Roy Bhaskar's Core Critical Realism and the Philosophy of Nancy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Roy Bhaskar's Core Critical Realism and the Philosophy of Nancy Roy Bhaskar’s Core Critical Realism and the Philosophy of Nancy Cartwright: Common Ground Radu Andrei Pârvulescu* March 15, 2020 Abstract This paper compares Roy Bhaskar’s core critical realism with the philosophy of science of Nancy Cartwright. It argues for either profound similarity or exact correspondence between the two on a number of key elements: strong realism, depth ontology, closed and open systems, intransitive and transitive dimensions of science, philosophical method, emergence and stratification, and explanatory critique. Through detailed, side-by-side textual comparison this paper provides a rigorous first step for critically engaging, and ultimately integrating, two influential and highly complimentary philosophies of science. keywords: Bhaskar; Cartwright; critical realism; core critical realism; nomological pluralism Introduction† Roy Bhaskar and Nancy Cartwright have proven to be influential philosophers of science in the late 20th and early 21st century. Differences in style, ambition, and institutional location have unfortunately prevented systematic comparison of their works, obscuring deep similarities; indeed, when reading Cartwright one often feels that she is a Bhaskarian, and vice versa. This agreement on fundamentals holds the promise of integrating these two highly complimentary philosophies, to the mutual benefit of each. First however, one must rigorously show that there is sufficient common ground for an honest and happy marriage. This exegetical essay compares the early philosophy of Roy Bhaskar (i.e. “core critical realism”) with most of the philosophy of Nancy Cartwright. I have limited myself to primary texts by the authors, with the exception of Andrew Collier’s summary of the early Bhaskar, which features clearer statements (with page-level citations) of key points in core critical realism than Bhaskar’s own, usually dense and neologism-heavy, prose. As of this writing there is, unfortunately, no similar introduction to the work of Cartwright. The citing convention I use is (text-acronym:page): (RST:57) means “page fifty-seven in A Realist Theory of Science.” The texts I reference are: * Radu Andrei Pârvulescu is a doctoral candidate in the Department of Sociology at Cornell University. Address correspondence to Radu Andrei Pârvulescu, Department of Sociology, Uris Hall, 109 Tower Road, Ithaca, NY, 14850, USA; email: [email protected]. † I would like to thank Steven Rytina for pointing out both the fundamental similarity between the philosophies of Bhaskar and Cartwright and the lack of communication between the two. The idea was his, the execution is mine, along with all shortcomings. I would also like to thank participants at a session of the Theory section of the European Sociological Association conference in Manchester, August 2019, where an earlier version of this paper was presented. Special thanks go to Johannes Jäger for encouragement and advice on further reading. Radu Andrei Pârvulescu 1 Early Bhaskar/Core Critical Realism Cartwright • A Realist Theory of Science (1975) – RST • Nature’s Capacities and Their • The Possibility of Naturalism (1998 Measurement (1989) – NCTM [1979]) – PN • The Dappled World: A Study of the • Scientific Realism and Human Boundaries of Science (1999) – DW Emancipation (1986) – SRHE • Hunting Causes and Using Them: • Critical Realism: An Introduction to Roy Approaches in Philosophy and Economics Bhaskar's Philosophy, by Andrew Collier (2007) – HCUT (1994) – AC • Evidence Based Policy: A Practical Guide to Doing It Better, co-authored with Jeremy Hardie (2012) – EBP The approach to comparing the two authors is dictated by the difference in scope. Bhaskar is catholic, touching everything from physics and chemistry to hermeneutics and phenomenology. For the most part he explicitly avoids the content of particular subfields. Cartwright, on the other hand, is much more focused: her works deals with physics, inferential statistics (usually in economics), and evidence- based policy, with pages dedicated to the minutiae of specific models, like lasers and Bayes nets. Since Bhaskar typically works at a higher level of generality I first describe his views, then endeavour to show how Cartwright fits. This style of comparison is strictly for presentational purposes, and should not be taken as implying either the primacy of generality over specificity, or of one author over the other. The comparison goes through the key points of core critical realism, loosely inspired by the structure of Collier’s introduction. Common Ground Strong Realism We begin with the fours senses in which a philosophy – first, Bhaskar’s – can be called “strong realism” (AC:6-7): 1) objectivity: “what is known is real whether or not it were known” 2) fallibility: since claims are made about some real thing (and not just our ideas about it), these claims can always be falsified 3) transphenomenality: we can have knowledge of underlying structures that endure longer than appearances, than the manifestations that they generate; knowledge “not just of family likeness but of the molecular structure of DNA.” 4) counter-phenomenality: knowledge of underlying structures may actually contradict appearances. The sun does not revolve around the Earth (though much evidence points to the contrary); selling your labour power consensually need not be fair. On all counts Cartwright is a realist (albeit a “local” realist [DW:23]), starting with objectivism. She certainly thinks that known things are real and not mere theoretical constructs (NCTM:77), which is why she opposes “[confusing] the world with our theories of it” (DW:110).1 She is sceptical of the 1 Readers of Bhaskar will recognize this as a critique of what Bhaskar calls the “epistemic fallacy” (AC:70-85). This critique is partly grounded in a common rejection of the copy theory of impression held by the British empiricists; 2 Bhaskar and Cartwright: Common Ground generality of scientific theories, but that does not translate into blanket denial of the reality of their objects (DW:34). Regarding fallibility when confronted with reality, Cartwright dedicates an entire book to “the multitude of bad cases, where the models, if available at all, provide a very poor image of the situation” (DW:26).2 Third, Cartwright believes that the real (often unseen) stuff of the world is natures (DW:80) that have capacities (DW:59-70),3 which “are not to be identified with any particular manifestations” (DW:64) – this is plainly transphenomenality. Finally to see that her work allows for and analyses counter-phenomenality, consider her description of a machine which uses Coulomb’s law of repulsion to move charged particles closer together, or of a Hotelling economy in which taxes decrease prices (DW:59-64). Depth Ontology Bhaskar’s intellectual project begins with ontological depth, the thesis that being can occupy three domains, each increasingly fundamental but decreasingly obvious: the empirical (that which we observe), the actual (that which happens) and the real (that which causes) (AC:42-45). Cartwright arrives at an equivalent tripartite hierarchy of modality – fact (Bhaskar’s empirical), law (the actual) and capacity (the real) (NCTM: Ch.4, esp.146-147, Figure 4.1 on p.159), and though she does not subsequently develop the idea it does recur in later work (e.g. EBP:23-27). The congruence on depth ontology is further attested by the similarity of their critique of Humean (and more generally empiricist) accounts of science, which by collapsing the real onto the actual (or both on the empirical) justifies the epistemology of constant conjunctions (RST:33-36; NCTM:187, cf. Ch.5 of NCTM on abstraction versus idealisation). The consequence of this ontological collapse is spurious explanatory reductionism, e.g. claiming that all society reduces to individuals (AC:7-12) or automatically dismissing policy research not based on randomised controlled trials (EBP:126-128). Depth realism implies that there is a generic route to explanatory success, that is, uncovering the real. For students of science this means that differences among scientific fields can often explained by differences in their objects of study: if astronomy and literary critique do not look the same, it is because comets and books are very different things (hence a “dappled” world: HCUT:23, DW:8, Figure 0.2; AC:160-168; epigraph of Ch.2 in SRHE). For practitioners and evaluators of science, the possibility of a generic form of successful science (whose aim is always to uncover the real) means that it can all be science; whether it actually is remains a matter for those fields. The final implication is that depth ontology licenses explanatory analogies and comparisons across domains, without privileging one source of metaphors and models. So when Cartwright titles a chapter (of NCTM) “What Quantum Mechanics can learn from Econometrics,” this does not strike a depth ontologist as surprising, or impudent. Closed and Open Systems No less important for core critical realism is the distinction between closed and open systems. In brief, closed systems are those in which single causal mechanisms can be identified through physical shielding (e.g. experiments in vacuum) or post-hoc factoring out (e.g. calculations of celestial orbits), while in open systems single causes cannot (yet?) be identified (e.g. meteorology, currency fluctuations) (AC:31-41). Cartwright agrees entirely: she holds that closed systems are very rare, Cartwright, DW:70, Bhaskar, RTS:31-32). 2 See also her remark on the revision
Recommended publications
  • Critical Realist Approaches to Global Learning: a Focus on Education for Sustainability’
    Khazem, D. (2018) ‘Critical realist approaches to global learning: A focus on education for sustainability’. International Journal of Development Education and Global Learning, 10 (2): 125–134. DOI https://doi.org/10.18546/IJDEGL.10.2.02 Critical realist approaches to global learning: A focus on education for sustainability Dima Khazem* – UCL Institute of Education, UK Abstract Critical realism offers a useful epistemology and ontology for conceptualizing theoretical and methodological considerations in global learning and may help to bridge the quantitative/qualitative divide that plagues social science. This article elaborates critical realist principles, concepts and methodologies to explain how they can be employed within global learning, with examples from education for sustainability. Keywords: ontological realism; epistemological relativism; judgemental rationality; education for sustainability; climate change Introduction At the ‘Research, evidence and policy learning for global education’ conference held in May 2017 in London, Professor Annette Scheunpflug, ‘a key figure in Europe in promoting the concept of global learning’ (Bourn, 2015: 72), spoke about the dilemmas of showing evidence and efficacy in recent educational policy discourse, and how the qualitative/quantitative divide that plagues social science affects research into global learning. As a member of the conference audience at the time, I suggested that critical realism, a meta-theory that I employ in my research, may offer a way forward for theoretical and methodological innovation within the field of global learning. Furthermore, critical realism, with its claim of methodological specificity, may help to mitigate the quantitative/qualitative dualism and bolster research evidence in global learning for policy consideration. This article proposes critical realist approaches to global learning and examines relevant theoretical and methodological issues with a specific focus on education for sustainability.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 PERSPECTIVE a Philosophical Memoir: Notes on Bhaskar, Realism
    PERSPECTIVE A Philosophical Memoir: Notes on Bhaskar, Realism and Cultural Theory1 John Roberts University of Wolverhampton, UK I first read Roy Bhaskar in Radical Philosophy in 1980, when ‘Scientific Explanation and Human Emancipation’ appeared.2 But when Bhaskar’s work cropped up in Art & Language’s writing in the early 1980s I resolved to read his A Realist Theory of Science (1975) and The Possibility of Naturalism (1979).3 I remember buying both from the excellent philosophy section of the old Compendium Books store in Camden Town. Art & Language were (probably) the first artists and art-theorists to recognise the critical importance of Bhaskar’s writing for a non-reductive account of realism in relation to art and cultural theory, given their general familiarity with debates in the philosophy of science and Anglo-American philosophy of language. W.V.O. Quine and Nelson Goodman, for instance, were part of the group’s daily conversational practices as artists during this period.4 Indeed, given their familiarity with the issues of intention, intension, the causal theory of representation (of- relations) the critique of empiricism and their general grounding in analytic philosophy and Boolean formal logic, the group were certainly well placed to develop Bhaskar’s own ground-breaking critique of empiricism in the philosophy of science, and push it in a productive cultural direction. Bhaskar became a crucial mediating figure between the ‘post-metaphysical’ interrogative mechanics of the analytic tradition and the genealogical-materialist
    [Show full text]
  • Contra O Ceticismo: Lukcs E Bhaskar
    CONTRA O CETICISMO EPISTEMOLÓGICO: A CONTRIBUIÇÃO DE LUKÁCS E BHASKAR Sandra Soares Della Fonte Profa. da UFES Doutoranda UFSC/CAPES Em nome da luta contra o positivismo, uma nova onda cética, sob uma capa pós- moderna, interpõe-se nas ciências humanas e na filosofia nos últimos anos e se traduz pela máxima de que a realidade é interna às convenções e aos esquemas culturais dos diversos grupos sociais1. São vários os argumentos dos partidários desse ceticismo epistemológico. Em um extremo, Baudrillard2 assevera que há uma ilusão radical na crença de que a realidade existe, de que há um referente para o conhecimento. Para ele, como não há real e não há vontade, o que resta é uma saída estetizante: “O que conta é a singularidade poética da análise. Só isso pode justificar escrever, e não a miserável objectividade crítica das idéias”3. Rorty4 não chega a negar a existência da realidade, mas nega a possibilidade de a ela ter acesso fora do âmbito de descrições particular. O autor afirma que a noção de um espelho da natureza desanuviado, de um ser humano que conhece o fato, é uma imagem de Deus. Joyce5 destaca que “o que está em questão não é a existência do real, mas – dado que o real só pode ser apreendido através de nossas categorias culturais – que versão do real deve predominar”. Ao reagir à epistemologia realista, ele acrescenta que o próprio referente é um produto discursivo da história. Já Braun6 explicita um dos desdobramentos mais diretos dessa discussão para a historiografia: “Assim, a ‘realidade’ passada não existe; no 1 Cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Realism, Cultural Studies and Althusser on Ideology
    Critical Realism, Cultural Studies and Althusser on Ideology (Preliminary remarks) (paper prepared for the IACR-conference "Debating Realism(s)", Roskilde University, Denmark, 17-19 August 2001) Hans Puehretmayer Introduction In my paper I first want to give a short outline of Althusser’s theory of ideology. I will suggest to divide his contributions to a conception of the ideological into four parts: i theoretical ideologies as conditions of science, and science as continually produced and continually threatened epistemological break with theoretical ideologies ii ideology as lived relation of individuals and groups to their conditions of existence iii relatively autonomous Ideological State Apparatuses securing the reproduction of a social formation iv ideology (in general) as constitutive mechanism for (each) subjectivity I did not choose Althusser by chance, I chose Althusser because he was one of the most influential authors both for Roy Bhaskar’s Critical Realism and for Cultural Studies (especially in the 1970s and 80s) (cf. Bhaskar 1989; Bhaskar 1997; Grossberg 1993; Barker 2000). Roughly one could say that Bhaskar has supplemented Althusser’s theory of epistemology (which he has adopted) with a new theory of ontology1 (which possibly is present implicitly in Althusser’s texts); while Cultural Studies - though critically - adopted the conceptions of ideology as lived relation of individuals to their conditions of existence and the conception of ideological apparatuses; in the 1990s they increasingly included the question of the constition of subjectivities, esp. in their research about racism, anti-racist resistance (f.e. Phil Cohen, Paul Gilroy, Les Back) and institutionalized sexist practices and discourses (McDowell 1997).
    [Show full text]
  • Tom Lewis: "Philosophical Realism & the Aesthetic in Michael Sprinker's
    Philosophical Realism and the Aesthetic in Michael Sprinker's Literary Criticism Tom Lewis I don't consider myself an "expert" on Michael Sprinker's writings. I have not read all of his works, and among those I have read I find that his knowledge and insight into matters discussed often surpass my own. I do consider myself to be someone who has learned from Michael's work. And those lessons form the subject of this presentation. I first met Michael in 1988 at the conference he organized at the Humanities Institute at SUNY-Stony Brook on "The Althusserian Legacy." I delivered a mediocre paper entitled "The Marxist Thing," in which I attempted to use Althusser's philosophy to identify "revolution" as the disciplinary object of historical materialism. The argument of the paper, such as it was, need not concern us here. In any case, what I recall is the discussion that followed, in which Michael asked the first question. At the time I was a fairly orthodox Althusserian and so had peppered my paper with potshots here and there against epistemology. In particular, I stated that I intended to rule out of court all epistemological questions about "causal primacy" and methodological "entry points." So I cruised along my merry way thinking I had safely ducked issues like base and superstructure, the ontological status of historical objects, the epistemological status of my own work, how do we know that Marx's account of capitalism is truer than Louis Ruckheyser's, etc. Well, as you can imagine, the first question I got--from Michael, and asked
    [Show full text]
  • Tuukka Kaidesoja on Critical Realist Transcendental Realism
    Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(2): 341–348 Book Symposium Open Access Ruth Groff Tuukka Kaidesoja on Critical Realist Transcendental Realism DOI 10.1515/jso-2014-0050 Abstract: I argue that critical realists think pretty much what Tukka Kaidesoja says that he himself thinks, but also that Kaidesoja’s objections to the views that he attributes to critical realists are not persuasive. Keywords: Critical realism; Naturalism; Roy Bhaskar; Social ontology. Thank you to the organizers of this symposium for inviting me to participate in it, and to Tuukka Kaidesoja for generously joining in. Here are the general facts of the matter, with respect to Kaidesoja’s Natural- izing Critical Realist Social Ontology. Kaidesoja thinks that: (1) Naturalism (the view that philosophical questions are properly settled via the deliverances and/or methodology of science) is preferable to competing meta-theoretical views; (2) Roy Bhaskar’s so-called “transcendental” argument against Hume’s account of causation fails; (3) Rom Harré and E. H. Madden’s (1975) treatment of what a causal power is (in Causal Powers) is preferable to the view of powers that Bhaskar (1978[1975]) advances in A Realist Theory of Science (RTS); Harré and Madden’s view is better because: (a) Bhaskar (according to Kaidesoja) is a Platonist about properties, while Harré and Madden are Aristotelians or immanent real- ists; and (b) Platonism about properties (Kaidesoja says) is at odds with naturalism; (4) Mario Bunge’s social ontology is preferable to Roy Bhaskar’s (1998[1979]) in The Possibility of Naturalism (PON), and to that of other critical realists; Bunge’s view is better because: (a) Bhaskar and other critical realists (says Kaidesoja) think that social structures are an abstraction, while Bunge Ruth Groff, Department of Political Science, McGannon Hall, Saint Louis University, St.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, the Noumenal, Freedom and Powers Alison Assiter When One
    Kant, the Noumenal, Freedom and Powers Alison Assiter When one gets beyond a certain ‘age’ in academic life, one comes to see that the intellectual world, no less than the musical or the artistic, or even the world of clothing, is subject to fashion. These ‘fashions’ may have some sort of extra theoretical ‘ground’, to use a contemporary term, unlike, for example, that for punk or for beards. Nonetheless, there are parallels with the latter. One fashion that is current at the moment, in certain philosophical circles, is a predilection for a certain type of materialism or realism as well as, in turn, a return to ontology and metaphysics, following a decline in interest in these domains in the mid-20th century. The 1930’s verificationists, to take the most outrageous example of the contrary view, had proclaimed, for a number of years, that metaphysical claims constituted literal nonsense. As someone who was a die-hard realist when a non-realist form of post-modernism was all the rage, I welcome this recent move. However, in this paper, I would like to offer a certain redress, a move back to the epistemic, not in order to deny this realism, but in order to 2 suggest that reading Kant through Lacan or through the lens of Laruelle, Meillassoux, or indeed through the lens of a certain form of Critical Realism, may fail to do justice to a crucial dimension of his thought. In the first section of the paper, I will respond to a variant of a certain type of realist critique of Kant.
    [Show full text]
  • Annotations to Bhaskar's Realist Theory of Science
    Annotations to Bhaskar’s Realist Theory of Science Hans G. Ehrbar May 12, 2005 Contents Prefaces i 0.1 Bibliographical Remark .......................... i 0.2 Preface to the First Edition ........................ ii 0.3 Preface to the 2nd edition ......................... xiii 0.4 Footnotes to the Preface .......................... xiii Introduction xv 2 CONTENTS 3 1 Philosophy and Scientific Realism 1 1.1 Two Sides of ‘Knowledge’ ......................... 1 1.2 Three Traditions in the Philosophy of Science .............. 8 1.3 The Transcendental Analysis of Experiences ............... 19 1.3.A The Analysis of Perception .................... 21 1.3.B Analysis of Experimental Activity ................ 25 1.4 Status of Ontology and its Dissolution in Classical Philosophy ..... 31 1.5 Ontology Vindicated and the Real Basis of Causal Laws ........ 47 1.6 A sketch of a critique of empirical realism ................ 68 1.7 Footnotes to Chapter 1 .......................... 76 2 Actualism and the Concept of a Closure 82 2.1 Introduction: On the Actuality of the Causal Connection ....... 82 2.2 Regularity Determinism and the Quest for a Closure .......... 90 2.3 The Classical Paradigm of Action ..................... 103 2.4 Actualism and Transcendental Realism: the Interpretation of Normic Statements ................................. 120 2.5 Autonomy and Reduction ......................... 140 2.6 Explanation in Open Systems ....................... 158 4 CONTENTS 2.7 Footnotes to Chapter 2 .......................... 169 2.8 Appendix: Orthodox Philosophy of Science and the Implications of Open Systems ................................ 173 3 The Logic of Scientific Discovery 196 3.1 Introduction: On the Contingency of the Causal Connection ...... 196 3.2 The Surplus-element in the Analysis of Law-like Statements: A Cri- tique of the Theory of Models ......................
    [Show full text]
  • The Pulse of Freedom? Bhaskar's Dialectic and Marxism
    Sean Creaven The Pulse of Freedom? Bhaskar’s Dialectic and Marxism Introduction Eight years have elapsed since the publication of Roy Bhaskar’s Dialectic. The stated aim of this project was extraordinarily ambitious. This was, basically, threefold. First, the ‘dialectical enrichment and deep- ening of critical realism – understood as consisting of transcendental realism as a general theory of science and critical naturalism as a special theory of social science’. Second, ‘the development of a gen- eral theory of dialectic. ..which will ...be capable of sustaining the development of a general metathe- ory for the social sciences, on the basis of which they will be capable of functioning as agencies of human self-emancipation’. Third, ‘the outline of the elements of a totalising critique of western philosophy, in its various (including hitherto dialectical) forms. ..[that is] capable. ..of casting light on the contemporary crisis of socialism’. 1 All of this was to be achieved primarily through the ‘non-preservative sublation of Hegelian dialectic’2 and the preservative sublation 1 Bhaskar 1993, p. 2. 2 Bhaskar 1993, p. xiii. Historical Materialism , volume 10:2 (77–141) ©Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2002 Also available online – www.brill.nl 78 Sean Creaven of Marxian dialectic. Bhaskar ’s Dialectic thus offered the prospect of providing ‘a philosophical basis for Marxian social theory consistent with Marx’s own undeveloped methodological insights’3 and of philosophically under -labouring a genuinely emancipatory socialist political project. Given the scope of the ambition of Dialectic (in terms of politics and philos - ophy), and given that it was intended to clarify Bhaskar’s relationship to Marxism, drawing up a balance sheet of the r espective merits and demerits of the new dialectical critical realism (DCR) system introduced by Bhaskar in Dialectic is long over due.
    [Show full text]
  • Marxism and Critical Realism£
    Marxism and Critical Realism£ Hans G. Ehrbar September 1998 We will discuss here the connection between Roy underlaborer of the scientist. Many successful scientists Bhaskar’s critical realism and Marxism. Bhaskar is a are realists, although others are quite naive regarding the Marxist, who did not write another exegesis of Grun- pre-conditions of their scientific activity. drisse, but re-derives Marx’s philosophical foundations Which results can the philosopher’s transcendental rea- based on today’s philosophical debates, by, as he says, soning lead to? The following is very abbreviated: “carrying the modern critiques of positivism to their logi- cal conclusion” [3]. 1. The world is open. Scientific activity does make a difference: it expands knowledge about the world and by this increases the range of things people can The Rediscovery of Ontology Do we need philosophy do. The ability of humans to make a difference is not in addition to the substantive sciences? Bhaskar thinks self-deception but is real. so; he is a philosopher. What is the difference between philosopher and scientist? 2. From the fact that science can explain the world al- though there is so much which we do not know fol- ¯ The scientist uses certain “scientific” methods to lows that the world must be stratified: its regularities gain knowledge about the world. are not anchored in one basic level (elementary par- ticle physics), but it has many levels each of which ¯ As it is commonly (but incorrectly) understood, the generates its own regularities. Chemistry cannot ex- philosopher derives these scientific principles. Here plain why dogs bark.
    [Show full text]
  • EPISTEMOLOGY and the PERSON Thomas J
    METHOD: Journal of Lonergan Studies, n.s. 5, no. 1 (2014) EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE PERSON Thomas J. McPartland Kentucky State University Frankfort, Kentucky he title “epistemology and the Person” may seem for many seem for many philosophical readers to be an oxymoron. And, certainly, if Tthis essay is a review of Christian Smith’s What Is a Person?, then such a description may seem warranted since Smith, in a powerful critique, shows how the “epistemological turn” in modern thought has had a devastating effect on the ability of social science to treat in a serious manner the reality of the person.1 What is needed, Smith argues, is a “metaphysical turn” to replace the “epistemological turn,” a frank acknowledgment, though in a critical manner, of the existence of a real world beyond the epistemological subject, a real world that includes the reality of persons. What is needed, then, is a “critical realist” perspective. The term “critical realism” (which Smith takes from the philosophy of Roy Bhaskar) immediately raises the prospects for those familiar with Lonergan of a genuine encounter that can perhaps be more a dialogue than a display of dialectics.2 It is the thesis of this paper that precisely such an encounter between Smith and Lonergan is an instance of the kind of “further collaboration” to which Lonergan famously offers an invitation at the beginning of Insight.3 For Smith employs his critical realist tools massively in the field of sociology. Lonergan, on the other hand, can provide an epistemology as an alternative to the “epistemological turn” that grounds the kind of metaphysics Smith finds necessary to correct the erroneous 1Christian Smith, What Is a Person? Rethinking Humanity, Social Life, and the Moral Good from the Person Up (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2010).
    [Show full text]
  • Dialectic Critical Realism and an Expanded Agenda for Industrial Marketing
    Dialectic critical realism and an expanded agenda for industrial marketing. Abstract This paper answers a call for industrial marketers to consider there place in a broader system of interactions. Using the principles of dialectical critical realism, a framework for such an endevour is proposed that considers interaction beyond a naïve dichotomy between agency and structure but instead envisages agency as being constrained by external environmental preconditions and internal predispositions in four dimensions. These dimensions, include interactions with nature, with organized resources, with ceremonial and technological systems and with habits of thought. The paper illustrates these dimension with reference to the context of late-liberalizing emerging economies and illustrates how industrial marketing interactions may become emancipatory in a broader system of interactions. 1: Introduction A central contention of the paper is that industrial marketing has undersold its importance to a broader audience. Hakansson and Waluszewski (2013:454) recently make a very strong case for consideration of the broader impacts of industrial marketing including “society at large”. In this paper we focus on the understated contributions of industrial marketing to the process of human development choosing the context of two late liberalising emerging economies (LEEs) in Africa and South Asia. However, in this paper we see the applicability of industrial marketing findings to a broader audience as a problem of theoretical lenses as well as context. We apply the emancipatory lens of dialectical critical realism to seek to identify causal, ‘real’ forces that impact on and constrain agency. The unique institutional environment of LEE countries makes a critical realist examination of firm activity in an embedded national and local socio-economic context compelling.
    [Show full text]