Lecture Notes

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lecture Notes MEASURE THEORY AND STOCHASTIC PROCESSES Lecture Notes José Melo, Susana Cruz Faculdade de Engenharia da Universidade do Porto Programa Doutoral em Engenharia Electrotécnica e de Computadores March 2011 Contents 1 Probability Space3 1 Sample space Ω .....................................4 2 σ-eld F .........................................4 3 Probability Measure P .................................6 3.1 Measure µ ....................................6 3.2 Probability Measure P .............................7 4 Learning Objectives..................................7 5 Appendix........................................8 2 Chapter 1 Probability Space Let's consider the experience of throwing a dart on a circular target with radius r (assuming the dart always hits the target), divided in 4 dierent areas as illustrated in Figure 1.1. 4 3 2 1 Figure 1.1: Circular Target The circles that bound the regions 1, 2, 3, and 4, have radius of, respectively, r , r , 3r , and . 4 2 4 r Therefore, the probability that a dart lands in each region is: 1 , 3 , 5 , P (1) = 16 P (2) = 16 P (3) = 16 7 . P (4) = 16 For this kind of problems, the theory of discrete probability spaces suces. However, when it comes to problems involving either an innitely repeated operation or an innitely ne op- eration, this mathematical framework does not apply. This motivates the introduction of a measure-theoretic probability approach to correctly describe those cases. We dene the proba- bility space (Ω; F;P ), where Ω is the sample space, F is the event space, and P is the probability 3 measure. Each of them will be described in the following subsections. 1 Sample space Ω The sample space Ω is the set of all the possible results or outcomes ! of an experiment or observation. For the previously described experience (hereafter referred to as E1), the sample space is Ω1 = f1; 2; 3; 4g. This is an example of a nite sample space. Considering a variant of E1, an example of an innitely repeated operation E2 would be throwing the dart until winning the game (hit the region 1). The sample space in this case would be Ω2 = f1; 21; 31; 41; 221; 231;:::g, and this is an example of an innite, yet countable, sample space. An example of an innitely ne operation E3 would be throwing the dart and viewing the point of impact as the outcome. For this experience, the sample space is Ω3 = (d; α): d 2 [0; r]; α 2 [0; 2π[, corresponding to an uncountable sample space. Thus, concerning their cardinality, we can classify the sample spaces as countable and nite, countable and innite, and uncountable. A set is countable if there exists a bijective mapping from a subset of the set of natural numbers onto that set. Therefore, all nite sets are count- able but not all countable sets are nite. The remaining countable sets are called innite and countable. For instance, the set of natural numbers itself is countable, but it is not nite. An uncountable set is an innite set which cannot be put in a one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers N, i.e., one cannot order the elements into a sequence, for example the set real numbers R. 2 σ-eld F Considering a completely arbitrary non-empty space Ω, a class F of subsets of Ω is called a σ-eld 1 if it contains the empty set, is closed under the formation of complements, and is closed under the formation of countable unions: (i) ; 2 F; (ii) A 2 F ) AC 2 F; (iii) countable set S . Ai 2 F i 2 I;I = ) i2I Ai 2 F Since Ω and the empty set are complementary, by (ii) the rst condition can be replaced with Ω 2 F. Being closed under complementation also implies that (iii) is equivalent to say that F is closed under the formation of countable intersections. This results from DeMorgan's law, A \ B = (AC [ BC )C and A [ B = (AC \ BC )C . In the more general case where F is closed 1Some authors also use the terms sigma-eld, sigma-algebra or σ-algebra. 4 under nite unions/intersections F is a eld. With this result we can concluded that all σ-elds are also elds, but the opposite is not always true. The largest σ-eld containing all possible subsets of Ω, including the empty set, is called power set. It contains 2n elements, where n is the number of elements of Ω, and is usually denoted by P (Ω). Being A a collection of subsets of Ω, there is a unique σ-eld generated by A, denoted by σ(A), which is the smallest σ-eld containing A. In cases where σ(A) is more dicult to obtain than P (Ω), we can use F = P (Ω), as σ(A) ⊆ P (Ω). Example 1. Suppose Ω = fa; b; cg. Then, P (Ω) = f;; fag; fbg; fcg; fabg; fbcg; facg; Ωg. We can see that jP (Ω)j = 23 = 8 elements. Considering A = fa; bg, σ(A) = f;; fag; fbg; Ωg. Therefore, it is clear that σ(A) = P (A) ⊂ P (Ω). An interesting curiosity is the analogy between the elements of the power set and the sequence of binary numbers, where "1" means that the corresponding element is in the subset, and "0" means the opposite, as shown in Table 1.1. abc Subset 0 000 fg 1 001 fcg 2 010 fbg 3 011 fcbg 4 100 fag 5 101 facg 6 110 fabg 7 111 fabcg Table 1.1: Power set construction example The power set is useful when we are dealing with countable sample spaces. However, when this is not the case, one needs a dierent way to dene the event space. Thus, when the sample space is uncountable, the Borel σ-eld is used. The Borel σ-eld B is the smallest σ-eld in a topological space X such that every open set in X belongs to B. The members of B are called Borel sets. If X = R, B can be generated by any of the intervals (a; b); (a; b]; [a; b), or [a; b], with −∞ ≤ a ≤ b ≤ +1, i.e.: B = σ((a; b)) = σ((a; b]) = σ((a; b]) = σ([a; b]) = σ(open subsets of R): Example 2. Considering , and 1 1 , 1 1 . Being Ω = [0; 1] A = [0; 4 ); [ 4 ; 1] σ(A) = f;; [0; 4 ); [ 4 ; 1]; Ωg B([0; 1]) the collection of all the Borel sets generated by [0; 1], it is clear that σ(A) ⊂ B([0; 1]) and, therefore, both can be used as a valid event space F associated with the sample space Ω. 5 3 Probability Measure P 3.1 Measure µ A measure µ is a function dened on a σ-eld M over a sample space Ω and taking values in + such that the following properties are satised: R0 (i) The empty set has measure zero: µ(;) = 0. (ii) Countable additivity or σ-additivity: if A1;A2;::: is a countable collection of pairwise disjoint sets in F, then: 1 ! 1 [ X µ Ai = µ(Ai): i=1 i=1 A measure space (Ω; F; µ) is said to be complete if A ⊂ B; B 2 F, and µ(B) = 0, together imply that A 2 F and hence that µ(A) = 0. In appendix there can be found some interesting properties and their corresponding proofs related with measure spaces. The Borel measure, dened on the Borel σ-eld B, gives to the interval (a; b], with a < b, the measure b−a. However, the Borel measure is not complete, which is why in practice the complete Lebesgue measure is preferred. The Lebesgue measure, dened on the Lebesgue σ-eld L, is a completion of the Borel measure and L is such that B ⊂ L. Actually, L is obtained by adding to B all the subsets of sets of measure zero that belong to the power set of R. This nds explanation in the fact that a subset of a set of measure zero might not be Borel measurable. Therefore every Borel measurable set is also Lebesgue measurable, and both measures agree. Note that the elements of the Lebesgue σ-eld are called Lebesgue measurable sets. Formally the Lebesgue measure is constructed in the following way: • For any half-open set ]a; b], with a < b, dene its length as L(]a; b]) = b − a. ∗ • For any subset of R dene µ (B) as ∗ µ (B) = inf f L(E): 8 E ⊇ B where E is a countable union of disjoint intervals ]ai; bi]g : • A set A ⊆ R is Lebesgue measurable, i.e., it belongs to the Lebesgue σ-algebra, if µ∗(B) = µ∗(B \ A) + µ∗(B − A) for all B ⊆ R. • The Lebesgue measure is dened by µ(A) = µ∗(A) for all A in the Lebesgue σ-algebra L. However, there are some sets that are not measurable. One example of such sets are the Vitali sets, named after Vitali who proved their existence. For more details on this subject please refer to [6]. 6 3.2 Probability Measure P Given a σ-eld F of subsets of Ω, any measure P : F! [0; 1] such that P (Ω) = 1 is called a probability measure on F. In addition, if F is complete with respect to P , we say that the triple (Ω; F;P ) forms a probability space. Therefore we can dene a probability measure P : F! [0; 1] according to the following proper- ties: (i) P (Ω) = 1. (ii) S1 P1 with T . P ( i=1 Ai) = i=1 P (Ai) Ai 2 F;Ai Aj = ;; i 6= j Similarly to what happens with basic probabilities, probability measures also follow the properties specied below, for A; B 2 F: (i) A ⊆ B ) P (A) ≤ P (B) (ii) P (A) = 1 − P (AC ) (iii) P (A [ B) = P (A) + P (B) − P (A \ B) (iv) P , being a partition of .
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, Including the Axiom of Choice) Plus the Negation of CH
    ANNALS OF ~,IATltEMATICAL LOGIC - Volume 2, No. 2 (1970) pp. 143--178 INTERNAL COHEN EXTENSIONS D.A.MARTIN and R.M.SOLOVAY ;Tte RockeJ~'ller University and University (.~t CatiJbrnia. Berkeley Received 2 l)ecemt)er 1969 Introduction Cohen [ !, 2] has shown that tile continuum hypothesis (CH) cannot be proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Levy and Solovay [9] have subsequently shown that CH cannot be proved even if one assumes the existence of a measurable cardinal. Their argument in tact shows that no large cardinal axiom of the kind present;y being considered by set theorists can yield a proof of CH (or of its negation, of course). Indeed, many set theorists - including the authors - suspect that C1t is false. But if we reject CH we admit Gurselves to be in a state of ignorance about a great many questions which CH resolves. While CH is a power- full assertion, its negation is in many ways quite weak. Sierpinski [ 1 5 ] deduces propcsitions there called C l - C82 from CH. We know of none of these propositions which is decided by the negation of CH and only one of them (C78) which is decided if one assumes in addition that a measurable cardinal exists. Among the many simple questions easily decided by CH and which cannot be decided in ZF (Zerme!o-Fraenkel set theory, including the axiom of choice) plus the negation of CH are tile following: Is every set of real numbers of cardinality less than tha't of the continuum of Lebesgue measure zero'? Is 2 ~0 < 2 ~ 1 ? Is there a non-trivial measure defined on all sets of real numbers? CIhis third question could be decided in ZF + not CH only in the unlikely event t Tile second author received support from a Sloan Foundation fellowship and tile National Science Foundation Grant (GP-8746).
    [Show full text]
  • Borel Structure in Groups and Their Dualso
    BOREL STRUCTURE IN GROUPS AND THEIR DUALSO GEORGE W. MACKEY Introduction. In the past decade or so much work has been done toward extending the classical theory of finite dimensional representations of com- pact groups to a theory of (not necessarily finite dimensional) unitary repre- sentations of locally compact groups. Among the obstacles interfering with various aspects of this program is the lack of a suitable natural topology in the "dual object"; that is in the set of equivalence classes of irreducible representations. One can introduce natural topologies but none of them seem to have reasonable properties except in extremely special cases. When the group is abelian for example the dual object itself is a locally compact abelian group. This paper is based on the observation that for certain purposes one can dispense with a topology in the dual object in favor of a "weaker struc- ture" and that there is a wide class of groups for which this weaker structure has very regular properties. If .S is any topological space one defines a Borel (or Baire) subset of 5 to be a member of the smallest family of subsets of 5 which includes the open sets and is closed with respect to the formation of complements and countable unions. The structure defined in 5 by its Borel sets we may call the Borel structure of 5. It is weaker than the topological structure in the sense that any one-to-one transformation of S onto 5 which preserves the topological structure also preserves the Borel structure whereas the converse is usually false.
    [Show full text]
  • STAT 571 Assignment 1 Solutions 1. If Ω Is a Set and C a Collection Of
    STAT 571 Assignment 1 solutions 1. If Ω is a set and a collection of subsets of Ω, let be the intersection of all σ-algebras that contain . ProveC that is the σ-algebra generatedA by . C A C Solution: Let α α A be the collection of all σ-algebras that contain , and fA j 2 g C set = α. We first show that is a σ-algebra. There are three things to A \ A A α A prove. 2 (a) For every α A, α is a σ-algebra, so Ω α, and hence Ω α A α = . 2 A 2 A 2 \ 2 A A (b) If B , then B α for every α A. Since α is a σ-algebra, we have c 2 A 2 A 2 A c B α. But this is true for every α A, so we have B . 2 A 2 2 A (c) If B1;B2;::: are sets in , then B1;B2;::: belong to α for each α A. A A 2 Since α is a σ-algebra, we have 1 Bn α. But this is true for every A [n=1 2 A α A, so we have 1 Bn . 2 [n=1 2 A Thus is a σ-algebra that contains , and it must be the smallest one since α for everyA α A. C A ⊆ A 2 2. Prove that the set of rational numbers Q is a Borel set in R. Solution: For every x R, the set x is the complement of an open set, and hence Borel.
    [Show full text]
  • (Measure Theory for Dummies) UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008
    A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Department of Electrical Engineering University of Washington Box 352500 Seattle, Washington 98195-2500 PHN: (206) 543-2150 FAX: (206) 543-3842 URL: http://www.ee.washington.edu A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 University of Washington, Dept. of EE, UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Abstract This tutorial is an informal introduction to measure theory for people who are interested in reading papers that use measure theory. The tutorial assumes one has had at least a year of college-level calculus, some graduate level exposure to random processes, and familiarity with terms like “closed” and “open.” The focus is on the terms and ideas relevant to applied probability and information theory. There are no proofs and no exercises. Measure theory is a bit like grammar, many people communicate clearly without worrying about all the details, but the details do exist and for good reasons. There are a number of great texts that do measure theory justice. This is not one of them. Rather this is a hack way to get the basic ideas down so you can read through research papers and follow what’s going on. Hopefully, you’ll get curious and excited enough about the details to check out some of the references for a deeper understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Probability Measures on Metric Spaces
    Probability measures on metric spaces Onno van Gaans These are some loose notes supporting the first sessions of the seminar Stochastic Evolution Equations organized by Dr. Jan van Neerven at the Delft University of Technology during Winter 2002/2003. They contain less information than the common textbooks on the topic of the title. Their purpose is to present a brief selection of the theory that provides a basis for later study of stochastic evolution equations in Banach spaces. The notes aim at an audience that feels more at ease in analysis than in probability theory. The main focus is on Prokhorov's theorem, which serves both as an important tool for future use and as an illustration of techniques that play a role in the theory. The field of measures on topological spaces has the luxury of several excellent textbooks. The main source that has been used to prepare these notes is the book by Parthasarathy [6]. A clear exposition is also available in one of Bour- baki's volumes [2] and in [9, Section 3.2]. The theory on the Prokhorov metric is taken from Billingsley [1]. The additional references for standard facts on general measure theory and general topology have been Halmos [4] and Kelley [5]. Contents 1 Borel sets 2 2 Borel probability measures 3 3 Weak convergence of measures 6 4 The Prokhorov metric 9 5 Prokhorov's theorem 13 6 Riesz representation theorem 18 7 Riesz representation for non-compact spaces 21 8 Integrable functions on metric spaces 24 9 More properties of the space of probability measures 26 1 The distribution of a random variable in a Banach space X will be a probability measure on X.
    [Show full text]
  • Descriptive Set Theory
    Descriptive Set Theory David Marker Fall 2002 Contents I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 2 1 Polish Spaces 2 2 Borel Sets 14 3 E®ective Descriptive Set Theory: The Arithmetic Hierarchy 27 4 Analytic Sets 34 5 Coanalytic Sets 43 6 Determinacy 54 7 Hyperarithmetic Sets 62 II Borel Equivalence Relations 73 1 8 ¦1-Equivalence Relations 73 9 Tame Borel Equivalence Relations 82 10 Countable Borel Equivalence Relations 87 11 Hyper¯nite Equivalence Relations 92 1 These are informal notes for a course in Descriptive Set Theory given at the University of Illinois at Chicago in Fall 2002. While I hope to give a fairly broad survey of the subject we will be concentrating on problems about group actions, particularly those motivated by Vaught's conjecture. Kechris' Classical Descriptive Set Theory is the main reference for these notes. Notation: If A is a set, A<! is the set of all ¯nite sequences from A. Suppose <! σ = (a0; : : : ; am) 2 A and b 2 A. Then σ b is the sequence (a0; : : : ; am; b). We let ; denote the empty sequence. If σ 2 A<!, then jσj is the length of σ. If f : N ! A, then fjn is the sequence (f(0); : : :b; f(n ¡ 1)). If X is any set, P(X), the power set of X is the set of all subsets X. If X is a metric space, x 2 X and ² > 0, then B²(x) = fy 2 X : d(x; y) < ²g is the open ball of radius ² around x. Part I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 1 Polish Spaces De¯nition 1.1 Let X be a topological space.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 2 the Borel Σ-Algebra
    MA40042 Measure Theory and Integration • A set K ⊂ Rd is compact if every open cover of K has a finite subcover. That is, if K can be `covered' by a (not necessarily countable) union of open sets [ d Lecture 2 K ⊂ Gα;Gα ⊂ R open for all α 2 I; The Borel σ-algebra α2I then there exists a finite subset fα1; : : : ; αN g ⊂ I that also covers K, N [ K ⊂ G : • Review of open, closed, αn n=1 and compact sets in Rd • The Borel σ-algebra on Rd Checking whether a set is compact under this definition can be difficult, but is made much easier by the following theorem (which we won't prove here). • Intervals and boxes in Rd Theorem 2.2 (Heine{Borel theorem). A set K ⊂ Rd is compact if and only if it is closed and bounded. For countable sets X, the powerset P(X) is a useful σ-algebra. But in larger d sets, such as R or R , the full powerset is often too big for interesting measures to Bounded here means that K ⊂ B(x; r) for some x 2 Rd and some r 2 (0; 1). exist, such as the Lebesgue length/area/volume measure. (We'll see a example of this later in the course.) d d 2.2 B( ) On R or R a useful σ-algebra is the Borel σ-algebra. The benefits of the Borel R σ-algebra are: Fix d, and write G, F, and K for, respectively, the collection of open, closed, and compact sets in d.
    [Show full text]
  • Descriptive Set Theory and the Ergodic Theory of Countable Groups
    DESCRIPTIVE SET THEORY AND THE ERGODIC THEORY OF COUNTABLE GROUPS Thesis by Robin Daniel Tucker-Drob In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy California Institute of Technology Pasadena, California 2013 (Defended April 17, 2013) ii c 2013 Robin Daniel Tucker-Drob All Rights Reserved iii Acknowledgements I would like to thank my advisor Alexander Kechris for his invaluable guidance and support, for his generous feedback, and for many (many!) discussions. In addition I would like to thank Miklos Abert,´ Lewis Bowen, Clinton Conley, Darren Creutz, Ilijas Farah, Adrian Ioana, David Kerr, Andrew Marks, Benjamin Miller, Jesse Peterson, Ernest Schimmerling, Miodrag Sokic, Simon Thomas, Asger Tornquist,¨ Todor Tsankov, Anush Tserunyan, and Benjy Weiss for many valuable conversations over the past few years. iv Abstract The primary focus of this thesis is on the interplay of descriptive set theory and the ergodic theory of group actions. This incorporates the study of turbulence and Borel re- ducibility on the one hand, and the theory of orbit equivalence and weak equivalence on the other. Chapter 2 is joint work with Clinton Conley and Alexander Kechris; we study measurable graph combinatorial invariants of group actions and employ the ultraproduct construction as a way of constructing various measure preserving actions with desirable properties. Chapter 3 is joint work with Lewis Bowen; we study the property MD of resid- ually finite groups, and we prove a conjecture of Kechris by showing that under general hypotheses property MD is inherited by a group from one of its co-amenable subgroups. Chapter 4 is a study of weak equivalence.
    [Show full text]
  • Stationary Probability Measures and Topological Realizations
    ISRAEL JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS ?? (2013), 1{14 DOI: 10.1007/s??????-??????-?????? STATIONARY PROBABILITY MEASURES AND TOPOLOGICAL REALIZATIONS BY Clinton T. Conley∗ 584 Malott Hall Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853 USA e-mail: [email protected] URL: http://www.math.cornell.edu/People/Faculty/conley.html AND Alexander S. Kechris∗∗ Mathematics 253-37 Caltech Pasadena, CA 91125 USA e-mail: [email protected] URL: http://www.math.caltech.edu/people/kechris.html AND Benjamin D. Miller∗ Institut f¨urmathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung Fachbereich Mathematik und Informatik Universit¨atM¨unster Einsteinstraße 62 48149 M¨unster Germany e-mail: [email protected] URL: http://wwwmath.uni-muenster.de/u/ben.miller 1 2 C.T. CONLEY, A.S. KECHRIS AND B.D. MILLER Isr. J. Math. ABSTRACT We establish the generic inexistence of stationary Borel probability mea- sures for aperiodic Borel actions of countable groups on Polish spaces. Using this, we show that every aperiodic continuous action of a countable group on a compact Polish space has an invariant Borel set on which it has no σ-compact realization. 1. Introduction It is well known that every standard Borel space is Borel isomorphic to a σ- compact Polish space (see [Kec95, Theorem 15.6]), and that every Borel action of a countable discrete group on a standard Borel space is Borel isomorphic to a continuous action on a Polish space (see [Kec95, Theorem 13.1]). Here we consider obstacles to simultaneously achieving both results. In x2, we give elementary examples of continuous actions of countable groups on Polish spaces which are not Borel isomorphic to continuous actions on σ- compact Hausdorff spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • Products of Two Borel Measures by Roy A
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 269, Number 2, February 1982 PRODUCTS OF TWO BOREL MEASURES BY ROY A. JOHNSON Abstract. Let ¡j, and v be finite Borel measures on Hausdorff spaces X and Y, respectively, and suppose product measures ¡i X x v and p. X2 v are defined on the Borel sets of X X Y by integrating vertical and horizontal cross-section measure, respectively. Sufficient conditions are given so that ¡i x¡ v = p x2v and so that the usual product measure u X v can be extended to a Borel measure on X X Y by means of completion. Examples are given to illustrate these ideas. Throughout this paper p and v will be finite Borel measures on Hausdorff spaces A and Y, respectively. That is, p and v will be countably additive, nonnegative real-valued measures on "35(A) and %(Y), where ÇÔ(A) and %(Y) are the Borel sets of A and Y, respectively. Sometimes p will be regular, which is to say that it is inner regular with respect to the compact sets. At times v will be two-valued, which means that its range consists of the two values 0 and 1. If »»can be expressed as the sum of a countable collection of multiples of two-valued Borel measures, then v is purely atomic. A (not necessarily regular) Borel measure p will be called r-additive if p(C\ Fa) = inf p(Fa) whenever {Fa} is a decreasing family of closed sets [4, p. 96]. Equiva- lently, p is r-additive if p( U Va) = sup p( Va) for each increasingly directed family { Va} of open sets.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Determinacy
    Virginia Commonwealth University VCU Scholars Compass Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2010 The Axiom of Determinacy Samantha Stanton Virginia Commonwealth University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd Part of the Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons © The Author Downloaded from https://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd/2189 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at VCU Scholars Compass. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of VCU Scholars Compass. For more information, please contact [email protected]. College of Humanities and Sciences Virginia Commonwealth University This is to certify that the thesis prepared by Samantha Stanton titled “The Axiom of Determinacy” has been approved by his or her committee as satisfactory completion of the thesis requirement for the degree of Master of Science. Dr. Andrew Lewis, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. Lon Mitchell, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. Robert Gowdy, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. John Berglund, Graduate Chair, Mathematics and Applied Mathematics Dr. Robert Holsworth, Dean, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. F. Douglas Boudinot, Graduate Dean Date © Samantha Stanton 2010 All Rights Reserved The Axiom of Determinacy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science at Virginia Commonwealth University. by Samantha Stanton Master of Science Director: Dr. Andrew Lewis, Associate Professor, Department Chair Department of Mathematics and Applied Mathematics Virginia Commonwealth University Richmond, Virginia May 2010 ii Acknowledgment I am most appreciative of Dr. Andrew Lewis. I would like to thank him for his support, patience, and understanding through this entire process.
    [Show full text]
  • Random Variables Lecturer: Dr
    EE5110: Probability Foundations for Electrical Engineers July-November 2015 Lecture 11: Random Variables Lecturer: Dr. Krishna Jagannathan Scribe: Sudharsan, Gopal, Arjun B, Debayani The study of random variables is motivated by the fact that in many scenarios, one might not be interested in the precise elementary outcome of a random experiment, but rather in some numerical function of the outcome. For example, in an experiment involving ten coin tosses, the experimenter may only want to know the total number of heads, rather than the precise sequence of heads and tails. The term random variable is a misnomer, because a random variable is neither random, nor is it a variable. A random variable X is a function from the sample space Ω to real field R. The term `random' actually signifies the underlying randomness in picking an element ! from the sample space Ω. Once the elementary outcome ! is fixed, the random variable takes a fixed real value, X(!): It is important to remember that the probability measure is associated with subsets (events), whereas a random variable is associated with each elementary outcome !. Just as not all subsets of the sample space are not necessarily considered events, not all functions from Ω to R are considered random variables. In particular, a random variable is an F-measurable function, as we define below. Definition 11.1 Measurable function: Let (Ω; F) be a measurable space. A function f :Ω ! R is said to be an F-measurable function if the pre-image of every Borel set is an F-measurable subset of Ω: In the above definition, the pre-image of a Borel set B under the function f is given by −1 f (B) , f! 2 Ω j f(!) 2 Bg: (11.1) Thus, according to the above definition, f :Ω ! R is an F-measurable function if f −1(B) is an F-measurable subset of Ω for every Borel set B: Definition 11.2 Random Variable: Let (Ω; F; P) be a probability space.
    [Show full text]