy should be understood as context- Indeed, we can find passages in the BLS dependent, or responding to the problems of that specifically criticize Confucian moral culti- its time through requiring the subject’s contri- vation and education. However, if we reex- bution to state wealth and strength. amine Legalist texts with a broader, sociological In short: The ruler creates laws that are in- conception of pedagogy, one that recognizes fused with values suitable for the times and cir- how learning and education can take place be- cumstances. Laws then facilitate a social prac- yond the context of individual cultivation, then tice through rewarding contributions to collec- it becomes apparent that the Legalist political tive survival and prosperity that are in accord- vision does facilitate a distinctly shared collec- ance with state values, while punishing the sub- tive culture through specific state practices. ject’s pursuits of profit and fame that occur at While much of the analysis of Legalist texts the state’s expense. In this sense, the law and its focuses on the ruler, methods for creating and reinforcements fundamentally shape individual maintaining social order, and the advantages identity according to what the ruler defines as collective need. 5 Schneider argued that the HFZ ideal state possesses a public “justice” (gong yi ), one of “order giving and Precedent for Treating Legalist order taking” (Schneider 2014: 30), that aligns the ruler’s interests with those of his ministers and the rest of his Thought as Pedagogical populace. See: Henrique Schneider, “Han Fei and Jus- tice,” Cambridge Journal of China Studies, 9, no.4 (2014): 20- It should be noted that this study would not be 37. the first to suggest that there is a pedagogical 6 I will not engage in a discussion over the ways the term “Legalist” has been problematized. An extended discus- quality to Legalist governance. sion of this can be found in Paul R. Goldin, “Persistent Xu argued that the HFZ’s law can be con- Misconceptions about Chinese ‘Legalism’,” Journal of Chi- ceptualized as moral education. Since the HFZ nese Philosophy 38, no. 1 (2011): 88-104. Generally, I will insists that there are only a few people who can follow the argument in favor of the use of the term “Le- be relied upon to engage in goodness on their galist” found in King (2015). The Journal of School & Society 42 ISSN 2575-9922 6(1) 40–54 ©Author(s) 2019 own accord, the law primarily educates by He suggested, given the objectives of the ideal blocking the pathways that would allow sub- state in the HFZ, that Legalist statecraft en- jects to engage in malfeasance, while causing courages behavioral conformity with a non- subjects to conform to what the state architec- moral normativity.10 Pines likewise noted that ture of governance encourages and discourages. the BLS does not speak of any “active dissemi- Xu also asserted that law is made public and nation of ideas or ideals amongst the popu- clear, accommodates the natural inclinations of lace.”11 human beings, and generally employs subjects Zhou, however, pointed out how some according to their respective talents. Through parts of the HFZ refer to Confucius approving- these aspects, the HFZ’s law teaches and trans- ly or as an authoritative source. This, according forms subjects on a social level rather than rely- to Zhou, is evidence of a general reverence for ing on them to do so on an individual basis.7 Confucius and his ideas about legal reinforce- Xie described the HFZ’s method of educa- ment, the reliability of the state apparatus, fair- tion through five aspects of his own. The quali- ness, balance, and the division between the rul- ty of education is rigid and non-accommodative er and ministers.12 Regardless of one’s position, to the love found in interpersonal relationships. it is clear that discourse about the moral and In addition, the HFZ’s law is used as a primary educational concern in Legalist text challenges source of teaching. As a result, the people will how they are traditionally interpreted.13 learn qualities and behavior the state considers So, whether or not HFZ’s reference to desirable from the good faith and mutual trust Confucians represents an appeal to authority or demonstrated by the implementation of the law merely a mouthpiece through which it com- and the ruler-subject relationship. Xie also ar- municates its own ideas, the text nevertheless gued that the ruler himself should exemplify the depicts a culture within which economic and aforementioned desirable character traits and symbolic capital are accumulated through the behaviors to further reinforce the teachings in enforcement of state law—that is, they are the law.8 Shi has asserted that the Legalist notion of law uses morality to assist in the implementa- 10 Eirik Lang Harris, “Han Fei on the Problem of Morali- tion of the legal system by praising those who ty,” in Paul R.
Recommended publications
  • Carroll 2018 [Dao]
    1 This is a post-peer-review, pre-copyedit version of an article published in Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy, December 2018, 17/4, 527–545. The final authenticated version is available online at: https://doi.org/ 10.1007/s11712-018-9627-5. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with Springer Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. “Wittgenstein and the Xunzi on the Clarification of Language”1 Thomas D. Carroll Senior Lecturer, General Education The Chinese University of Hong Kong, Shenzhen 2001 Longxiang Avenue, Longgang District Shenzhen, China 518172 Email: [email protected] ORCID: 0000-0003-2890-9323 Abstract: Broadly speaking, language is part of a social activity in both Wittgenstein and Xunzi 荀⼦, and for both clarification of language is central to their philosophical projects; the goal of this article is to explore the extent of resonance and discord that may be found when comparing these two philosophers. While for Xunzi, the rectification of names (zhengming 正名) is anchored in a regard for establishing, propagating, and/or restoring a harmonious social system, perspicuity is for Wittgenstein represented as a philosophical end in itself. The article ventures study in particular the themes of perspicuity and aspect-perception in Wittgenstein together with the topics of correcting names and the cultivation of the heart-mind (xin ⼼) in the Xunzi. The 1 A previous version of this article was read at the 2015 meeting of the International Society for Chinese Philosophy in Hong Kong. I am thankful to attendees for questions that have helped improve my thinking with respect to these philosophical traditions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Romance of the Three Kingdoms Podcast. This Is Episode 53. Last
    Welcome to the Romance of the Three Kingdoms Podcast. This is episode 53. Last time, Sun Quan’s adviser Lu Su had brought Zhuge Liang to the Southlands to meet with his master in hopes of forming an alliance between Liu Bei and the Southlands to resist Cao Cao. But when Lu Su went to see Sun Quan, he found the other advisers all telling Sun Quan that Cao Cao was too strong and that it was in everyone’s best interest to surrender. Sun Quan was nonplussed by this, and while he was taking a bathroom break, Lu Su told him that while everyone else could surrender to Cao Cao, Sun Quan alone could not. “For the likes of me,” Lu Su said, “surrender means being sent back to my hometown. Eventually, I can work my way back into high office. But if you surrender, you would not be able to go home. Your rank would be no more than a marquis. You would have but one carriage, one horse, and a few servants. You would be no one’s lord. Everyone else was just trying to save themselves. You must not listen to them. It’s time to make a master plan for yourself.” Now, Lu Su’s analysis is pretty spot on if you think about it. Look at what happened when Cao Cao took over Jing Province. All the officials and officers who surrendered made out pretty well with nice ranks and titles. But their former lord, Liu Cong (2), met an ignoble end. Sun Quan himself had just been pressed by his own advisers to surrender, and those advisers were no doubt looking out for themselves.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Examination of Confucius' Rectification of Names
    Journal of chinese humanities � (���6) �47-�7� brill.com/joch A New Examination of Confucius’ Rectification of Names Cao Feng (曹峰) Professor of Philosophy, Renmin University, China [email protected] Translated by Brook Hefright Abstract Confucius’ explanation of the “rectification of names” is not necessarily related to the theories of “social status” and “names and actuality.” The reason scholars have inter- preted the rectification of names in the Analects in so many different ways is, to a large degree, due to assumptions about Confucius’ thinking by his successors, and based on the views on rectification of names among later generations. In the course of the devel- opment of thinking about names, scholars have augmented Confucius’ own explana- tion, gradually fleshing it out from an empty shell into a substantial edifice. The original meaning may have been very simple: Confucius did not wish to establish a standard system of names. Rather, he was simply the first person in history to realize the impor- tance of language in politics. As a politician, Confucius noticed and foresaw the influ- ence that the indeterminacy, ambiguity, and arbitrariness of names could have on politics. He discerned the political consequences when language could not accurately express meaning or when there was no way for people to accurately perceive it. He also recognized how names, as a way of clarifying right and wrong and establishing norms, could have a great effect on a society’s politics. Although Confucius noted that disunity in speech could lead to disunity in politics, he did not propose a solution.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Qing Æ…–In the Huainanziâ•Žs Ethics
    Susquehanna University Scholarly Commons Religious Studies Faculty Publications 9-2015 The Role of Qing 情in the Huainanzi’s Ethics Matthew L. Duperon Susquehanna University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarlycommons.susqu.edu/reli_fac_pubs Part of the Chinese Studies Commons, and the Religion Commons Recommended Citation Duperon, Matthew L., "The Role of Qing 情in the Huainanzi’s Ethics" (2015). Religious Studies Faculty Publications. Paper 1. http://scholarlycommons.susqu.edu/reli_fac_pubs/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Role of Qing 情 in the Huainanzi’s Ethics Matthew Duperon Susquehanna University The second-century BCE text Huainanzi purports to be an exhaustive compendium of all knowledge needed to successfully govern a vast, diverse empire like the one administrated by the early Han dynasty. As such, it addresses topics from a range of theoretical and applied fields like military theory, politics and the administration of government, economics, geography, ritual practice, and much more, all within the metaphysical framework of correlative cosmology in vogue at the time. In developing an overall program for how the Han empire should be administered, the Huainanzi authors take normative stances on these issues, and the text consequently includes a great deal of ethical content. The authors’ syncretic vision based in correlative cosmology provides the meta-ethical foundation upon which they build this ethical program. Thus, their program of ethical self-cultivation—how humans can move from a state of imperfection toward one of sagely perfection—partakes of the same theoretical framework that shapes the argument of the text as a whole.
    [Show full text]
  • {PDF EPUB} Five Lost Classics Tao Huang-Lao and Yin-Yang in Han China by Robin D.S
    Read Ebook {PDF EPUB} Five Lost Classics Tao Huang-lao and Yin-yang in Han China by Robin D.S. Yates Learn - Explore | Bibliographical notes for the Ma Wang Dui texts. Mawang Dui 馬王堆 - the Horse King Mound - is an archaeological site located in Changsha, China. It is the site of three tombs belonging to the first Marquis of Dai, his wife, and a male who is believed to be their son. The site was excavated from 1972 to 1974. Most of the artifacts from Mawangdui are displayed at the Hunan Provincial Museum. This discovery was monumental, one of the most significant of the 20th century and has changed our view of the history of medicine and Daoism in China. The tomb contained various medical texts, including depictions of qigong (dao yin) exercises. For our purposes we will mainly focus on these philosophical and medical texts, but the tombs contained political and historical texts as well. the texts. These text were “written to advise ruling Han dynasty authorities on how to attune themselves to the cosmos at a time of rapidly changing political and social climate.” From the sleeve of Yates' Five Lost Classics : “In 1973, among the many unique documents discovered in the richly furnished tomb of a Han-dynasty aristocrat, were five books written on silk, primary texts of Huang-lao Daoism and Yin-yang philosophy that had been lost to mankind for more than 2,000 years. A discovery as important in China as the unearthing of the Dead Sea Scrolls was in the West, the Mawangdui texts created a sensation when they were first published, even leading to the foundation of a new religion on Taiwan… The recovery of the five lost classics sheds new light on a critical transitional period of Chinese political and intellectual history.
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL 3531: Topics in Chinese Philosophy: Huanglao Daoism Term 2, 2019
    PHIL 3531: Topics in Chinese Philosophy: Huanglao Daoism Term 2, 2019 Time: Thur 9:30 am-12:15 pm Location: ELB 303 Course Overview This course examines one of the most neglected schools of ancient China: Huanglao Daoism. Arising in the late Warring States period, Huanglao reached its peak in the Han dynasty. The school is syncretic in nature, drawing upon the Legalist thought of Hanfeizi and Guanzi, the Daoist thought of Laozi, and the medical writings attributed to the Yellow Emperor. There is no central text used by this School but a selection of concepts that were discussed across a variety of texts, the most notable being: “law, standard” (fa 法), Dao 道, “punishment” (xing 刑), “virtue” (de 德), Qi 氣, Yin-Yang 陰陽, etc. These concepts were all used by the ruler as an expression of his authority and as a model for benevolent governance. The second half of the course focusses on Chinese medicine and its connection to Huanglao cosmology which saw humans as inseparable from and subject to the cycles of Nature and the spiritual power of Heaven. Advisory to Majors: to be taken in year 2 or above. Learning Outcomes 1. Become familiar with key philosophical concepts, arguments, and movements. 2. Develop your skill in reading philosophical texts. 3. Develop your critical thinking skills by discussing lecture materials in tutorials. 4. Learn how to research and write philosophical papers. Topics See lecture schedule below Learning Activities 1. Read and give thought to the assigned readings. 2. Develop the skills mentioned above in the Learning Outcomes.
    [Show full text]
  • Emptying the Mind and Stilling the Body Syncretism in the Concept of Self-Regulation in Chapter 22 of the Chunqiu Fanlu
    Original Paper UDC 111:159.9.016.1(315) Received April 24th, 2014 Ivana Buljan University of Zagreb, Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences, Ivana Lučića 3, HR–10000 Zagreb [email protected] Emptying the Mind and Stilling the Body Syncretism in the Concept of Self-Regulation in Chapter 22 of the Chunqiu fanlu Abstract The concept of shen 身, meaning a person in all his or her physiological, psychological, and sociological aspects, is an important concept in Chinese philosophy. What the nature of shen is, and consequently how to maintain, regulate, and cultivate one’s own body/self/ person, has been a prominent philosophical issue in China. This article examines how this issue was comprehended in Chapter 22, the “Tong guo shen” 通 國身 (“Linking the State and the Body”) chapter, of the important Chinese philosophical compendium the Chunqiu fanlu 春秋繁露, traditionally ascribed to Dong Zhongshu 董仲舒 (c. 179 to 104 BCE). This article follows and expands upon research conducted by Sarah Queen, who suggested that some of the chapters of the unit to which the “Tong guo shen” belongs are character­ ised by a syncretic approach and suggest familiarity with inner-cultivation techniques. This article particularly focuses on syncretism in the notion of self­regulation in the “Tong guo shen” chapter. It examines the core principles, values, concepts, and ideas of self-regulation in the context of the Chunqiu fanlu’s earlier sources. Through an examination of texts and documents produced from the Spring and Autumn period to the end of the Eastern Han dy­ nasty, this paper reconstructs the idea of self-regulation through a mutually corroborative philological and philosophical analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • The Old Master
    INTRODUCTION Four main characteristics distinguish this book from other translations of Laozi. First, the base of my translation is the oldest existing edition of Laozi. It was excavated in 1973 from a tomb located in Mawangdui, the city of Changsha, Hunan Province of China, and is usually referred to as Text A of the Mawangdui Laozi because it is the older of the two texts of Laozi unearthed from it.1 Two facts prove that the text was written before 202 bce, when the first emperor of the Han dynasty began to rule over the entire China: it does not follow the naming taboo of the Han dynasty;2 its handwriting style is close to the seal script that was prevalent in the Qin dynasty (221–206 bce). Second, I have incorporated the recent archaeological discovery of Laozi-related documents, disentombed in 1993 in Jishan District’s tomb complex in the village of Guodian, near the city of Jingmen, Hubei Province of China. These documents include three bundles of bamboo slips written in the Chu script and contain passages related to the extant Laozi.3 Third, I have made extensive use of old commentaries on Laozi to provide the most comprehensive interpretations possible of each passage. Finally, I have examined myriad Chinese classic texts that are closely associated with the formation of Laozi, such as Zhuangzi, Lüshi Chunqiu (Spring and Autumn Annals of Mr. Lü), Han Feizi, and Huainanzi, to understand the intellectual and historical context of Laozi’s ideas. In addition to these characteristics, this book introduces several new interpretations of Laozi.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analects of Confucius
    The analecTs of confucius An Online Teaching Translation 2015 (Version 2.21) R. Eno © 2003, 2012, 2015 Robert Eno This online translation is made freely available for use in not for profit educational settings and for personal use. For other purposes, apart from fair use, copyright is not waived. Open access to this translation is provided, without charge, at http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23420 Also available as open access translations of the Four Books Mencius: An Online Teaching Translation http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23421 Mencius: Translation, Notes, and Commentary http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23423 The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the Mean: An Online Teaching Translation http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23422 The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the Mean: Translation, Notes, and Commentary http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23424 CONTENTS INTRODUCTION i MAPS x BOOK I 1 BOOK II 5 BOOK III 9 BOOK IV 14 BOOK V 18 BOOK VI 24 BOOK VII 30 BOOK VIII 36 BOOK IX 40 BOOK X 46 BOOK XI 52 BOOK XII 59 BOOK XIII 66 BOOK XIV 73 BOOK XV 82 BOOK XVI 89 BOOK XVII 94 BOOK XVIII 100 BOOK XIX 104 BOOK XX 109 Appendix 1: Major Disciples 112 Appendix 2: Glossary 116 Appendix 3: Analysis of Book VIII 122 Appendix 4: Manuscript Evidence 131 About the title page The title page illustration reproduces a leaf from a medieval hand copy of the Analects, dated 890 CE, recovered from an archaeological dig at Dunhuang, in the Western desert regions of China. The manuscript has been determined to be a school boy’s hand copy, complete with errors, and it reproduces not only the text (which appears in large characters), but also an early commentary (small, double-column characters).
    [Show full text]
  • History of Chinese Philosophy: Antiquity to 1200
    Winter 2017 Tues. and Weds 9:00-10:40 Location TBA HISTORY OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY: ANTIQUITY TO 1200 Tracing its beginnings back to the time of the pre-Socratics, the Chinese philosophical tradition is marked by a diversity and sophistication that makes it interesting not only in its own right, but also as a point of comparative reference: it offers an alternative conceptual and moral space from which to think about basic ideas and questions, and to interrogate the very foundations of philosophical inquiry. This course introduces the maJor texts of the Chinese philosophical tradition from its beginnings c. 6th century BCE to around 1200 CE. The first half will be devoted to key early texts – those connected to the figures of Confucius, Mozi, Mencius, Xunzi, Laozi, Zhuangzi, Han Feizi and others. We will learn about the distinctive concerns and approaches of each of these texts, and the positions they represented within the cosmological, ethical and political debates that ensued during the period of the Warring States (4th-3rd centuries BCE). In the second half of the course, we will learn about new styles of inquiry that accompanied the rise and consolidation of the first empires in China, as well as those that emerged in the wake of imperial collapse in the 3rd century CE. In this part we will study texts connected to the cosmological synthesis of the Han empire; Buddhist hermeneutics and metaphysics; the “Learning of the Mystery”; medieval Daoist self-cultivation; literary theory; and Neo-Confucianism. Source texts will be read in English translation. Instructor Curie Virág Office: TBA [email protected] Tel: TBA E-mail policy I will try to respond to e-mails within 24 hours.
    [Show full text]
  • Han Fei and the Han Feizi
    Introduction: Han Fei and the Han Feizi Paul R. Goldin Han Fei 韓非 was the name of a proli fi c Chinese philosopher who (according to the scanty records available to us) was executed on trumped up charges in 233 B.C.E. Han Feizi 韓非子, meaning Master Han Fei , is the name of the book purported to contain his writings. In this volume, we distinguish rigorously between Han Fei (the man) and Han Feizi (the book) for two main reasons. First, the authenticity of the Han Feizi —or at least of parts of it—has long been doubted (the best studies remain Lundahl 1992 and Zheng Liangshu 1993 ) . This issue will be revisited below; for now, suffi ce to it to say that although the contributors to this volume accept the bulk of it as genuine, one cannot simply assume that Han Fei was the author of everything in the Han Feizi . Indeed, there is a memorial explic- itly attributed to Han Fei’s rival Li Si 李斯 (ca. 280–208 B.C.E.) in the pages of the Han Feizi ( Chen Qiyou 陳奇猷 2000 : 1.2.42–47); some scholars fear that other material in the text might also be the work of people other than Han Fei. Second, and no less importantly, even if Han Fei is responsible for the lion’s share of the extant Han Feizi , a reader must be careful not to identify the philosophy of Han Fei himself with the philosophy (or philosophies) advanced in the Han Feizi , as though these were necessarily the same thing.
    [Show full text]
  • Han Feizi's Criticism of Confucianism and Its Implications for Virtue Ethics
    JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY Journal of Moral Philosophy 5 (2008) 423–453 www.brill.nl/jmp Han Feizi’s Criticism of Confucianism and its Implications for Virtue Ethics * Eric L. Hutton Department of Philosophy, University of Utah, 215 S. Central Campus Drive, CTIHB, 4th fl oor, Salt Lake City, UT 84112, USA [email protected] Abstract Several scholars have recently proposed that Confucianism should be regarded as a form of virtue ethics. Th is view off ers new approaches to understanding not only Confucian thinkers, but also their critics within the Chinese tradition. For if Confucianism is a form of virtue ethics, we can then ask to what extent Chinese criticisms of it parallel criticisms launched against contemporary virtue ethics, and what lessons for virtue ethics in general might be gleaned from the challenges to Confucianism in particular. Th is paper undertakes such an exercise in examining Han Feizi, an early critic of Confucianism. Th e essay off ers a careful interpretation of the debate between Han Feizi and the Confucians and suggests that thinking through Han Feizi’s criticisms and the possible Confucian responses to them has a broader philosophical payoff , namely by highlighting a problem for current defenders of virtue ethics that has not been widely noticed, but deserves attention. Keywords Bernard Williams, Chinese philosophy, Confucianism, Han Feizi, Rosalind Hursthouse, virtue ethics Although Confucianism is now almost synonymous with Chinese culture, over the course of history it has also attracted many critics from among the Chinese themselves. Of these critics, one of the most interesting is Han Feizi (ca.
    [Show full text]