<<

's and

Reading and Essays Questions

Exeter College, Oxford University, HT13

Tutor: Simona Aimar

E-mail: [email protected]

Weekly Meetings: TBA

General Information

This is a syllabus for eight weeks work for the first-year course on Plato’s Meno and Euthyphro. Please email your assignments to me 24h before the tutorials. I am afraid that I will not be able to write comments on essays that are handed in later than this (unless – for exceptional , e.g. illness – I have agreed to this beforehand).

You are required to do at least five essays in the course of the term, plus one set of gobbets. You should each write an essay for the first tutorial. In week 7, you will write gobbets (comments on passages) instead of an essay. In any week when you do not do an essay/gobbets, you should do the reading and think about the question in advance of the tutorial, so that you are ready to discuss the essay question in the tutorial.

We shall focus each week on one of the essays in the tutorial, alternating between you and the other student who will be attending the tutorials with you. If we are focusing on your essay, I’ll ask you to summarize it at the start of the tutorial. If we are focusing on someone else’s essay, you should have read her/his essay before the tutorial, and have spent some time thinking about whether you agree with it and how it might be improved.

You will do a collection on this paper at the beginning of MT.

Please do bring copies of the relevant text (Euthyphro and/or Meno) to the tutorials.

Some notes on how to approach the readings1

It is essential to read, and think carefully about, the two dialogues: Meno and Euthyphro. I have also suggested some ‘optional secondary reading’. Doing some of these readings will be helpful. I have starred the things I particularly recommend. In general Dominic Scott’s book Plato’s Meno is a very , recent, book on the Meno. In philosophy, however, it is always important to spend quite a bit of time thinking carefully about the questions. So don’t get too bogged down in the reading. If it starts to be the case that you are spending more time trying to understand what one of the secondary authors says than trying to understand Plato, then you should put the secondary author aside and just try to think for yourself about what Plato says.

1 These notes benefited from Ursula Coope’s own writings on teaching philosophy.

1 (There’s a longer reading list, available on the web from the philosophy faculty web site – go to ‘undergraduates’ then ‘reading lists’ in Weblearn.)

Some notes on writing philosophy essays

In commenting on philosophy essays, tutors often find themselves saying that the student needs to write more clearly. It can be hard to know what this means when you are just beginning. The point is that, although in philosophy we often deal with big and difficult questions, in order to make progress with them we need to try to answer them in as simple and down-to-earth a way as possible. (This is what professional philosophers are trying – perhaps not always very successfully – to do, not simply what you are being asked to do.)

One way to do this, sometimes, is to try to give concrete examples when you are making a general point. So, for example, suppose I claim that it is possible to understand a word without being able to define it. I might then give an example: ‘for example, I can’t define the word red, but I know what ‘red’ means, in the sense that I can pick out red objects from objects of other colours’. Notice how giving this example forced me to think a bit more about the general claim I was making: in what sense do I understand what ‘red’ means? (In giving the example I spelt this out by saying that I could pick out red objects. But is the fact that I can do this really enough to show that I know what ‘red’ means?)

Another thing that is different about philosophy essays, is that you are typically asked not only to explain Plato’s views, but also to assess them in some way. In the question for the first week, for instance, you are asked whether a certain claim can be defended against ’s objections. To answer this, you need first to understand what Socrates’ objections are (this itself is not an easy task), but you are also asked how one might reply to Socrates’ objections. That requires you to think for yourself about whether Socrates’ arguments are good ones, how you might answer them (and perhaps also even, how he might reply to your answer). In the second week, I have asked you to write an essay which answers three questions. The first question is about what Socrates says in the Meno and the Euthyprho, but the other two questions require you to think critically about the assumptions that lie behind what he says.

Good philosophy essays need not be long. About 1000-1500 words is usually enough.

On the web, there is some very good advice about writing philosophy from a distinguished philosopher in the US: http://www.jimpryor.net/teaching/guidelines/writing.html I recommend that you read this, but bear in mind that not everything he says is relevant to you: he is writing for US students who are producing finished term papers for continuous assessment. You are producing less finished weekly tutorial papers for us to discuss (so you don’t need to write multiple drafts etc).

Requirements for the different versions of mods

Euthyphro: Greek text in OCT, ed. E.A. Duke et al. (Oxford 1995). The set translation is in The Last Days of Socrates, tr. Tredennick & Tarrant (Penguin revised 1993). Meno: Greek text in OCT, ed. J. Burnet (Oxford 1903). Set translation: Meno in R.W. Sharples Plato: Meno (Aris & Phillips 1985): introduction, text, translation, and commentary.

2 If you are doing Course IA or IC you are expected to have read Meno in Greek and Euthyphro in English. If you are doing IIA, you are expected to read both works in translation. If you are taking IB or IIB, you are expected to have read Meno 70a-86d2 in Greek and the rest of Meno and Euthyphro in English.

Some notes on how to write Gobbets (from the Lit Hum handbook) A gobbet is a short commentary on a passage. For philosophy Gobbets, the first requirement is to identify the argumentative context of the passage, e.g. `This passage occurs in Socrates' response to Thrasymachus' claim that the ruler properly so-called is expert in promoting his own advantage; in reply Socrates urges that all expertise aims to promote the advantage of that on which the expertise is exercised, hence the expert ruler must aim to promote, not his own advantage, but that of the subject'. You should then set out the specific contribution of the passage to the argumentative context, e.g. a sub-argument (in which case the steps of the argument should be set out), or a distinction (in which case you should clearly state what is being distinguished from what), or the introduction of some key concept, which should be clearly elucidated. Where appropriate, elucidation should be followed by criticism; thus if the passage contains a fallacious or unsound argument, or a faulty distinction, the flaw should be briefly identified. If the significance of the passage goes beyond the immediate argumentative context (e.g. in introducing a concept which is important for a wider range of contexts) that wider significance should be indicated. Wider significance may be internal to the work as a whole, or may extend beyond it, for instance by relating to some theme central to the thought of the author (such as Plato's or 's Categories) or to some important topic in modern philosophy. Your primary focus in philosophy gobbets should be on argumentative and conceptual content. Details of sentence construction, vocabulary etc should be discussed only in so far as they affect the content thus conceived. The same goes for the identification of persons etc named in the passage; note that where the passage is taken from a Platonic dialogue it will usually be relevant to identify the speaker(s). It is vitally important to observe the time constraints imposed by the number of passages to be translated and commented on. Brevity, relevance and lucidity are crucial. It is especially important not to be carried away in expounding the wider significance of the passage (see above); a gobbet should not expand into an essay on the Theory of Forms or the problem of universals. Use your own judgement on how much you can afford to put in.

Topics and Readings

Week 1. Socrates’ Arguments against Euthyphro’s of Piety

This week we look at what Socrates is trying to do in the Euthyphro. What is Socrates’s method? Why does he seek definitions of ethical concepts? What kind of definitions is he looking for? As you read Plato's text, I would recommend keeping track of each of Euthyphro's definions of piety. For each definition, try and think about whether it fails to satisfy Socrates, and why. What would Socrates consider a successful definition of piety? Why does he think it is important to find such definition? More generally, what is the so-called Socratic 'elenchus'?

Essay Question Could the definition of ‘the holy’ as ‘what is approved of by all the gods’ be defended against Socrates’ objections?

3 Main Reading (1) Read the Euthyphro carefully.

Optional secondary readings (2) Benson, H. '', in Daniel Morrison (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Socrates (CUP: Cambridge, 2011), pp. 179-200. (3) *Geach, P. ‘Plato’s Euthyphro: An Analysis and Commentary’, Monist 50 (1966), 369-82 (4) Cohen, S. M. ‘Socrates on the Definition of Piety: Euthyphro 10A-11B’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 9 (1971), 1-13; reprinted in Vlastos (ed.), Socrates (5) *Patzig, G. ‘Logic in the “Euthyphro”’, in S.M. Stern, A. Hourani, and V. Brown (eds), Islamic Philosophy and the Classical Tradition (Cassirer 1972) -- an offprint of this is available at the Philosophy Library (shelf-mark O/P PAZ 1).

Optional background reading (6) Woodruff, P. 'Plato's Shorter Ethical Works', in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:

Week 2. Socratic definition This week we take a closer look at one putative problem with Socrates’s demand for definitions. Socrates claims that Euthyphro cannot know whether his action is piuous until he knows what piety is. Similarly, he claims that he and Meno cannot know whether is teachable until they know what virtue is. Try and spell out what grounds these claims, for Socrates. Do they depend on some specific view of ? Is this a good view? How does this connect with Socrates's demand for definitions?

Essay Questions What requirements does Socrates impose on definition in the Euthyphro and the Meno? Is it true that, if a word has meaning, it must be definable in this way? Are there any definitions that satisfy these requirements?

Main Readings (1) * Euthyphro. (2) * Meno 70a-80e, 86d-e.

Optional readings (2) Crombie, I. M, pp. 90-3 of ‘Socratic Definition’, Paideia 1976 (Special Plato Issue); reprinted as pp. 187-92 of Day, Plato’s Meno in Focus. (3) * Vlastos, G. ‘What Did Socrates Understand by his “What is F?” Question?’, in Vlastos, Platonic Studies (Princeton 1981). (4) * Nehamas, A. Part I of ‘Meno’s and Socrates as a Teacher’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3 (1985), 1-30; reprinted in Benson (ed.), Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates, and in J. Day, Plato’s Meno in Focus. (5) Irwin, T. Plato's (OUP: Oxford, 1995), Sections 12-18, and 88-91. (6) Brickhouse, T. and Smith, N. The Philosophy of Socrates (Westview Press: Oxford, 2000), Chapter 3. (7) Wolfsdorf, D. 'The Socratic Fallacy and the Epistemological Priority of Definitional Knowledge', in Apeiron 31 (2011), pp. 35-68). [This is a very thorough examination of the Socratic Fallacy, with good summaries of the various positions commentators have taken.]

4 Week 3. Desire and the good

In a number of Platos' dialogues, Socrates makes some extremely interesting, and controversial, psychological claims. This week we will be examining what the Meno tells us about this psychological theory and how it relates to Socrates's broader philosophical beliefs.

Essay Question Explain Socrates’ argument that no one desires what is bad. If you were in Meno’s position, how might you answer it? Could Socrates defend his argument against your reply?

Main Reading (1) Meno 77b-78c.

Optional readings (2) * Plato's , 352a-358e. (3) * Plato's , 467c-468e. [How is this argument similar to Meno 77c-78b? How is it different? Compare, in particular, 77d7-e4]. (4) Bobonich, C. 'Socrates and ', in The Cambridge Companion to Socrates, pp 293- 332. [An excellent introduction to Socratic psychology – longish, but also easy to read.] (3) Santas, G. X. ‘The Socratic ’, Philosophical Review 73 (1964), 147-64; reprinted with revisions as Chapter 6 of his Socrates. (4) Walsh, J. J. Aristotle’s Conception of Moral Weakness (Columbia 1964), ch. 1; reprinted as ‘The Socratic Denial of Akrasia’, in Vlastos (ed.), The Philosophy of Socrates. (5) Irwin, T. Plato’s Moral Theory (Oxford 1977), pp. 78-82. (6) * Scott, D. Plato’s Meno, ch4.

Week 4. Meno’s Paradox

This week we look at Meno's Paradox, which is supposed to show that inquiry is impossible. Carefully consider and compare Meno's (80d6-8) and Socrates's (80e1-5) formulations of the paradox. Do they differ significantly? Does any of them count as a paradox? Why? In your essay, make clear what definition of 'paradox' you are working with.

Essay Question ‘Which of the things that you don’t know will you suppose that it is, when you are searching for it? And even if you do come across it, how are you going to know that this is the thing you didn’t know?’ (Meno, 80d6-8). Is either of these a good for thinking that enquiry is impossible?

Main Reading (1) Meno 79e-86c.

Optional readings (2) * Fine, G. ‘Inquiry in the Meno’ in Kraut (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Plato. (3) * Nehemas, A. ‘Meno’s paradox and Socrates as a teacher’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 3, 1985. Reprinted in Jane Day (ed.), Plato’s Meno in Focus. (4) * Scott, D. Plato’s Meno, Part 2, Chapters 6 and 7.

5 Week 5. The Theory of Recollection and the of the Soul

This week we consider Plato's theory of recollection. What's the theory? How does it relate to Meno's paradox? Does it imply that the soul is immortal? Or does it presuppose that the soul is immortal? Why?

Essay Question ‘The experiment with the slave proves that we have the capacity for knowledge, but not that the soul is immortal.’ Discuss.

Main Reading (1) Meno 81a-86c.

Optional readings (2) Plato's 723-84b and 245c-249d [Two statements of the theory of recollection; compare them with the Meno's.] (3) Readings for last week. (4) * Scott, D. Plato’s Meno, Part 2, Chapters 8-10.

Week 6. Knowledge (Episteme) and Opinion ()

A common, although controversial, modern definition of knowledge is “justified, true ”. A true belief falls short of knowledge, then, if it lacks adequate justification. At first glance, Socrates' view that the belief becomes knowledge only when it is tied down by an “aitias logismos” (98a) seems quite close to this modern account. This week we will consider whether or not, on closer inspection, this is indeed the case.

Essay Question What is the role, in the Meno, of the distinction between knowledge and true belief? Does the Meno provide an adequate account of this distinction?

Main Reading (1) Meno 85b-86c, 96d-end.

Optional readings (2) Burnyeat, M. ‘Socrates and the jury: paradoxes in Plato’s distinction between knowledge and true belief’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Suppl, v. 54 (1980), pp. 173-91. [Burnyeat argues that Plato's distinction is between true belief and understanding, where the latter requires more than justification (e.g. I have a justified, true belief that Einstein's theory of relativity is true, but I don't understand it).] (3) *Scott, D. Plato’s Meno, Chapter 14. (4) Fine, G. 'Knowledge and True Belief in the Meno', in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27 (Winter 2004), pp. 41-81. [Fine argues that knowledge in the Meno is closer to justified true belief than is often assumed.]

Week 7. Virtue () and Knowledge (Episteme)

Assignment for this week Two gobbets (to be distributed nearer the time).

6

Question to think about Does the Meno provide any good arguments for or against the view that virtue is knowledge?

Main Reading (1) Meno 86c-96d.

Optional readings (2) Plato's 194c-201c, Gorgias 466a-479d, and Protagoras 352a-362a. (3) Devereux, D. T. ‘Nature and Teaching in Plato’s Meno’, in 23 (1978), pp. 118-26. (4) * Wilkes, K. V. ‘Conclusions in the Meno’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 61 (1979), pp. 143-53; reprinted in Day, Plato’s Meno in Focus. (5) T. Irwin Plato’s Ethics, sections 96-103.

Week 8. Hypotheses and Philosophical Method in the Meno

This week we will consider what philosophical method is in play in the Meno, if any.

Essay Question EITHER What should we conclude from the Meno about the teachability of virtue? OR How seriously should we take the suggestion at the end of the Meno that civic excellence is a matter of 'divine dispensation'?

Main Reading (1) Meno 86c-96d.

Optional readings (2) * Wilkes, K. V. ‘Conclusions in the Meno’, listed under “Week 7” above. (3) * D. Scott Plato’s Meno, chapters 12-13.

7