Saving Moral Realism: Against Blackburn's Projectivism
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
1 the Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation Adam Lerner Some People Care
The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation Adam Lerner Some people care about doing the right thing as such. They want to do the right thing under that description. These people have what has come to be known as a de dicto desire to do what is right.1 Some people who have a desire to do what’s right as such desire to do what’s right only as a means. They want to do the right thing in order to avoid punishment, or as a way of doing what God or their mother would approve of, or because it would be a sign that they are predestined for salvation. But many care about doing the right thing for its own sake: because it’s the right thing. They have a final desire to do what’s right as such. This desire is an instance of what I will call pure moral motivation (PMM).2 Other instances of PMM include the desire to avoid doing what’s wrong as such, the desire to promote what’s good as such, and the desire to prevent what’s bad as such. Contemporary views in metaethics have been built to satisfy familiar desiderata: accommodating Moorean open questions, explaining the connection between moral judgment and moral motivation, accounting for the supervenience of the moral on the non-moral, and many others. In this paper, I introduce a new desideratum: vindicating the rationality of PMM. I argue that PMM is often rational, and that any adequate view must accommodate this fact. The puzzle of PMM is to explain how that can be done. -
Moral Philosophy in Question
PHILOSOPHY AND WORLD PROBLEMS-Vol . I-Moral Philosophy In Question-John McMurtry MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN QUESTION John McMurtry Department of Philosophy, University of Guelph, Guelph NIG 2W1, Canada Keywords: addiction, aesthetics, analysis, axiology, deep ecology, desire theory, emotivism, evil, intrinsic value, idealism, life value, market theory, Marxian analysis, meta-ethics, moral blindness, moral philosophy, needs, objective values, social value system. Contents 3.1. The Underlying Problem of Moral Philosophy: Decoupling from the Life-Ground 3.2. The Conventional Tendency: Prescribing and Punishing Without Good Reason 3.3. The Professional Tendency: Moral Philosophy without Life Substance 3.4. Evaluating Social Value Systems: Off-Limits Even to Marxian Thought 3.5. What the Organism Wants: Desire Theory and its Fatal Flaw 3.6. The Paradox of Market Success: Magnitude of Desire Objects Multiplies Disvalues 3.7. Life-Value versus Desire-Value: The Turning Point of Value Judgment 3.8. Desire Theory Lacks Moral Resources to Rule out Destructive Addictions 3.9. The Logic of Moral Disaster: Freedom and Democracy as Multiplied Wants 3.10. Correct Love: From Subjective Desires to Transcendental Ideals 3.11. What We Don’t See: The Common Structure of Moral Blindness 3.12. Avoiding the Problem: Invaliding Moral Principles as Such 3.13. Ruling out Objective Values by Definition: The Life-Ground Counter Argument 3.14. Towards Value System Re-Grounding: The Needs Criterion of Value 3.15. Going Deeper: Understanding the Truth and the Limits of a Needs -
1 Moral Realism Geoffrey Sayre-Mccord UNC/Chapel Hill
Moral Realism facts that peoples’ moral judgments are true or false, and that the facts being what they are (and so the judgments being true, when they are) is not merely a Geoffrey Sayre-McCord reflection of our thinking the facts are one way or another. That is, moral facts UNC/Chapel Hill are what they are even when we see them incorrectly or not at all. Introduction Moral realists thus all share the view that there are moral facts in light of People come, early and easily, to think in moral terms: to see many things which our moral judgments prove to be true or false. Yet they needn’t, and as good or bad, to view various options as right or wrong, to think of particular don’t, all share any particular view about what those facts are, and they might distributions as fair or unfair, to consider certain people virtuous and others well not be confident of any view at all. When it comes to moral matters, there vicious.[1] What they think, when they are thinking in these terms, often has a is no less disagreement among realists than among people at large and no large impact on their decisions and actions as well as on their responses to what incompatibility between being a realist and thinking oneself not in a good others do. People forego attractive possibilities when they think pursuing them position to know what the facts are. would be wrong, they push themselves to face death if they think it their duty, Furthermore, being a realist is compatible with holding a truly radical view they go to trouble to raise their kids to be virtuous, and they pursue things they of the moral facts. -
Wittgenstein, Wright, Rorty and Minimalism Author(S): Simon Blackburn Source: Mind , Jan., 1998, Vol
Wittgenstein, Wright, Rorty and Minimalism Author(s): Simon Blackburn Source: Mind , Jan., 1998, Vol. 107, No. 425 (Jan., 1998), pp. 157-181 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Mind Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.com/stable/2659811 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Oxford University Press and are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Mon, 29 Jun 2020 15:38:47 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms SYMPOSIUM: REALISMAND TRUTH Wittgenstein, Wright, Rorty and Minimalism SIMON BLACKBURN 1. Introduction William James said that sometimes detailed philosophical argument is irrelevant. Once a current of thought is really under way, trying to oppose it with argument is like planting a stick in a river to try to alter its course: ''round your obstacle flows the water and 'gets there just the same"' (James 1909, p. 55). He thought pragmatism was such a river. There is a contemporary river that sometimes calls itself pragmatism, although other titles are probably better. At any rate it is the denial of differences, the cel- ebration of the seamless web of language, the soothing away of distinc- tions, whether of primary versus secondary, fact versus value, description versus expression, or of any other significant kind. -
607 RN Johnson and M. Smith (Eds.) the Range and Influence of Simon Blackburn's Work Is Reflected in The
Book Reviews 607 R.N. Johnson and M. Smith (eds.) Passions and Projections: Themes from the Philosophy of Simon Blackburn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), xx + 276 pages. isbn: 9780198723172. Hardback: $65.00. The range and influence of Simon Blackburn’s work is reflected in the the- matic variety of the contributions to this excellent volume edited by Robert N. Johnson and Michael Smith. The quality of the essays is consistently high, and together they provide a comprehensive, in-depth treatment of Black- burn’s many original and controversial ideas. The book is divided in two parts: Metaphysics and Epistemology (eight chapters), and Metaethics and Moral Psychology (six chapters). I will discuss one chapter below, but first let me of- fer a brief overview of the other essays. Louise Antony explores the relation between her position and Blackburn’s when it comes to giving an account of folk psychology, and suggests that their main disagreement concerns the need for a “language of thought” hypothesis. Helen Beebee compares Blackburn’s Humean account of causation, on which causal claims express inferential commitments, with a different projectivist view, proposed by Frank Ramsey and Huw Price, according to which causal discourse encodes the epistemic standpoint of a deliberating agent. Frank Jackson uses a possible worlds framework to give an account of the content of singular thought, a topic explored by Blackburn in Spreading the Word (Oxford University Press, 1984). Carrie Jenkins argues that quasi-realists about any domain of thought need to account for the possibility of knowledge in that domain, and that her own explanation-based epistemology might be useful in addressing this challenge. -
Introduction to Philosophy Paul Muench University of Montana - Missoula, [email protected]
University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Syllabi Course Syllabi Fall 9-1-2018 PHL 101Y.01: Introduction to Philosophy Paul Muench University of Montana - Missoula, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/syllabi Recommended Citation Muench, Paul, "PHL 101Y.01: Introduction to Philosophy" (2018). Syllabi. 8293. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/syllabi/8293 This Syllabus is brought to you for free and open access by the Course Syllabi at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Syllabi by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Philosophy 101Y/L University of Montana Prof. Paul Muench (pronounced “Minch”) Fall 2018 T.A.: Mason Voehl office: LA 151 office hours: Tue, 11-12; Wed, 1-3; Thu, 2-3; or by appointment mailbox: LA 152 email: office phone: (406) 243-2351 ___________________________________________________________________________________ Introduction to Philosophy Monday/Wednesday/Friday, 10-10:50 a.m., LA 11 Course Objectives This course will introduce you to some of the questions that philosophers have traditionally asked (questions about what we know and how we know it, about what is real, about what is valuable, and about how one should live) and to some of the answers they have proposed. It will also introduce you to some of the skills and methods used in philosophical inquiry, skills and methods that may be useful in other sorts of inquiries as well. These include the ability to analyze and criticize arguments; the ability to articulate one’s own views and to support them with reasoned arguments; and the ability to read a text carefully, sympathetically, and critically. -
Quasi-Realism in Moral Philosophy an Interview with Simon Blackburn
QUASI-REALISM IN MORAL PHILOSOPHY An interview with SIMON BLACKBURN By Darlei Dall´Agnol ethic@ - Would you, please, introduce yourself to the readers of ethic@ and tell us why you chose to study philosophy and what your main interests in it are? I chose to study philosophy because I was bored with the natural sciences of the school. I went up to Cambridge, people expected me to read natural sciences and so, physics, chemistry. But I decided that my friends in art subjects were having a much better time. They were sitting around discussing novels, while I was sitting in a laboratory learning about properties. I wanted to change to an art subject. The admission teacher said that since I’ve been in sciences, I wouldn’t like English because of all its topics, because it was not vigorous. Philosophy was the thing for me. I was really directed into it. But when I got up to Cambridge, I had a wonderful tutor, a man called Casemir Lewy. He was the editor of G. E. Moore. He made all these fascinating remarks about philosophy. So, I became a philosopher by accident. It was luck that I went to that college, that tutor, that direction. I could have been anything, but I would probably be a lawyer. ethic@ - You have been developing over the years a metaphysical program known as “quasi-realism”. How would you explain it in a few words to our readers? I think, the easiest way to understand my program is if we look back to people likeA.J.Ayer,Language, truth and logic, Charles Stevenson, Ethics and language,and the expressivist or emotivist traditions in ethics. -
When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’S Development Into a Normative Ideal
When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’s Development into a Normative Ideal A Senior Honor Thesis Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with distinction in Political Science in the College of Social and Behavioral Sciences by Benjamin T. Jones The Ohio State University December 10, 2006 Project Advisors: John M. Parrish, Department of Political Science (Loyola Marymount University) Michael A. Neblo, Department of Political Science (The Ohio State University) Table of Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements iii Introduction 1 The Paradox at the Heart of Altruism 4 Defining Altruism and Normativity 6 What Are We Looking For? 11 Roadmap of What’s to Come 14 Part I Towards a Problem: The Ancient Debate over Public Life 17 Eudaimonia and Ancient Ethics 18 Plato and Aristotle 24 Epicurus and the Stoics 40 A Solution from an Unlikely Source 47 Augustine’s Reconciliation of the Two Cities 55 Conclusion 63 Part II Self-Love’s Fall from Grace: How Normative Altruism Developed out of the Augustinian Tradition 65 Entangled in Self-love: Augustine’s Normative Argument 67 Augustine Goes Secular 75 Kant’s Problematic Solution 83 Reworking Kant—And Altruism 89 Conclusion 91 Part III The Problems with Normative Altruism 93 Two Conceptions of Altruism 93 Evidence for Altruism on a Descriptive Level 95 Motivational Barriers to Normative Altruism 113 Changing the Way We Talk About Altruism 121 Conclusion 126 Bibliography 131 i Abstract In contemporary moral philosophy, altruism holds a place of prominence. Although a complex idea, the term seeps into everyday discourse, by no means confined to the esoteric language of philosophers and psychologists. -
The Concept of Moral Blindness
Jacob Dahl RENDTORFF Roskilde University, Denmark EVIL IN ORGANIZATIONS AND CORPORATIONS: THE CONCEPT OF MORAL BLINDNESS Summary. This paper provides an analysis of evil in corporations and organizations by presenting the concept of moral blindness in relation to business organizations and public administration on the basis of the concept of administrative evil as it has been developed by Hannah Arendt and her followers. After a discussion of the definition of the concept from Hannah Arendt’s to Philip Zimbardo’s social psychology, the paper gives a general definition of the concept as the basis for application and case studies in public administration and private business corporations. Keywords: Evil, moral blindness, ethics, social roles, organizational bureaucracy ZŁO W ORGANIZACJACH I KORPORACJACH: KONCEPCJA ŚLEPOTY MORALNEJ Streszczenie. W artykule zaprezentowano analizę zła w korporacjach i organiza- cjach, przedstawiając koncepcję ślepoty moralnej w odniesieniu do organizacji biznesowych i administracji publicznej, na podstawie koncepcji zła administra- cyjnego, zgodnie z teorią Hannah Arendt i jej zwolenników. Po dyskusji definicji koncepcji od Hannah Arendt do psychologii społecznej Philipa Zimbardo, artykuł przedstawia ogólną definicję pojęcia ślepoty moralnej jako podstawy dla wniosków i analiz przypadków w administracji publicznej oraz w przedsiębiorstwach prywatnych. Słowa kluczowe: zło, ślepota moralna, etyka, role społeczne, biurokracja organizacyjna 96 J.D. Rendtorff 1. Introduction Evil or harm is arguably something that is often caused by the structure of organizations and institutions. We can refer to military institutions, public administrations and private corporations. One definition of administrative evil is the following: “So evil is really about the exercise of power to inflict harm, hurt, and destruction of others individually or collectively and it occurs on the institutional scale, to commit crimes against humanity” (Adams, Balafour, 2009: xv). -
Escribir El Título Del Artículo
CON-TEXTOS KANTIANOS. International Journal of Philosophy N.o 11, Junio 2020, pp. 313-335 ISSN: 2386-7655 Doi: 10.5281/zenodo.3864972 Kantian Transcendental Pessimism and Jamesian Empirical Meliorism SAMI PIHLSTRÖM• University of Helsinki, Finland Abstract Kant’s philosophy was an important background for the pragmatist tradition, even though some of the major classical pragmatists, especially William James, were unwilling to acknowledge their debt to Kant. This essay considers the relation between Kant and James from the perspective of their conceptions of the human condition. In particular, I examine their shared pessimism, employing Vanden Auweele’s (2019) recent analysis of Kant’s pessimism and arguing that this is required by James’s meliorism (which is put forward as a middle-ground option between optimism and pessimism). A comparative inquiry into Kant’s and James’s views on the relation between ethics and religion is provided against this background of their shared philosophical anthropology. Keywords James, Kant, meliorism, pessimism, religion Abstrakti Kantin filosofia toimi tärkeänä vaikuttimena pragmatistiselle traditiolle, vaikka moni klassinen pragmatisti, William James erityisesti, ei ollut halukas tunnustamaan velkaansa Kantille. Artikkelissa tarkastellaan Kantin ja Jamesin ajattelun välistä suhdetta heidän ihmisyyttä koskevien • Sami Pihlström is (since 2014) Professor of Philosophy of Religion at the University of Helsinki, Finland. He is currently also the President of the Philosophical Society of Finland, as well as the Chair of the Research Council for Culture and Society at the Academy of Finland. He was previously (2009-2015) the Director of the Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies. He has since the 1990s published widely on pragmatism, realism, ethics, metaphysics, and philosophy of religion. -
From Neural 'Is' to Moral 'Ought'
PERSPECTIVES 34. Churchland, P. S. Brain-wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy Acknowledgements usual Humean and Moorean reasons. (MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 2002). I thank P. M. Churchland and P. S. Churchland for their close 35. Churchland, P. M. Towards a cognitive neurobiology of reading of the manuscript and invaluable advice about its struc- Contemporary proponents of naturalized the moral virtues. Topoi 17, 83–96 (1998). ture and content. In addition, J. Greene’s sceptical remarks were ethics are aware of these objections, but in my 36. Wallis, J. D., Anderson, K. C. & Miller, E. K. Single extremely helpful. J. Moll also provided useful preprints of his neurons in prefrontal cortex encode abstract rules. team’s work in this area. opinion their theories do not adequately meet Nature 411, 953–956 (2001). them. Casebeer, for example, examines recent 37. Casebeer, W. D. & Churchland, P. S. The neural mechanisms of moral cognition: a multiple-aspect Online links work in neuroscientific moral psychology and approach to moral judgment and decision-making. Biol. finds that actual moral decision-making looks Philos. 18, 169–194 (2003). FURTHER INFORMATION 8 38. Moreno, J. D. Neuroethics: an agenda for neuroscience MIT Encyclopedia of Cognitive Sciences: more like what Aristotle recommends and and society. Nature Rev. Neurosci. 4, 149–153 (2003). http://cognet.mit.edu/MITECS/ less like what Kant9 and Mill10 recommend. 39. Cacioppo, J. T. et al. (eds) Foundations in Social Neuro- limbic system | moral psychology | social cognition | theory of science (MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 2002). mind From this he concludes that the available 40. Rachels, J. -
Arisotelian and Confucian Cultures.Of Authority
\l \ (Oy, I UNIVERSITY OF HAWAII LIBRARY ARISOTELIAN AND CONFUCIAN CULTURES.OF AUTHORITY: JUSTIFYING MORAL NORMS BY APPEAL TO THE AUTHORITY OF EXEMPLARY PERSONS A THESIS SUBMmED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2005 By Thorian Rane Harris Thesis Committee: Roger Ames, Chairperson Eliot Deutsch Thomas Jackson James Tiles Dedicated to my own exemplars: CLAUDIA CLOSE and JOCELYN HOY, jor modeling wonder and the teaching ojphilosophy; and CASSANDRA SWETT, jor modeling jriendship. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract '" '" v Chapter One: Norms and the Normative Question 1 Chapter Two: Aristotle, Confucius, and the Normative Question........................ 26 Section One: How Aristotle Answers the Normative Question............... 27 Section Two: How Confucius Answers the Normative Question 46 Section Three: Summary 69 Chapter Three: The Authority of Exemplary Persons 74 Section One: Exemplary Persons and Moral Blindness '" 74 Section Two: The Authority of Aristotelian and Confucian Exemplary Persons. .. 86 Literature Cited................................................................................. 102 iv Abstract This thesis attempts to argue that exemplary persons-teachers, parents, etc.-are norms in their own right. They do not merely exemplify virtues or demonstrate a life according to duty, nor are they simply the embodiment of a bunch of moral principles. Rather, they are a unique variety of norm altogether, and, as Aristotle and Confucius illustrate, can be a moral system's most basic norm-that is, the source ofjustification for all other norms, and the source of their own normative justification. To defend these claims I begin, in the first chapter, by discussing the meaning of the word "norm," and then turn to a consideration of the requirements for justifying moral norms.