Proquest Dissertations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Proquest Dissertations Pragmatics and the Showing-Saying Distinction Timothy John Wharton Thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. University of London, May 2003 ProQuest Number: 10010418 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest. ProQuest 10010418 Published by ProQuest LLC(2016). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 Abstract This thesis focuses on the role in communication of ‘natural’ signs and natural behaviours—facial expressions, spontaneous expression of emotion, interjections etc.—and considers how they might be accommodated within a pragmatic theory. Linguists generally abstract away from such behaviours and focus on the grammar, or linguistic code. However, there are two reasons why the pragmatist should cast a broader net. Firstly, it is increasingly recognised in pragmatics that verbal communication is not simply a coding-decoding process but an intelligent activity involving the expression and recognition of intentions. Secondly, sentences are rarely uttered in a behavioural vacuum; the aim of a pragmatic theory is to explain how utterances—with all their linguistic and non-linguistic properties—are understood. The analysis I propose has implications for theories of utterance interpretation. Firstly, verbal communication often involves a mixture of (what Paul Grice called) natural(N) and non-natural(NN) meaning, and there is a continuum of cases between ‘showing’ and meaningNN; I show that natural communicative phenomena may be located at different points along the showing- meaningNN continuum. This has clear implications for the domain of pragmatic principles or maxims, for it suggests that they are best seen as applying to the domain of intentional communication as a whole, rather than to the domain of meaningNN. Secondly, the wider question of how ‘natural’ communicative behaviours are to be accommodated within a pragmatic theory breaks down into several further, more specific, questions— How are natural phenomena interpreted? Do they all work in the same way? I argue that some natural behaviours have a signalling function: they are, in effect, natural codes. Such behaviours do not fit easily into Grice’s distinction between natural and non­ natural meaning, which suggests that it is not exhaustive, and that it does not provide the best starting point for constructing theories of communication. Pragmatics and the Showing-Saying Distinction Table of Contents Acknowledgments 5 Introduction 8 Chapter One 1. Natural and non-natural meaning 22 2. Showing and meaning 36 3. Deliberately shown natural behaviours 42 Chapter Two 1. Saying and meaning 1.0 The territory 49 1.1 Saying and truth-conditions 53 1.2 Underdeterminacy: bridging the gap 59 2. Saying 2.0 Grice’s wider programme 65 2.1 The four-step progression 74 2.2 Riddle of the strands 81 3. Implications 97 Chapter Three 1. Relevance theory and the showing-meaning^N continuum 104 2. Relevance theory and lexical pragmatics 116 3. Translational and non-translational activation of concepts 123 Chapter Four 1. Inteijections 133 2. Inteijections and concepts 138 3. Inteijections and‘response cries’ 149 4. Inteijections and meaning 153 5. Inteijections and procedures 160 6. Inteijections and language 164 7. The naturalness of inteijections 171 Chapter Five 1. Natural Codes 1.0 Codes, honeybee dances and smiles 180 1.1 Signs and signals 188 2. What do natural codes encode? 2.0 Sebeok’s codes and Peircean 194 2.1 The conceptualist approach to facial expression 201 2.2 Non-translational encoding II 209 Chapter Six 1. Mindreaders 219 2. Two ‘showing-meaning’ continua 233 3. A prince among primates 241 4. Myths 250 Bibliography 257 Acknowledgments I owe an enormous debt of gratitude to many people. I cannot hope to mention them all, and apologise to those I have left out. Thank you to my parents, Roy and Mary Wharton, and my brother Nick, for their love; Thank you to those few, close friends who have supported me in everything I have done—David Brown deserves special mention here, and Phil Harrison too, for happening to watch (and staying sober enough to remember) the Leonard Bernstein lecture that got him hooked on linguistics, and eventually led to my getting hooked too; Thank you to Katherine Bradley, for all her help in the past, and Peter Eastham for all his help in the present—special thanks also to Roma Loban, to whose memory this work is in part dedicated; Thank you to those teachers at school who recognised that education is (as Chomsky once said) 1% about methodology and 99% about inspiration—I single out Martin Herbert and Don Moffat here (though this is not to question their methodology); Thank you to everyone involved in the Department of Phonetics and Linguistics at University College London, where I have been studying and working for the past seven years—in particular I thank Neil Smith, whose book ‘The Twitter Machine’ reeled me in (having already been hooked). Thank you also to Nick Allott, Corinne Iten, Paula Rubio, Rosa Vega-Moreno and members of the Relevance Theory Reading Group for stimulating discussion, and Richard Horsey for sharing with me soft-shell crabs, crayfish popcorn and much discussion of cognitive linguistics in Santa Barbara, Summer 2001; Thank you to the UCL Graduate School who (somehow) deemed me worthy of investment, and provided me with the financial support that made it possible for me to continue my studies; Thank you to all the wonderful students I have taught at UCL; Thank you to Steve and Mary Skelly, who cut me my own set of keys to their beautiful West London house, and to Clive and Denise Smith, who generously provided me with office space in Lewes. I hope I will be forgiven if I also thank a man whose figure looms large over this thesis—a person I never met, but sometimes feel as if I have, and always feel as if I wish I had—Paul Grice. As well as all the above, I would like to single out five special people and reserve my biggest thanks for them. I have been uncommonly lucky that these five people have found (and find) it within themselves to think I am worthy of their guidance, fnendship and (in some cases) love. The first of these is my principal supervisor—Deirdre Wilson. To say she has been supportive over the past few years is to do no justice at all to everything she has done for me, both personally and professionally: on a personal level, she has helped me through some hard times, and shown patience, understanding and encouragement well beyond the call of duty; on a professional level, while some supervisors offer their students new roads down which to travel, Deirdre throws open the shutters to reveal whole new vistas, whole new landscapes to explore. I’ve really hardly begun my exploration, but I feel very lucky to have been given the chance. The second person is Robyn Carston, my second supervisor. I single Robyn out because as well as all the time, effort and patience she has invested in me during my time at UCL as both an undergraduate and postgraduate student, Robyn is a teacher with the kind of qualities I allude to above. Studying her undergraduate courses was never work, it was always pleasure; one course in particular in the Spring of 1998 was largely responsible for my decision to make ‘meaning’ the general direction I intended to pursue. And so to the final three: my wife Tamsin, and my daughters Xanthe and Zoë. I don’t think I’m easy to be with at the best of times, and during the past few years (some of which have not been the best of times) I’ve been plain impossible. Tam, thank you for your love and support, and for making home more than just a place I live. Xanthe and Zoë, I’m so lucky to be your daddy; and among all the wonderful things that await you in your lives, I hope that one day you too can experience the sheer, indulgent pleasure of being allowed, no encouraged, to think and to leam. (Just don’t leave it as late as I have.) Introduction ‘A wagging tongue ... proves to be only one part of a complex human act whose meaning must also be sought in the movement of the eyebrows and hand.’ (Goffman 1964, pp. 133-134) ‘We see it as a major challenge for any account of human communication to give a precise description and explanation of its vaguer effects. Distinguishing meaning from communication, accepting that something can be communicated without strictly speaking being meant by the communicator or the communicator’s behaviour, is a first essential step. [...] Once this step is taken, we believe that this framework we propose... can rise to this challenge.’ (Sperber and Wilson 1986/1995, pp. 57-58) Sentences are rarely uttered in a behavioural vacuum. We colour and flavour our speech with a variety of ‘natural’ vocal and facial gestures, which indicate our internal state by conveying attitudes to the propositions we express or information about our emotions or feelings. Though we may be aware of them, such behaviours are often beyond our conscious control: they are involuntary, spontaneous.
Recommended publications
  • An Interpretationist Approach to the Thinking Mind DISSERTATION
    Thought Without Language: an Interpretationist Approach to the Thinking Mind DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Michael Dean Jaworski Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2010 Dissertation Committee: Neil Tennant, Advisor William Taschek Ben Caplan Copyright by Michael Dean Jaworski 2010 Abstract I defend an account of thought on which non-linguistic beings can be thinkers. This result is significant in that many philosophers have claimed that the ability to think depends on the ability to use language. These opponents of my view note that our everyday understanding of our own cognitive activities qua thought bestows upon those activities the propositional structure of sentences and the inferential norms of public linguistic practice. They hold that our attributions of thought to non-linguistic beings project non-existent structure onto the cognitive activities of those beings, and assess the beings’ activities according to standards to which the beings bear no responsibility. So, despite the complex neural and behavioral activities of many non-linguistic beings, my opponents hold that those beings are not properly described as thinkers. To respond to my opponents successfully, one must not merely cite scientific and folk practices of thought attribution that permit thought to be attributed to some non- linguistic beings. My opponents’ insights might be taken to demonstrate a need to revise those practices, or to treat the attributions of thought to non-linguistic beings made within those practices as instrumentally valuable but technically false. Instead, my strategy is to acknowledge the language-like structure and norms of thought, and show that a non- linguistic being’s cognitive activities might nonetheless have that structure and be subject ii to those norms.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Grice, Philosopher and Linguist Other Books by Siobhan Chapman
    Paul Grice, Philosopher and Linguist Other books by Siobhan Chapman ACCENT IN CONTEXT PHILOSOPHY FOR LINGUISTS Paul Grice, Philosopher and Linguist Siobhan Chapman © Siobhan Chapman 2005 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2005 978-1-4039-0297-9 All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Tottenham Court Road, London W1T 4LP. Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The author has asserted her right to be identified as the author of this work in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. First published 2005 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS and 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10010 Companies and representatives throughout the world PALGRAVE MACMILLAN is the global academic imprint of the Palgrave Macmillan division of St. Martin’s Press, LLC and of Palgrave Macmillan Ltd. Macmillan® is a registered trademark in the United States, United Kingdom and other countries. Palgrave is a registered trademark in the European Union and other countries. ISBN 978-0-230-20693-9 ISBN 978-0-230-00585-3 (eBook) DOI 10.1057/978023005853 This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained forest sources.
    [Show full text]
  • Herbert Paul Grice 1913–1988
    PAUL GRICE Copyright © The British Academy 2001 – all rights reserved Herbert Paul Grice 1913–1988 PAUL GRICE was born 15 March 1913 in Birmingham, the elder son of Herbert Grice, businessman and musician, and his wife, Mabel Felton, a schoolmistress. He died on 28 August 1988, in Berkeley, California. The salient facts of his career are easily stated. He was educated first at Clifton College, Bristol, where he was head boy and also distinguished in music and sports, and second, at Corpus Christi College, Oxford, where he was awarded first class honours in classical honour moderations (1933) and literae humaniores (1935) and of which he later became an honorary fellow (1988). After a year as assistant master at Rossall School, Lancashire, and then two years as Harmsworth Senior Scholar at Merton College, Oxford, he was appointed lecturer and in 1939 Fellow and tutor in philosophy at St John’s College, Oxford, and university lecturer in the sub-faculty of philosophy. He was elected a Fellow of the British Academy in 1966 and became an Honorary Fellow of St John’s in 1980. During the Second World War he served in the Royal Navy in the Atlantic theatre and then in Admiralty intelligence from 1940 to 1945. In 1942 he married Kathleen, daughter of George Watson, naval architect, and sister of Steven Watson, a St John’s colleague and historian. After the war he soon became known as a philosopher of great origin- ality and independence and was frequently invited to the United States where he held visiting appointments at Harvard, Brandeis, Stanford, and Cornell universities.
    [Show full text]
  • The APA Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy
    2013 The APA GUide To GraduatE ProGrAms in PhilosoPhy University of Delaware Newark, DE 19716 www.apaonline.org All data collected by the American Philosophical Association. The data in this publication have been provided by the departments and programs listed; in the cases where no response was received to repeated requests for information, the most recent data provided, if any, can be found in the previous edition. The APA cannot guarantee the accuracy of this report; because all information has been self- reported, there may be errors or inconsistencies in these data. Readers should therefore examine the available data closely to ensure that any comparisons are made in a fair and reasonable manner. Errors or inconsistencies should be brought to the attention of the American Philosophical Association by email to [email protected]. For clarification, correction, updating, or supplementation of the information provided, contact the department(s) in question. © 2013, 2014 The American Philosophical Association This publication of the American Philosophical Association may not be reproduced for sale or future distribution without the express written consent of the executive director. Inquiries should be directed as follows: The American Philosophical Association University of Delaware, 31 Amstel Avenue, Newark, DE 19716 Phone (302) 831-1112 • Fax (302) 831-8690 [email protected] Last updated March 14, 2014 About the Grad Guide The Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy, originally published biennially until the early 2000s, was relaunched in 2012 as an annual online resource. The guide compiles data on both doctoral and master’s degree programs in philosophy at institutions throughout the US and Canada, offering prospective students, job candidates, and other members of the profession a rich resource on post- graduate education and employment in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Philip Robichad CV
    Philip Robichaud PHILIP ROBICHAUD Department of Philosophy Rice University P.O. Box 1892 Houston, TX 77251 (832) 465-1333 (cell) [email protected] EDUCATION Ph.D. Philosophy, Rice University (Expected 2011) M.A. Philosophy, Rice University (2008) B.S. Molecular and Cell Biology, Texas A&M University (1999) B.S. Genetics, Texas A&M University (1999) AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION AND COMPETENCE AOS: Ethics, Moral Psychology AOC: Social and Political Philosophy, Metaethics, Medical Ethics, Environmental Ethics DISSERTATION Title: The Epistemic Condition of Moral Responsibility and Normative Ignorance George Sher (chair), Baruch Brody, Tamler Sommers Abstract: I defend an account of the epistemic condition for moral responsibility. After criticizing extant theories of the epistemic condition, I propose and defend an account in which epistemic norms play a leading role. I argue that an agent’s ignorance is culpable only if it is traceable to failures to respond to the epistemic reasons that ground epistemic norms. I analyze the nature of epistemic norms and their underlying epistemic reasons, and I argue that the relevant norms are picked out by reference to the epistemic capacities of the agent. I also develop a notion of the self that is required for grounding claims of epistemic responsibility. Finally, I discuss the implications of my view for a special class of ignorance, namely normative ignorance, and I argue that my account captures much of what is intuitive about such cases. PAPERS IN PREPARATION “Culpable ignorance, control, and quality of will” “Epistemic agency and quality of will” 1 of 4 Philip Robichaud CONFERENCE PRESENTATIONS Comments on “Deceiving you, deceiving me: The nature and morality of self deception” By Amber Griffoen.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconsidering the Character and Role of Inquiry in School Science: Analysis of a Conference12
    Reconsidering the Character and Role of Inquiry in School Science: Analysis of a Conference12 Richard E. Grandy Philosophy and Cognitive Sciences Rice University [email protected] Richard A. Duschl Graduate School of Education Rutgers University Introduction This is a report of an NSF sponsored conference we organized whose purpose was to provide a structure for discussion of science education with the goal of summarizing and synthesizing developments in three domains (1) science studies, e.g., history, philosophy and sociology of science (2) the learning sciences, e.g., cognitive science, philosophy of mind, educational psychology, social psychology, computer sciences, linguistics, and (3) educational research focusing on the design of learning environments that promote inquiry and that facilitate dynamic assessments. These three domains have reshaped our thinking about the role that inquiry has in science education programs. Over the past 50 years there have been dynamic changes in our conceptualizations of science, of learning, and of science learning environments. Such changes have important implications for how we interpret (1) the role of inquiry in K-12 science education programs and (2) the design of curriculum, instruction, and assessment models that strive to meet the NSES inquiry goals: • Students should learn to do scientific inquiry. • Students should develop an understanding of scientific inquiry. Although these domains have undergone closely related changes, the communication among them has been very partial and haphazard. The point of our conference was to provide a rich structure for interaction. We wrote a plenary paper, which was circulated before hand, and discussed the first evening. On each of the following two days there were four main papers, each with a commentator, followed at the end of the day by a four person panel.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration's Research Tradition
    Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration’s Research Tradition Patricia M. Shields Southwest Texas State University Department of Political Science San Marcos, TX 78666 512-245-2143 [email protected] Presented at the Trinity Symposium on Public Management Research, San Antonio, TX July 23, 1995 1 Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration’s Research Tradition Patricia M. Shields Southwest Texas State University Public Administration has had a history of difficulty and confusion defining itself. Evidence of this confusion can be found in the theory/practice debate. Part of the confusion stems from the way the research/theory/practice problem is conceptualized. For example, some academics argue that the discipline of Public Administration1 needs more rigor and stature. Using the norms of science, they seek explanatory theories with empirical import.2 Another group of academics is concerned about the norms of science being inappropriately applied to Public Administration. 3They are critical of the logical positivist philosophic tradition introduced by Herbert Simon (1945) in Administrative Behavior. Finally, the practitioner asks a wholly different question: What is the use of theory? How can it help me do my job? The differences in these perspectives led me to ask; Just what were the philosophic traditions that underlie the debate and approaches to public administration as either a field of study or a world of practice? Could confusion over unstated philosophic assumptions be hampering productive dialogue? Could these seemingly conflicting positions live under one larger umbrella? This paper is a preliminary attempt to explore three modern philosophical traditions and link them to Public Administration theory and practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Sentential Logic Primer
    Sentential Logic for Psychologists Richard Grandy Daniel Osherson Rice University1 Princeton University2 September 28, 2010 [email protected] [email protected] ii Copyright This work is copyrighted by Richard Grandy and Daniel Osherson. Use of the text is authorized, in part or its entirety, for non-commercial non-profit purposes. Electronic or paper copies may not be sold except at the cost of copy- ing. Appropriate citation to the original should be included in all copies of any portion. iii Preface Students often study logic on the assumption that it provides a normative guide to reasoning in English. In particular, they are taught to associate con- nectives like “and” with counterparts in Sentential Logic. English conditionals go over to formulas with ! as principal connective. The well-known difficul- ties that arise from such translation are not emphasized. The result is the conviction that ordinary reasoning is faulty when discordant with the usual representation in standard logic. Psychologists are particularly susceptible to this attitude. The present book is an introduction to Sentential Logic that attempts to situate the formalism within the larger theory of rational inference carried out in natural language. After presentation of Sentential Logic, we consider its mapping onto English, notably, constructions involving “if . then . .” Our goal is to deepen appreciation of the issues surrounding such constructions. Errors, obscurity, or other defects can be brought to our attention via elec- tronic mail ([email protected], [email protected]). The provenance of revisions will be gratefully acknowledged as new versions are produced. Richard Grandy Daniel Osherson iv Note to students So .
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Grice and His Audience
    — Masterthesis Philosophy — Paul Grice and his audience The role of the audience in Grice’s ideas Student: Wouter Janssen First reader: dr. Menno Lievers Second reader: prof. dr. Jan van Ophuijsen Studentnumber: 3239837 Email: [email protected] Date: 10-09-2010 Academic Master Philosophy at Utrecht University Grice and his audience Wouter Janssen Preface What makes a language? What do words and sentences mean? How are we able to communicate through the use of a language made out of words and sentences? What do I need to know to be able to communicate efficiently? As Michael Dummett notes: The central task of the philosopher of language is to explain what meaning is, that is, what makes a language language . Consider two speakers engaged in conversation. To immediate inspection, all that is happening is that sounds of a certain kind issue from the mouths of each alternately. But we know that there is a deeper significance: they are expressing thoughts, putting forward arguments, stating conjectures, asking questions, etc. What the philosopher of language has to explain is what gives this character to the sounds they utter: what makes their utterances expressions of thought and all these other things? 1 These types of questions are of high importance in the Philosophy of Language. Paul Grice spent a lifetime trying to answer these questions and reading Grice for the first time made me think he could be on the right track. Although Grice made a huge effort in explaining utterer’s-meaning, his answers and solutions are sometimes far from straightforward and several different interpretations exist on a lot of his proposals.
    [Show full text]
  • 30 Thomas S. Kuhn (1922–1996)
    30 Thomas S. Kuhn (1922–1996) RICHARD GRANDY Thomas S. Kuhn’s second monograph, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) is the most widely read and most influential book on the philosophy of science of the twentieth century. It spawned the ubiquitous use of the term “paradigm” in popular culture, including cartoons and business management courses, and a million copies have been sold in almost twenty languages. The central thesis of the book is that the nature of scientific development had been seriously misunderstood by philosophers and scientists, and that, in the words of the opening sentence: “History, if viewed as a repository for more than anecdote or chronology, could produce a decisive transformation in the image of science by which we are now possessed.” The image he sought to transform was one in which science is cumulative, varying in the speed of its progress, but always moving forward, an image in which scientific controversies are a small and unimportant part of the process, friction in the wheels of progress. The contrasting image he championed portrays mature sciences as alternating between two kinds of change. The first are periods of cumulative progress in which sci- entists apply generally accepted theories to the unresolved questions in a domain according to a shared understanding of what constitutes a reasonable scientific ques- tion and of what criteria are used to judge answers. This “normal science” is a very sophisticated form of puzzle-solving and can require great ingenuity, but occurs within a stable framework of tradition. In contrast, the alternating periods of “revolutionary science” consist of confrontation between two diverse understandings of what consti- tutes a reasonable question and what criteria should be used to adjudicate disputes.
    [Show full text]
  • Contributors
    Contributors Kent Bach, Professor of Philosophy, San Francisco State University, California. José A. Benardete, Professor of Philosophy, University of Syracuse, New York. Ermanno Bencivenga, Professor of Philosophy, University of California, Irvine, California. Emma Borg, Lecturer in Philosophy, University of Reading, Pennsylvania. E. P. Bos, University Lecturer in Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, Leiden University, The Netherlands. Bryson Brown, Professor of Philosophy, University of Lethbridge, Lethbridge, Alberta, Canada. James Cargile, Professor of Philosophy, University of Virginia, Virginia. Robert Demolombe, Director of Research, ONERA, Department of Information Processing and Modeling, Toulouse Centre, Toulouse, France. Maarten de Rijke, Professor, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation (ILLC), Department of Mathematics, Computer Science, Physics and Astronomy, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Branden Fitelson, Acting Assistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy, Stanford University, Stanford, California, and Scientific Associate, Mathematics and Computer Science Division, Argonne National Laboratory, Argonne, Illinois. Melvin Fitting, Professor of Philosophy, Lehman College and the Graduate Center, City University of New York, New York. Peter A. Flach, Reader in Machine Learning, Department of Computer Science, University of Bristol, UK. Peter Forrest, Professor of Philosophy, School of Social Science, University of New England, Armidale, New South Wales, Australia. D. M. Gabbay, FRSC, Augustus De Morgan Professor of Logic, Group of Logic and Computation, Department of Computer Science, King’s College, London, UK. viii CONTRIBUTORS Rolf George, Professor of Philosophy, University of Waterloo, Ontario, Canada. Stephen Glaister, Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, University of Washington, Seattle, Washington. Paul Gochet, Professor Emeritus, Department of Philosophy, and Ministère de l’Education et de la Recherche scientifique de la Comunauté Française, University of Liège, Belgium.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Are There More Than Minimal a Priori Constraints on Irrationality?
    [Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72(1) (March 1994): 89-102] Are There More Than Minimal A Priori Constraints on Irrationality? John Biro and Kirk Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL 32611-8545 Our concern in this paper is with the question of how irrational an intentional agent can be, and, in particular, with an argument Stephen Stich has given for the claim that there are only very minimal a priori requirements on the rationality of intentional agents. The argument appears in chapter 2 of The Fragmentation of Reason.1 Stich is concerned there with the prospects for the ‘reform-minded epistemologist’. If there are a priori limits on how irrational we can be, there are limits to how much reform we could expect to achieve. With this in mind, Stich sets out to determine what a priori limits there are on irrationality by examining `a cluster of influential arguments aimed at showing that there are conceptual constraints on how badly a person can reason’ (p. 30). Stich aims to remove the threat of a priori limits on the project of reforming our cognitive practices by showing, first, that these influential arguments are bad arguments, and, second, that at best there are only minimal constraints on how irrational we can be.2 We aim to show three things. The first is that Stich’s own arguments against strong a priori limits on how badly a person can reason are unsuccessful, because Stich fails to take into account that the concept of rationality is an epistemic, not just a logical concept, and because he fails to take into account the connection between having a concept and being able to recognize conceptually simple inferences involving the concept.
    [Show full text]