2 Probability, Random Elements, Random Sets

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

2 Probability, Random Elements, Random Sets Tel Aviv University, 2012 Measurability and continuity 25 2 Probability, random elements, random sets 2a Probability space, measure algebra . 25 2b Standard models . 30 2c Random elements . 33 2d Random sets . 37 Hints to exercises ....................... 44 Index ............................. 45 After introducing probability measures we discuss random objects of two kinds. 2a Probability space, measure algebra We know that algebras are easy but σ-algebras are not. Surprisingly, a mea- sure makes σ-algebras easy by neglecting null sets. In particular, the Lebesgue σ-algebra is simpler than the Borel σ-algebra. 2a1 Definition. (a) A probability measure on a measurable space (X; A) is a map µ : A! [0; 1] such that µ(X) = 1 and µ(A1 [ A2 [ ::: ) = µ(A1) + µ(A2) + ::: whenever sets A1;A2; · · · 2 A are pairwise disjoint. (b) A probability space is a triple (X; A; µ) such that (X; A) is a measur- able space and µ is a probability measure on (X; A). 2a2 Example. One and only one probability measure µ on ([0; 1]; B[0; 1]) satisfies µ([0; x]) = x for all x 2 [0; 1]. This µ is often called \Lebesgue measure on [0; 1]", but I prefer to add \restricted to the Borel σ-algebra". 2a3 Definition. Let (X; A; µ) be a probability space, and A ⊂ X. ∗ (a) Inner measure µ∗(A) and outer measure µ (A) of A are defined by ∗ µ∗(A) = maxfµ(B): B 2 A;B ⊂ Ag ; µ (A) = minfµ(B): B 2 A;B ⊃ Ag ; (b) A is a null (or negligible) set1 if µ∗(A) = 0; ∗ (c) A is a µ-measurable set (symbolically, A 2 Aµ) if µ∗(A) = µ (A). 1Terence Tao calls it \sub-null set", requiring A 2 A for null sets. For some authors, \null" means just \empty". Tel Aviv University, 2012 Measurability and continuity 26 In contrast, sets of A will be called A-measurable. Clearly, A ⊂ Aµ; that is, A-measurability implies µ-measurability. For µ of 2a2, Aµ is the Lebesgue σ-algebra on [0; 1]. 2a4 Core exercise. Prove that (a) the maximum and minimum in 2a3(a) ∗ are reached; and (b) µ∗(A) = 1 − µ (X n A). 2a5 Core exercise. Prove that µ∗ : 2X ! [0; 1] satisfies (a) µ∗(;) = 0, (b) µ∗(A) ≤ µ∗(B) whenever A ⊂ B ⊂ X (\monotonicity"); ∗ ∗ ∗ (c) µ (A1 [ A2 [ ::: ) ≤ µ (A1) + µ (A2) + ::: for all A1;A2; · · · ⊂ X (\countable subadditivity"). Deduce that the null sets are a σ-ideal, that is, every subset of a null set is a null set, and a countable union of null sets is a null set. If A is a null set then its complement X n A is called a set of full measure (or conegligible), and one says that x2 = A for almost all x, in other words, almost everywhere or almost surely (\a.s."). 2a6 Definition. Let (X; A; µ) be a probability space, and A; B ⊂ X. (a) The distance between A and B is1 dist(A; B) = µ∗(A4B); here the symmetric difference A4B = (A n B) [ (B n A) = fx : 1A(x) 6= 1B(x)g. (b) Sets A; B are equivalent or almost equal (symbolically, A ∼µ B) if dist(A; B) = 0, that is, their symmetric difference is a null set. Note that (2a7) dist(A; B) = minfµ∗(C): A \ (X n C) = B \ (X n C)g : (\By throwing C away we get A = B". ) 2a8 Core exercise. Prove that dist : 2X × 2X ! [0; 1] is a pseudometric, that is, (a) dist(A; A) = 0, (b) dist(A; B) = dist(B; A) (\symmetry"), (c) dist(A; C) ≤ dist(A; B) + dist(B; C) (\triangle inequality"). 1Not at all the distance between their closest points. Tel Aviv University, 2012 Measurability and continuity 27 2a9 Core exercise. Let An;Bn ⊂ X, dist(An;Bn) = "n, then (a) dist(A1 \ A2;B1 \ B2) ≤ "1 + "2, (b) dist(A1 [ A2;B1 [ B2) ≤ "1 + "2, (c) dist(A1 n A2;B1 n B2) ≤ "1 + "2, (d) dist(A14A2;B14B2) ≤ "1 + "2. Prove it. Generalize (a), (b) to finite and countable operations. Deduce that µ µ µ µ 8n An ∼ Bn implies A1 \ A2 ∼ B1 \ B2, A1 [ A2 ∼ B1 [ B2, A1 n A2 ∼ µ B1 nB2 and A14A2 ∼ B14B2. Generalize the first two relations to countable operations. 2a10 Core exercise. (a) A set is µ-measurable if and only if it is equivalent to some A-measurable set. (b) Aµ is a σ-algebra. (c) there exists one and only one probability measureµ ¯ on (X; Aµ) such thatµ ¯jA = µ. Prove it. The probability space (X; Aµ; µ¯) is called the completion of (X; A; µ). It is complete; that is, the given σ-algebra contains all null sets. Sometimes I'll write µ(A) (instead ofµ ¯(A)) for A 2 Aµ. Consider the set 2X =∼µ of all equivalence classes. According to 2a9 we may apply finite and countable (but not uncountable) operations to equivalence classes; and the usual properties (such as (A [ B) \ C = (A \ C) [ (B \ C)) hold. The relation A ⊂ B for A; B 2 2X =∼µ may be defined by µ∗(AnB) = 0, and is equivalent to A = A \ B (as well as B = A [ B). Also the distance is well-defined on 2X =∼µ , and is a metric; that is, a pseudometric satisfying dist(A; B) = 0 =) A = B for A; B 2 2X =∼µ : ∗ X µ Note that µ∗; µ : 2 =∼ ! [0; 1] are well-defined. The set of all equivalence classes of measurable sets,1 µ µ A=∼ = Aµ=∼ ; is called the measure algebra of (X; A; µ). It is closed under the finite and countable operations.2 Note that µ : A=∼µ ! [0; 1] is well-defined. 1\Many of the difficulties of measure theory and all the pathology of the subject arise from the existence of sets of measure zero. The algebraic treatment gets rid of this source of unpleasantness by refusing to consider sets at all; it considers sets modulo sets of measure zero instead." (P.R. Halmos, \Lectures on ergodic theory", Math. Soc. Japan 1956, p. 42.) 2In fact, A=∼µ is a complete Boolean algebra, and is topologically closed in 2X =∼µ . Tel Aviv University, 2012 Measurability and continuity 28 X Recall ∼E; Ed; Es; Eδ; Eσ introduced in Sect. 1(a,b) for arbitrary E ⊂ 2 . Now they are also well-defined for arbitrary E ⊂ 2X =∼µ . Similarly to 1a10 X µ and 1b8, a set E ⊂ 2 =∼ is called an algebra if it contains ∼E, Ed, Es, and σ-algebra, if it contains ∼E, Eδ, Eσ. 2a11 Core exercise. Measure subalgebras, that is, sub-σ-algebras of A=∼µ , are in a natural bijective correspondence with sub-σ-algebras of Aµ that contain all null sets.1 Formulate it accurately, and prove. We know (recall 1a21 and 1c18 or the paragraph before 1b8) that Eds = Esd X but generally Eδσ 6= Eσδ for E ⊂ 2 . µ 2a12 Proposition. For every algebra E ⊂ A=∼ the set Eδσ is a σ-algebra, and Eδσ = Eσδ. A surprise: no more Eσδσ and the like! In particular, for an arbitrary probability measure on the Cantor set we µ µ have Fσ=∼ = Gδ=∼ (recall 1b7). 2a13 Extra exercise. Does the equality Eδσ = Eσδ hold for arbitrary sets (not just algebras) E ⊂ A=∼µ ? The \sandwich" below implies 2a12 and gives substantially more detailed information. 2a14 Proposition. Let E ⊂ A be an algebra and B 2 σ(E); then there µ µ exist A 2 Eδσ and C 2 Eσδ such that A ⊂ B ⊂ C and A ∼ B ∼ C. For an arbitrary probability measure on the Cantor set we get A 2 Fσ, C 2 Gδ. In particular, every null set is contained in a Gδ null set. In order to get the same for a probability measure on Rd we generalize 2a14. Given a set F ⊂ A, we introduce µ∗F (A) = supfµ(B): B 2 F;B ⊂ Ag for A ⊂ X: 2a15 Proposition. If F ⊂ A satisfies Fs ⊂ F and Fδ ⊂ F then the set f A 2 Aµ : µ∗F (A) = µ(A) ^ µ∗F (X n A) = µ(X n A) g is a σ-algebra. Let us denote this σ-algebra by Sandwich(F). Clearly, the set F of all closed (or only compact) subsets of Rd satisfies Fs ⊂ F and Fδ ⊂ F. 1That is, all subsets of all measure 0 sets of the whole σ-algebra A. Tel Aviv University, 2012 Measurability and continuity 29 2a16 Core exercise. Let X = Rd, A = B(Rd), F be the set of all closed subsets of Rd, and µ a probability measure on (X; A). Then (a) A ⊂ Sandwich(F). (b) Aµ = Sandwich(F). Deduce it from 2a15. Do the same for compact (rather than closed) subsets of Rd. 2a17 Core exercise. If Fδ ⊂ F then the set E = fA 2 Aµ : µ∗F (A) = µ(A)g satisfies Eδ = E. Prove it. 2a18 Core exercise. If F ⊂ A satisfies Fs ⊂ F then µ fA 2 Aµ : µ∗F (A) = µ(A)g = fA 2 Aµ : 9B 2 Fσ ( B ⊂ A ^ B ∼ A ) g : Prove it. 2a19 Core exercise. For arbitrary F ⊂ A the set E = fA 2 Aµ : 9B 2 µ Fσ ( B ⊂ A ^ B ∼ A ) g satisfies Eσ ⊂ E. Prove it. 2a20 Core exercise. Prove Prop. 2a15. 2a21 Core exercise. Prove Prop. 2a14. Here is another useful implication of the sandwich. 2a22 Proposition. If two probability measures on (X; A) coincide on an algebra E ⊂ A then they coincide on σ(E). Proof.
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, Including the Axiom of Choice) Plus the Negation of CH
    ANNALS OF ~,IATltEMATICAL LOGIC - Volume 2, No. 2 (1970) pp. 143--178 INTERNAL COHEN EXTENSIONS D.A.MARTIN and R.M.SOLOVAY ;Tte RockeJ~'ller University and University (.~t CatiJbrnia. Berkeley Received 2 l)ecemt)er 1969 Introduction Cohen [ !, 2] has shown that tile continuum hypothesis (CH) cannot be proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Levy and Solovay [9] have subsequently shown that CH cannot be proved even if one assumes the existence of a measurable cardinal. Their argument in tact shows that no large cardinal axiom of the kind present;y being considered by set theorists can yield a proof of CH (or of its negation, of course). Indeed, many set theorists - including the authors - suspect that C1t is false. But if we reject CH we admit Gurselves to be in a state of ignorance about a great many questions which CH resolves. While CH is a power- full assertion, its negation is in many ways quite weak. Sierpinski [ 1 5 ] deduces propcsitions there called C l - C82 from CH. We know of none of these propositions which is decided by the negation of CH and only one of them (C78) which is decided if one assumes in addition that a measurable cardinal exists. Among the many simple questions easily decided by CH and which cannot be decided in ZF (Zerme!o-Fraenkel set theory, including the axiom of choice) plus the negation of CH are tile following: Is every set of real numbers of cardinality less than tha't of the continuum of Lebesgue measure zero'? Is 2 ~0 < 2 ~ 1 ? Is there a non-trivial measure defined on all sets of real numbers? CIhis third question could be decided in ZF + not CH only in the unlikely event t Tile second author received support from a Sloan Foundation fellowship and tile National Science Foundation Grant (GP-8746).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes
    MEASURE THEORY AND STOCHASTIC PROCESSES Lecture Notes José Melo, Susana Cruz Faculdade de Engenharia da Universidade do Porto Programa Doutoral em Engenharia Electrotécnica e de Computadores March 2011 Contents 1 Probability Space3 1 Sample space Ω .....................................4 2 σ-eld F .........................................4 3 Probability Measure P .................................6 3.1 Measure µ ....................................6 3.2 Probability Measure P .............................7 4 Learning Objectives..................................7 5 Appendix........................................8 2 Chapter 1 Probability Space Let's consider the experience of throwing a dart on a circular target with radius r (assuming the dart always hits the target), divided in 4 dierent areas as illustrated in Figure 1.1. 4 3 2 1 Figure 1.1: Circular Target The circles that bound the regions 1, 2, 3, and 4, have radius of, respectively, r , r , 3r , and . 4 2 4 r Therefore, the probability that a dart lands in each region is: 1 , 3 , 5 , P (1) = 16 P (2) = 16 P (3) = 16 7 . P (4) = 16 For this kind of problems, the theory of discrete probability spaces suces. However, when it comes to problems involving either an innitely repeated operation or an innitely ne op- eration, this mathematical framework does not apply. This motivates the introduction of a measure-theoretic probability approach to correctly describe those cases. We dene the proba- bility space (Ω; F;P ), where Ω is the sample space, F is the event space, and P is the probability 3 measure. Each of them will be described in the following subsections. 1 Sample space Ω The sample space Ω is the set of all the possible results or outcomes ! of an experiment or observation.
    [Show full text]
  • Ernst Zermelo Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus in Cooperation with Volker Peckhaus Ernst Zermelo
    Ernst Zermelo Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus In Cooperation with Volker Peckhaus Ernst Zermelo An Approach to His Life and Work With 42 Illustrations 123 Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus Mathematisches Institut Abteilung für Mathematische Logik Universität Freiburg Eckerstraße 1 79104 Freiburg, Germany E-mail: [email protected] Volker Peckhaus Kulturwissenschaftliche Fakultät Fach Philosophie Universität Paderborn War burger St raße 100 33098 Paderborn, Germany E-mail: [email protected] Library of Congress Control Number: 2007921876 Mathematics Subject Classification (2000): 01A70, 03-03, 03E25, 03E30, 49-03, 76-03, 82-03, 91-03 ISBN 978-3-540-49551-2 Springer Berlin Heidelberg New York This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broad- casting, reproduction on microfilm or in any other way, and storage in data banks. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of the German Copyright Law of September 9, 1965, in its current version, and permission for use must always be obtained from Springer. Violations are liable for prosecution under the German Copyright Law. Springer is a part of Springer Science+Business Media springer.com © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2007 The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant pro- tective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. Typesetting by the author using a Springer TEX macro package Production: LE-TEX Jelonek, Schmidt & Vöckler GbR, Leipzig Cover design: WMXDesign GmbH, Heidelberg Printed on acid-free paper 46/3100/YL - 5 4 3 2 1 0 To the memory of Gertrud Zermelo (1902–2003) Preface Ernst Zermelo is best-known for the explicit statement of the axiom of choice and his axiomatization of set theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Borel Structure in Groups and Their Dualso
    BOREL STRUCTURE IN GROUPS AND THEIR DUALSO GEORGE W. MACKEY Introduction. In the past decade or so much work has been done toward extending the classical theory of finite dimensional representations of com- pact groups to a theory of (not necessarily finite dimensional) unitary repre- sentations of locally compact groups. Among the obstacles interfering with various aspects of this program is the lack of a suitable natural topology in the "dual object"; that is in the set of equivalence classes of irreducible representations. One can introduce natural topologies but none of them seem to have reasonable properties except in extremely special cases. When the group is abelian for example the dual object itself is a locally compact abelian group. This paper is based on the observation that for certain purposes one can dispense with a topology in the dual object in favor of a "weaker struc- ture" and that there is a wide class of groups for which this weaker structure has very regular properties. If .S is any topological space one defines a Borel (or Baire) subset of 5 to be a member of the smallest family of subsets of 5 which includes the open sets and is closed with respect to the formation of complements and countable unions. The structure defined in 5 by its Borel sets we may call the Borel structure of 5. It is weaker than the topological structure in the sense that any one-to-one transformation of S onto 5 which preserves the topological structure also preserves the Borel structure whereas the converse is usually false.
    [Show full text]
  • STAT 571 Assignment 1 Solutions 1. If Ω Is a Set and C a Collection Of
    STAT 571 Assignment 1 solutions 1. If Ω is a set and a collection of subsets of Ω, let be the intersection of all σ-algebras that contain . ProveC that is the σ-algebra generatedA by . C A C Solution: Let α α A be the collection of all σ-algebras that contain , and fA j 2 g C set = α. We first show that is a σ-algebra. There are three things to A \ A A α A prove. 2 (a) For every α A, α is a σ-algebra, so Ω α, and hence Ω α A α = . 2 A 2 A 2 \ 2 A A (b) If B , then B α for every α A. Since α is a σ-algebra, we have c 2 A 2 A 2 A c B α. But this is true for every α A, so we have B . 2 A 2 2 A (c) If B1;B2;::: are sets in , then B1;B2;::: belong to α for each α A. A A 2 Since α is a σ-algebra, we have 1 Bn α. But this is true for every A [n=1 2 A α A, so we have 1 Bn . 2 [n=1 2 A Thus is a σ-algebra that contains , and it must be the smallest one since α for everyA α A. C A ⊆ A 2 2. Prove that the set of rational numbers Q is a Borel set in R. Solution: For every x R, the set x is the complement of an open set, and hence Borel.
    [Show full text]
  • (Measure Theory for Dummies) UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008
    A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Department of Electrical Engineering University of Washington Box 352500 Seattle, Washington 98195-2500 PHN: (206) 543-2150 FAX: (206) 543-3842 URL: http://www.ee.washington.edu A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 University of Washington, Dept. of EE, UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Abstract This tutorial is an informal introduction to measure theory for people who are interested in reading papers that use measure theory. The tutorial assumes one has had at least a year of college-level calculus, some graduate level exposure to random processes, and familiarity with terms like “closed” and “open.” The focus is on the terms and ideas relevant to applied probability and information theory. There are no proofs and no exercises. Measure theory is a bit like grammar, many people communicate clearly without worrying about all the details, but the details do exist and for good reasons. There are a number of great texts that do measure theory justice. This is not one of them. Rather this is a hack way to get the basic ideas down so you can read through research papers and follow what’s going on. Hopefully, you’ll get curious and excited enough about the details to check out some of the references for a deeper understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Probability Measures on Metric Spaces
    Probability measures on metric spaces Onno van Gaans These are some loose notes supporting the first sessions of the seminar Stochastic Evolution Equations organized by Dr. Jan van Neerven at the Delft University of Technology during Winter 2002/2003. They contain less information than the common textbooks on the topic of the title. Their purpose is to present a brief selection of the theory that provides a basis for later study of stochastic evolution equations in Banach spaces. The notes aim at an audience that feels more at ease in analysis than in probability theory. The main focus is on Prokhorov's theorem, which serves both as an important tool for future use and as an illustration of techniques that play a role in the theory. The field of measures on topological spaces has the luxury of several excellent textbooks. The main source that has been used to prepare these notes is the book by Parthasarathy [6]. A clear exposition is also available in one of Bour- baki's volumes [2] and in [9, Section 3.2]. The theory on the Prokhorov metric is taken from Billingsley [1]. The additional references for standard facts on general measure theory and general topology have been Halmos [4] and Kelley [5]. Contents 1 Borel sets 2 2 Borel probability measures 3 3 Weak convergence of measures 6 4 The Prokhorov metric 9 5 Prokhorov's theorem 13 6 Riesz representation theorem 18 7 Riesz representation for non-compact spaces 21 8 Integrable functions on metric spaces 24 9 More properties of the space of probability measures 26 1 The distribution of a random variable in a Banach space X will be a probability measure on X.
    [Show full text]
  • Descriptive Set Theory
    Descriptive Set Theory David Marker Fall 2002 Contents I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 2 1 Polish Spaces 2 2 Borel Sets 14 3 E®ective Descriptive Set Theory: The Arithmetic Hierarchy 27 4 Analytic Sets 34 5 Coanalytic Sets 43 6 Determinacy 54 7 Hyperarithmetic Sets 62 II Borel Equivalence Relations 73 1 8 ¦1-Equivalence Relations 73 9 Tame Borel Equivalence Relations 82 10 Countable Borel Equivalence Relations 87 11 Hyper¯nite Equivalence Relations 92 1 These are informal notes for a course in Descriptive Set Theory given at the University of Illinois at Chicago in Fall 2002. While I hope to give a fairly broad survey of the subject we will be concentrating on problems about group actions, particularly those motivated by Vaught's conjecture. Kechris' Classical Descriptive Set Theory is the main reference for these notes. Notation: If A is a set, A<! is the set of all ¯nite sequences from A. Suppose <! σ = (a0; : : : ; am) 2 A and b 2 A. Then σ b is the sequence (a0; : : : ; am; b). We let ; denote the empty sequence. If σ 2 A<!, then jσj is the length of σ. If f : N ! A, then fjn is the sequence (f(0); : : :b; f(n ¡ 1)). If X is any set, P(X), the power set of X is the set of all subsets X. If X is a metric space, x 2 X and ² > 0, then B²(x) = fy 2 X : d(x; y) < ²g is the open ball of radius ² around x. Part I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 1 Polish Spaces De¯nition 1.1 Let X be a topological space.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 Measure Spaces
    Chapter 2 Measure spaces 2.1 Sets and σ-algebras 2.1.1 Definitions Let X be a (non-empty) set; at this stage it is only a set, i.e., not yet endowed with any additional structure. Our eventual goal is to define a measure on subsets of X. As we have seen, we may have to restrict the subsets to which a measure is assigned. There are, however, certain requirements that the collection of sets to which a measure is assigned—measurable sets (;&$*$/ ;&7&"8)—should satisfy. If two sets are measurable, we would like their union, intersection and comple- ments to be measurable as well. This leads to the following definition: Definition 2.1 Let X be a non-empty set. A (boolean) algebra of subsets (%9"#-! ;&7&"8 -:) of X, is a non-empty collection of subsets of X, closed under finite unions (*5&2 $&(*!) and complementation. A (boolean) σ-algebra (%9"#-! %/#*2) ⌃ of subsets of X is a non-empty collection of subsets of X, closed under countable unions (%**1/ 0" $&(*!) and complementation. Comment: In the context of probability theory, the elements of a σ-algebra are called events (;&39&!/). Proposition 2.2 Let be an algebra of subsets of X. Then, contains X, the empty set, and it is closed under finite intersections. A A 8 Chapter 2 Proof : Since is not empty, it contains at least one set A . Then, A X A Ac and Xc ∈ A. Let A1,...,An . By= de∪ Morgan’s∈ A laws, = ∈ A n n c ⊂ A c Ak Ak .
    [Show full text]
  • SOME REMARKS CONCERNING FINITELY Subaddmve OUTER MEASURES with APPUCATIONS
    Internat. J. Math. & Math. Sci. 653 VOL. 21 NO. 4 (1998) 653-670 SOME REMARKS CONCERNING FINITELY SUBADDmVE OUTER MEASURES WITH APPUCATIONS JOHN E. KNIGHT Department of Mathematics Long Island University Brooklyn Campus University Plaza Brooklyn, New York 11201 U.S.A. (Received November 21, 1996 and in revised form October 29, 1997) ABSTRACT. The present paper is intended as a first step toward the establishment of a general theory of finitely subadditive outer measures. First, a general method for constructing a finitely subadditive outer measure and an associated finitely additive measure on any space is presented. This is followed by a discussion of the theory of inner measures, their construction, and the relationship of their properties to those of an associated finitely subadditive outer measure. In particular, the interconnections between the measurable sets determined by both the outer measure and its associated inner measure are examined. Finally, several applications of the general theory are given, with special attention being paid to various lattice related set functions. KEY WORDS AND PHRASES: Outer measure, inner measure, measurable set, finitely subadditive, superadditive, countably superadditive, submodular, supermodular, regular, approximately regular, condition (M). 1980 AMS SUBJECT CLASSIFICATION CODES: 28A12, 28A10. 1. INTRODUCTION For some time now countably subadditive outer measures have been studied from the vantage point of a general theory (e.g. see [4], [6]), but until now this has not been true for finitely subadditive outer measures. Although some effort has been made to explore the interconnections between certain specific examples of finitely subadditive outer measures (see [3], [7], [8], [10]), there is still no unifying framework for this subject analogous to the one for the countably subadditive case.
    [Show full text]
  • Structural Features of the Real and Rational Numbers ENCYCLOPEDIA of MATHEMATICS and ITS APPLICATIONS
    ENCYCLOPEDIA OF MATHEMATICS AND ITS APPLICATIONS FOUNDED BY G.-C. ROTA Editorial Board P. Flajolet, M. Ismail, E. Lutwak Volume 112 The Classical Fields: Structural Features of the Real and Rational Numbers ENCYCLOPEDIA OF MATHEMATICS AND ITS APPLICATIONS FOUNDING EDITOR G.-C. ROTA Editorial Board P. Flajolet, M. Ismail, E. Lutwak 40 N. White (ed.) Matroid Applications 41 S. Sakai Operator Algebras in Dynamical Systems 42 W. Hodges Basic Model Theory 43 H. Stahl and V. Totik General Orthogonal Polynomials 45 G. Da Prato and J. Zabczyk Stochastic Equations in Infinite Dimensions 46 A. Bj¨orner et al. Oriented Matroids 47 G. Edgar and L. Sucheston Stopping Times and Directed Processes 48 C. Sims Computation with Finitely Presented Groups 49 T. Palmer Banach Algebras and the General Theory of *-Algebras I 50 F. Borceux Handbook of Categorical Algebra I 51 F. Borceux Handbook of Categorical Algebra II 52 F. Borceux Handbook of Categorical Algebra III 53 V. F. Kolchin Random Graphs 54 A. Katok and B. Hasselblatt Introduction to the Modern Theory of Dynamical Systems 55 V. N. Sachkov Combinatorial Methods in Discrete Mathematics 56 V. N. Sachkov Probabilistic Methods in Discrete Mathematics 57 P. M. Cohn Skew Fields 58 R. Gardner Geometric Tomography 59 G. A. Baker, Jr., and P. Graves-Morris Pade´ Approximants, 2nd edn 60 J. Krajicek Bounded Arithmetic, Propositional Logic, and Complexity Theory 61 H. Groemer Geometric Applications of Fourier Series and Spherical Harmonics 62 H. O. Fattorini Infinite Dimensional Optimization and Control Theory 63 A. C. Thompson Minkowski Geometry 64 R. B. Bapat and T.
    [Show full text]
  • COUNTABLE BOREL EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS Introduction. These
    COUNTABLE BOREL EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS SIMON THOMAS AND SCOTT SCHNEIDER Introduction. These notes are based upon a day-long lecture workshop presented by Simon Thomas at the University of Ohio at Athens on November 17, 2007. The workshop served as an intensive introduction to the emerging theory of countable Borel equivalence relations. These notes are an updated and slightly expanded version of an earlier draft which was compiled from the lecture slides by Scott Schneider. 1. First Session 1.1. Standard Borel Spaces and Borel Equivalence Relations. A topological space is said to be Polish if it admits a complete, separable metric. If B is a σ-algebra of subsets of a given set X, then the pair (X, B) is called a standard Borel space if there exists a Polish topology T on X that generates B as its Borel σ-algebra; in which case, we write B = B(T ). For example, each of the sets R, [0, 1], NN, and 2N = P(N) is Polish in its natural topology, and so may be viewed, equipped with its corresponding Borel structure, as a standard Borel space. The abstraction involved in passing from a topology to its associated Borel structure is analagous to that of passing from a metric to its induced topology. Just as distinct metrics on a space may induce the same topology, distinct topologies may very well generate the same Borel σ-algebra. In a standard Borel space, then, one “remembers” only the Borel sets, and forgets which of them were open; it is natural therefore to imagine that any of them might have been, and indeed this is the case: Theorem 1.1.1.
    [Show full text]