Theistic Activism and the Euthyphro Dilemma

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Theistic Activism and the Euthyphro Dilemma THEISTIC ACTIVISM AND THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA by DAVID BAGGEn DISSERTATION Submltbtd to the Gradua.. School of Wayne Stat. University Detroit, Michigan In partlill fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY 2002 MAJOR: PHILOSOPHY ,.Cbr. ~ 3/;;/02- Advisor Date o COPYRIGHT BY DAVID BAGGETT 2002 All Rights Re.. rved DEDICATION To my parents, Leonard and Evelyn Baggett, for their years of support and encouragement, whose lives provided for me a model of practical theistic ethics. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Sincere thanks to numerous friends for putting up with my insufferable e­ mails about my dissertation and for often responding with far more illuminating e­ mails of their own. Notably Jim Brent, Ron Butzu, Sloan Lee, and especially Steve Patterson. Deepest thanks go to my dearest friend, Ginger Asel, for all her encouragement, and special thanks to Brian MacPherson for the numerous ways in which he helped me prepare for my final defense. Many thanks to my dissertation committee: First and foremost, Bruce Russell, my practically Anselmian advisor, for his consistent toughness and faimess; Herb Granger, for his knowledge of the history of philosophy and model of philosophical collaboration; William Stine, for conSistently spurring me to do my best; and Elton Higgs, a dear friend and long-time mentor who has taught me what it means to be a Christian scholar. Special thanks to Mike McKinsey too, who, though not an official member of my committee (Since he was out of the country when I had to select it), is nonetheless an invaluable part of it. His incredible generosity of time and philosophical expertise strengthened my work considerably. I would be remiss if I were not to thank Jerry Walls, whose influence over the last dozen years has been tremendously formative in my personal and professional development. He models what it takes and means to be a premier Christian philosopher. iii Dedication ii Acknowtedgments iii Introduction 1 Chapter 1: The Euthyphro Dilemma 6 Chapter 2: The God of Anselm 46 Chapter 3: A Theory of the Good 97 Chapter 4: A Theory of the Right 137 Chapter 5: Why a Good God Issues Bad Commands 189 Conclusion 222 Bibliography 225 Abstract 239 Autobiographical Statement 241 iv 1 Introduction The horrific images of September 11, 2001 remain vividly bumed in the minds of everyone witness to the day's tragic events. Four airplanes hijacked, two of which were within minutes buried in the heart of New York's Wortd Trade Center and a third into the United States Pentagon. Over three thousand innocents extinguished in a single day. Pascal's waming that evil is never done so zealously than when it is performed out of religious conviction struck a poignantly prophetic note, as investigations would soon reveal that the perpetrators of this terrorist plot on American soil were profoundly religious persons. Incensed at America's support of Israel in its conflict with Palestinians, at America's sanctions against Iraq that have contributed to dismal living conditions within that country, and at America's occupation of lands perceived as the sacred ground of Islam, rigidly fundamentalist Muslims trained by a terrorist network loosely run by Osama bin Laden had perpetrated this violence as part of jihad. A holy war against Israel and the United States was touted by bin Laden, dissident Saudi Arabian son of a billionaire, as Allah's sovereign plan to purify Islam, rectify injustices, and defeat evil. Such is only the latest spectre raised in the minds of many listeners when they hear talk of religious ethics. Inquisitions and holy wars, crusades and witch bumings, violent acts of terror and inhumane acts of cruelty, all justified in the name of God. So to affirm an intimate connection between God and morality is to tear open a monstrous can of worms, entailing the loss of moral autonomy and objectivity in the face of divine fiat, or at least faith in divine fiat. Little wonder that numerous contemporary secular and religious thinkers alike would prefer to put 2 ethics on a more solid footing not so susceptible to subjective visions and unverifiable claims of revelation. Not everyone, however, who is sickened and appalled at (what has simply come to be known as) "9/11- shares such skepticism toward religious ethics. A radically different sort of vision of God and religious ethics is possible, bearing as little relation to Osama bin Laden as a loving father does to a pedophile. Rather than making the content of ethics wildly malleable for being a function of divine whim, it is a view of ethics according to which God exists as a plausible candidate, if not the best explanation, for morality's reality. prescriptive power, and stable objectivity. It is a view according to which God, if he exists, is not irrelevant to ethics. neither to moral rightness nor to moral goodness. Admittedly, this is close to the heart of the way in which I have for nearly a" my life thought of ethics, as intimately tied to the existence, nature, and commands of a loving God. The years I have spent studying philosophy have not lessened my confidence in the veridicality of this vision. On entering graduate school, I knew from day one that this would be the topic of my dissertation. I knew that it was a topic on which important work needs to be done. For religious ethics has been confronted since nearly the inception of westem philosophy with what many perceive to be an almost intractable objection. The Euthyphro Dilemma is often touted as posing an in-principle objection to religious ethics. It offers seemingly but two altematives to religious ethicists, one of which entailing religion's irrelevance to morality, the other landing them in the thick of the worst sort of arbitrariness. For quite some time. I have struggled with this challenge to theistic ethics and divine command theory. I was convinced that there was an answer to it, but unsure of what it was. This dissertation is my provisional attempt to answer this 3 challenge. To the extent it is successful, it will not have shown theistic ethics to be true, but simply that the Euthyphro Dilemma does not pose the in-principle objection to it that it is often thought to. Theistic ethics will have survived as at least a living possibility, at most as a compelling and philosophically plausible vision to which those thinking about ethics ought to seriously consider giving their allegiance. But pushing the latter case with any effectiveness requires more constructive work than what I do in this predominantly defensive dissertation. Relative to my specific objectives, allow me to provide a cursory overview of the chapters to follow. Chapter 1 features a general introduction to the Euthyphro dialogue itself. An effort is made to underscore some of the interesting philosophical features of this dialogue leading up to the crucial passage and the Dilemma itself: Is something good or right because God commands it, or does God command it because it is good or right? Both homs of the Dilemma are then discussed, particularty that hom of the Dilemma not favored by the divine command theorist. Chapter 2 spells out the specific theological commitments operative here that serve as constraints on the particular divine command theory defended. It is heavy on biblical and philosophical theology for the purpose of clarifying exactly what operative conception of deity is assumed and what conception of ethics dominates the discussion. Chapter 3 spells out this dissertation's theory of the good and highlights the severe limitations of a definist analysis of theistic ethics. Chapter 4 explicates a divine command theory of the right, while delineating the range of questions that every version of OCT needs to answer. Chapter 5 deploys my analysis in answering arbitrariness and vacuity objections to divine command theory and theistic ethics. In his 1983 inaugural address as the John A. O'Brien Professor of Philosophy at Notre Dame University, Alvin Plantinga delivered an address 4 entitled -Advice to Christian Philosophers,- in which he encouraged them to allow their religious convictions to shape the work they do in philosophy. He counseled them to be unafraid to articulate and explore distinctively religious or even Christian conceptions in their work. Recognizing the vital role played by certain of those most deeply ingrained and cherished aspects of one's social context to the way one orders experience and perceives the world, Plantinga writes Christian philosophers are the philosophers of the Christian community; and it is part of their task as Christian philosophers to seNe the Christian community. But the Christian community has its own questions, its own concems, its own topics for investigation, its own agenda and its own research program. Christian philosophers ought not merely take their inspiration from whafs going on at Princeton or Berkeley or HaNard, attractive and scintillating as that may be; for perhaps those questions and topiCS are not the ones, or the only ones, they should be thinking about as the philosophers of the Christian community. There are other philosophical topics the Christian community must work at, and other topics the Christian community must work at philosophically. And obviously, Christian philosophers are the ones who must do the philosophical work involved. If they devote their best efforts to the topics fashionable to the non-Christian philosophical world, they will neglect a crucial and central part of their task as Christian philosophers. What is needed here is more independence, more autonomy with respect to the projects and concems of the non-theistic philosophical world .... In ethics, for 5 example: perhaps the chief theoretical concem, from the theistic perspective, is the question of how are right and wrong, good and bad, duty, pennission and obligation related to God and to his will and to his creative activity? This question doesn't arise, naturally enough, from a non-theistic perspective; and so, naturally enough, non-theist ethicists do not address it.
Recommended publications
  • 1 the Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation Adam Lerner Some People Care
    The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation Adam Lerner Some people care about doing the right thing as such. They want to do the right thing under that description. These people have what has come to be known as a de dicto desire to do what is right.1 Some people who have a desire to do what’s right as such desire to do what’s right only as a means. They want to do the right thing in order to avoid punishment, or as a way of doing what God or their mother would approve of, or because it would be a sign that they are predestined for salvation. But many care about doing the right thing for its own sake: because it’s the right thing. They have a final desire to do what’s right as such. This desire is an instance of what I will call pure moral motivation (PMM).2 Other instances of PMM include the desire to avoid doing what’s wrong as such, the desire to promote what’s good as such, and the desire to prevent what’s bad as such. Contemporary views in metaethics have been built to satisfy familiar desiderata: accommodating Moorean open questions, explaining the connection between moral judgment and moral motivation, accounting for the supervenience of the moral on the non-moral, and many others. In this paper, I introduce a new desideratum: vindicating the rationality of PMM. I argue that PMM is often rational, and that any adequate view must accommodate this fact. The puzzle of PMM is to explain how that can be done.
    [Show full text]
  • One Hundred Years of Thomism Aeterni Patris and Afterwards a Symposium
    One Hundred Years of Thomism Aeterni Patris and Afterwards A Symposium Edited By Victor B. Brezik, C.S.B, CENTER FOR THOMISTIC STUDIES University of St. Thomas Houston, Texas 77006 ~ NIHIL OBSTAT: ReverendJamesK. Contents Farge, C.S.B. Censor Deputatus INTRODUCTION . 1 IMPRIMATUR: LOOKING AT THE PAST . 5 Most Reverend John L. Morkovsky, S.T.D. A Remembrance Of Pope Leo XIII: The Encyclical Aeterni Patris, Leonard E. Boyle,O.P. 7 Bishop of Galveston-Houston Commentary, James A. Weisheipl, O.P. ..23 January 6, 1981 The Legacy Of Etienne Gilson, Armand A. Maurer,C.S.B . .28 The Legacy Of Jacques Maritain, Christian Philosopher, First Printing: April 1981 Donald A. Gallagher. .45 LOOKING AT THE PRESENT. .61 Copyright©1981 by The Center For Thomistic Studies Reflections On Christian Philosophy, All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or Ralph McInerny . .63 reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written Thomism And Today's Crisis In Moral Values, Michael permission, except in the case of brief quotations embodied in Bertram Crowe . .74 critical articles and reviews. For information, write to The Transcendental Thomism, A Critical Assessment, Center For Thomistic Studies, 3812 Montrose Boulevard, Robert J. Henle, S.J. 90 Houston, Texas 77006. LOOKING AT THE FUTURE. .117 Library of Congress catalog card number: 80-70377 Can St. Thomas Speak To The Modem World?, Leo Sweeney, S.J. .119 The Future Of Thomistic Metaphysics, ISBN 0-9605456-0-3 Joseph Owens, C.Ss.R. .142 EPILOGUE. .163 The New Center And The Intellectualism Of St. Thomas, Printed in the United States of America Vernon J.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Euthyphro and Meno
    Plato's Euthyphro and Meno Reading and Essays Questions Exeter College, Oxford University, HT13 Tutor: Simona Aimar E-mail: [email protected] Weekly Meetings: TBA General Information This is a syllabus for eight weeks work for the first-year course on Plato’s Meno and Euthyphro. Please email your assignments to me 24h before the tutorials. I am afraid that I will not be able to write comments on essays that are handed in later than this (unless – for exceptional reasons, e.g. illness – I have agreed to this beforehand). You are required to do at least five essays in the course of the term, plus one set of gobbets. You should each write an essay for the first tutorial. In week 7, you will write gobbets (comments on passages) instead of an essay. In any week when you do not do an essay/gobbets, you should do the reading and think about the question in advance of the tutorial, so that you are ready to discuss the essay question in the tutorial. We shall focus each week on one of the essays in the tutorial, alternating between you and the other student who will be attending the tutorials with you. If we are focusing on your essay, I’ll ask you to summarize it at the start of the tutorial. If we are focusing on someone else’s essay, you should have read her/his essay before the tutorial, and have spent some time thinking about whether you agree with it and how it might be improved.
    [Show full text]
  • Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza's Ethics
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza’s Ethics STEVEN NADLER I Descartes famously prided himself on the felicitous consequences of his philoso- phy for religion. In particular, he believed that by so separating the mind from the corruptible body, his radical substance dualism offered the best possible defense of and explanation for the immortality of the soul. “Our natural knowledge tells us that the mind is distinct from the body, and that it is a substance...And this entitles us to conclude that the mind, insofar as it can be known by natural phi- losophy, is immortal.”1 Though he cannot with certainty rule out the possibility that God has miraculously endowed the soul with “such a nature that its duration will come to an end simultaneously with the end of the body,” nonetheless, because the soul (unlike the human body, which is merely a collection of material parts) is a substance in its own right, and is not subject to the kind of decomposition to which the body is subject, it is by its nature immortal. When the body dies, the soul—which was only temporarily united with it—is to enjoy a separate existence. By contrast, Spinoza’s views on the immortality of the soul—like his views on many issues—are, at least in the eyes of most readers, notoriously difficult to fathom. One prominent scholar, in what seems to be a cry of frustration after having wrestled with the relevant propositions in Part Five of Ethics,claims that this part of the work is an “unmitigated and seemingly unmotivated disaster..
    [Show full text]
  • What Has Athens to Do with Mormonism?
    Utah State University DigitalCommons@USU Arrington Student Writing Award Winners Leonard J. Arrington Mormon History Lectures 12-2012 What has Athens to do with Mormonism? Benjamin Wade Harman Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/arrington_stwriting Part of the Religion Commons Recommended Citation Harman, Benjamin Wade, "What has Athens to do with Mormonism?" (2012). Arrington Student Writing Award Winners. Paper 9. https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/arrington_stwriting/9 This Essay is brought to you for free and open access by the Leonard J. Arrington Mormon History Lectures at DigitalCommons@USU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Arrington Student Writing Award Winners by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@USU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. What has Athens to do with Mormonism? Benjamin Wade Harman In his lecture, Terryl Givens presents one with a new way to approach the prophecy of Enoch that was received by Joseph Smith. Contained in this short narrative is a new, innovative conception about God that differs greatly from traditional Christianity. This notion is that of a passible deity, a God that is susceptible to feeling and emotion. It is a God who weeps, a God who is vulnerable and suffers emotional pain. God, as defined by the Christian creeds, is one who lacks passions.1 Givens, in drawing attention to the passible deity, is illuminating just a small portion of a much larger tension that exists between Mormonism and traditional Christianity. The God of Mormonism is not just a slight modification of the God of the creeds. Traditionally Christians, who now will be referred to as orthodox, have endorsed a view of deity that is more or less in line with the God of Classical Theism, or the God of the philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Theses Graduate Works 4-16-2012 Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis Recommended Citation Krista, Hyde Dawn, "Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife" (2012). Theses. 261. http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis/261 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Works at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Krista Hyde M.L.A., Washington University in St. Louis, 2010 B.A., Philosophy, Southeast Missouri State University – Cape Girardeau, 2003 A Thesis Submitted to The Graduate School at the University of Missouri – St. Louis in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts in Philosophy April 2012 Advisory Committee Gualtiero Piccinini, Ph.D. Chair Jon McGinnis, Ph.D. John Brunero, Ph.D. Copyright, Krista Hyde, 2012 Abstract Thomas Aquinas nearly succeeds in addressing the persistent problem of the mind-body relationship by redefining the human being as a body-soul (matter-form) composite. This redefinition makes the interaction problem of substance dualism inapplicable, because there is no soul “in” a body. However, he works around the mind- body problem only by sacrificing an immaterial afterlife, as well as the identity and separability of the soul after death. Additionally, Thomistic psychology has difficulty accounting for the transmission of universals, nor does it seem able to overcome the arguments for causal closure.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's "Euthyphro"
    24.231 Ethics – Handout 1 Plato, “The Euthyphro” I. Plato’s Dialogue Plato’s Question: What is it to be pious? - He is not looking for a list of things that are pious - He is not looking for a property that (even all) pious things have. Euthyphro’s (best?) answer: To be pious is to be loved by all the gods. Plato’s Argument against Euthyphro’s answer: Perhaps all and only those things/actions that are loved by the gods are pious. But why is that? Are pious things loved by the gods because they are pious, or are they pious because they are loved by the gods? Socrates and Euthyphro agree that they must be loved by the gods because they are pious. But, says Socrates, in that case, being pious cannot be the same thing as being god-beloved. Because something that is god-beloved is so because it is loved by the gods. But something that is pious isn’t so because it is loved by the gods; rather, it is loved by the gods because it is pious. Being loved by the gods causes god-belovedness, but being loved by the gods does not cause piety. So god-belovedness and piety cannot be the same thing. (This kind of argument will be relevant again in the selection from Moore that we’re reading for Wednesday.) II. The “Euthyphro Problem” Socrates’ question about whether what’s loved by the gods is pious because it is loved by them, or loved by them because it is pious, forms the lynchpin of an important contemporary debate about what moral philosophers call “Divine Command Theory.” According to DCT, morally good actions are good because they are commanded by God.
    [Show full text]
  • Saving Moral Realism: Against Blackburn's Projectivism
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 5-2015 Saving Moral Realism: Against Blackburn's Projectivism Paul James Cummins Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/895 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] SAVING MORAL REALISM: AGAINST BLACKBURN’S PROJECTIVISM BY PAUL J. CUMMINS A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2015 © 2015 Paul J. Cummins All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted by the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. David M. Rosenthal (Date) Chair of Examining Committee John Greenwood (Date) Executive Officer Steven M. Cahn Stefan Baumrin Rosamond Rhodes Supervisory Committee The City University of New York iii Abstract SAVING MORAL REALISM: AGAINST BLACKBURN’S PROJECTIVISM by Paul J. Cummins Adviser: Professor Steven M. Cahn In the argumentative dialectic between moral realists and non-cognitivist moral antirealists each side in the debate is typically thought to enjoy a different prima facie advantage over its rival. Moral realism gains plausibility from its truth-conditional semantics because it can explain the meaning of moral judgments on the same basis as ordinary propositions.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparativeurban Studies Project
    COMPARATIVE URBAN STUDIES PROJECT URBAN UPDATE September 2007 NO. 12 Cities and Fundamentalisms WRITTEN BY: Nezar AlSayyad, Professor of Architecture, Planning, and Urban History & Chair of the Center for Middle Eastern Studies, University of California at Berkeley; Mejgan Massoumi, Program Assistant, Comparative Urban Studies Project (2005-2007); Mrinalini Rajagopalan, Assistant Professor, Draper Faculty Fellow (The City), New York University. With the unanticipated resur- gence of religious and ethnic loy- alties across the world, commu- nities are returning to, reinvigo- rating, and giving new meaning to religions and their common practices. Islam, Christianity, Judaism, and Hinduism, among others, are experiencing new in- fl uxes of commitments and tra- ditions. These changes have been coupled with the breakdown of order and of state power under the neo-liberal economic para- Top Row, Left to Right: Salwa Ismail, Mrinalini Rajagopalan, Raka Ray, Blair Ruble, Renu Desai, Nezar AlSayyad. Bottom Row, Left to Right: digm of civil society which have Omri Elisha, Emily Gottreich, Mona Harb, Mejgan Massoumi. created vacuums in the provi- sion of social services. Religious groups in many countries around the world are increasingly providing those services left unattended to by state bureaucracies. The once sacred divide between church and COMPARATIVE URBAN STUDIES PROJECT state or the confi nement of religion to the pri- fundamentalisms in several parts of the world. The vate sphere is now being vigorously challenged systematic transformation of the urban landscape as radical religious groups not only gain ground through various strategies of religious funda- within sovereign nation-states but in fact forge mentalism has led to the redefi nition of minority enduring and powerful transnational connections space in many cities.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and the Art of Living Aristotle, Spinoza, Hegel
    Philosophy and the Art of Living Osher Life-Long Learning Institute (UC Irvine) 2010 The Masters of Reason and the Masters of Suspicion: Aristotle, Spinoza, Hegel Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Sartre When: Mondays for six weeks: November 1 ,8, 15, 22, 29, and Dec. 6. Where: Woodbridge Center, 4628 Barranca Pkwy. Irvine CA 92604 NOTES AND QUOTES: Aristotle: 384 BCE- 322 BCE (62 years): Reference: http://www.jcu.edu/philosophy/gensler/ms/arist-00.htm Theoretical Reason contemplates the nature of Reality. Practical Reason arranges the best means to accomplish one's ends in life, of which the final end is happiness. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/#IntVir Aristotle distinguishes two kinds of virtue (1103a1-10): those that pertain to the part of the soul that engages in reasoning (virtues of mind or intellect), and those that pertain to the part of the soul that cannot itself reason but is nonetheless capable of following reason (ethical virtues, virtues of character). Intellectual virtues are in turn divided into two sorts: those that pertain to theoretical reasoning, and those that pertain to practical thinking 1139a3-8). He organizes his material by first studying ethical virtue in general, then moving to a discussion of particular ethical virtues (temperance, courage, and so on), and finally completing his survey by considering the intellectual virtues (practical wisdom, theoretical wisdom, etc.). Life : Aristotle was born in northern Greece in 384 B.C. He was raised by a guardian after the death of his father, Nicomachus, who had been court physician to the king of Macedonia. Aristotle entered Plato's Academy at age 17.
    [Show full text]
  • Intellectualism in Aristotle
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1978 Intellectualism in Aristotle David Keyt University of Washington, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Keyt, David, "Intellectualism in Aristotle" (1978). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 87. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/87 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. INTELLECTUALISM IN ARISTOTLE David Keyt University of Washington 1978 I When Aristotle returns to the topic of happiness at the end of the Nicoma­ chean Ethics (X.6-8) presumably to give us his final and best thoughts on the matter, he says that perfect happiness (he. teleia eudaimonia) is theoretical activity (the�retik� energeia), that happiness and contemplation (theoria) are coextensive, and that the life of reason (ho kata ton � bios), also called 1 the philosophic or theoretical life (I.5.1095bl9, �.E. I . 4. 1215bl-2, �passim), is the happiest life (X. 7.1177al2-18, 1178a4-8, 8.ll 78b7-32). He goes on to say that the life in accordance with the other excellence (ho kata tl!'n allen areten bios)--namely, the life in accordance with practical wisdom and moral virtue, elsewhere called the political or practical life (I.
    [Show full text]
  • Can God's Goodness Save the Divine Command Theory
    CAN GOD’S GOODNESS SAVE THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY FROM EUTHYPHRO? JEREMY KOONS Georgetown University School of Foreign Service in Qatar Abstract. Recent defenders of the divine command theory like Adams and Alston have confronted the Euthyphro dilemma by arguing that although God’s commands make right actions right, God is morally perfect and hence would never issue unjust or immoral commandments. On their view, God’s nature is the standard of moral goodness, and God’s commands are the source of all obligation. I argue that this view of divine goodness fails because it strips God’s nature of any features that would make His goodness intelligible. An adequate solution to the Euthyphro dilemma may require that God be constrained by a standard of goodness that is external to Himself – itself a problematic proposal for many theists. The Euthyphro dilemma is often thought to present a fatal problem for the divine command theory (aka theological voluntarism). Are right acts commanded by God because they are right, or are they right because they are commanded by God? If the former, then there is a standard of right and wrong independent of God’s commands; God’s commands are not relevant in determining the content of morality. This option seems to compromise God’s sovereignty in an important way. But the second horn of the dilemma presents seemingly insurmountable problems, as well. First, if God’s commands make right actions right, and there is no standard of morality independent of God’s commands, then that seems to make morality arbitrary. Thus, murder is not wrong because it harms someone unjustly, but merely because God forbids it; there is (it seems) no good connection between reason and the wrongness of murder.
    [Show full text]