Cardinality and Equivalence Relations Greg Hjorth
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Filtering Germs: Groupoids Associated to Inverse Semigroups
FILTERING GERMS: GROUPOIDS ASSOCIATED TO INVERSE SEMIGROUPS BECKY ARMSTRONG, LISA ORLOFF CLARK, ASTRID AN HUEF, MALCOLM JONES, AND YING-FEN LIN Abstract. We investigate various groupoids associated to an arbitrary inverse semigroup with zero. We show that the groupoid of filters with respect to the natural partial order is isomorphic to the groupoid of germs arising from the standard action of the inverse semigroup on the space of idempotent filters. We also investigate the restriction of this isomorphism to the groupoid of tight filters and to the groupoid of ultrafilters. 1. Introduction An inverse semigroup is a set S endowed with an associative binary operation such that for each a 2 S, there is a unique a∗ 2 S, called the inverse of a, satisfying aa∗a = a and a∗aa∗ = a∗: The study of ´etalegroupoids associated to inverse semigroups was initiated by Renault [Ren80, Remark III.2.4]. We consider two well known groupoid constructions: the filter approach and the germ approach, and we show that the two approaches yield isomorphic groupoids. Every inverse semigroup has a natural partial order, and a filter is a nonempty down-directed up-set with respect to this order. The filter approach to groupoid construction first appeared in [Len08], and was later simplified in [LMS13]. Work in this area is ongoing; see for instance, [Bic21, BC20, Cas20]. Every inverse semigroup acts on the filters of its subsemigroup of idempotents. The groupoid of germs associated to an inverse semigroup encodes this action. Paterson pioneered the germ approach in [Pat99] with the introduction of the universal groupoid of an inverse semigroup. -
Relations on Semigroups
International Journal for Research in Engineering Application & Management (IJREAM) ISSN : 2454-9150 Vol-04, Issue-09, Dec 2018 Relations on Semigroups 1D.D.Padma Priya, 2G.Shobhalatha, 3U.Nagireddy, 4R.Bhuvana Vijaya 1 Sr.Assistant Professor, Department of Mathematics, New Horizon College Of Engineering, Bangalore, India, Research scholar, Department of Mathematics, JNTUA- Anantapuram [email protected] 2Professor, Department of Mathematics, SKU-Anantapuram, India, [email protected] 3Assistant Professor, Rayalaseema University, Kurnool, India, [email protected] 4Associate Professor, Department of Mathematics, JNTUA- Anantapuram, India, [email protected] Abstract: Equivalence relations play a vital role in the study of quotient structures of different algebraic structures. Semigroups being one of the algebraic structures are sets with associative binary operation defined on them. Semigroup theory is one of such subject to determine and analyze equivalence relations in the sense that it could be easily understood. This paper contains the quotient structures of semigroups by extending equivalence relations as congruences. We define different types of relations on the semigroups and prove they are equivalence, partial order, congruence or weakly separative congruence relations. Keywords: Semigroup, binary relation, Equivalence and congruence relations. I. INTRODUCTION [1,2,3 and 4] Algebraic structures play a prominent role in mathematics with wide range of applications in science and engineering. A semigroup -
Set Theory, Including the Axiom of Choice) Plus the Negation of CH
ANNALS OF ~,IATltEMATICAL LOGIC - Volume 2, No. 2 (1970) pp. 143--178 INTERNAL COHEN EXTENSIONS D.A.MARTIN and R.M.SOLOVAY ;Tte RockeJ~'ller University and University (.~t CatiJbrnia. Berkeley Received 2 l)ecemt)er 1969 Introduction Cohen [ !, 2] has shown that tile continuum hypothesis (CH) cannot be proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Levy and Solovay [9] have subsequently shown that CH cannot be proved even if one assumes the existence of a measurable cardinal. Their argument in tact shows that no large cardinal axiom of the kind present;y being considered by set theorists can yield a proof of CH (or of its negation, of course). Indeed, many set theorists - including the authors - suspect that C1t is false. But if we reject CH we admit Gurselves to be in a state of ignorance about a great many questions which CH resolves. While CH is a power- full assertion, its negation is in many ways quite weak. Sierpinski [ 1 5 ] deduces propcsitions there called C l - C82 from CH. We know of none of these propositions which is decided by the negation of CH and only one of them (C78) which is decided if one assumes in addition that a measurable cardinal exists. Among the many simple questions easily decided by CH and which cannot be decided in ZF (Zerme!o-Fraenkel set theory, including the axiom of choice) plus the negation of CH are tile following: Is every set of real numbers of cardinality less than tha't of the continuum of Lebesgue measure zero'? Is 2 ~0 < 2 ~ 1 ? Is there a non-trivial measure defined on all sets of real numbers? CIhis third question could be decided in ZF + not CH only in the unlikely event t Tile second author received support from a Sloan Foundation fellowship and tile National Science Foundation Grant (GP-8746). -
Lecture Notes
MEASURE THEORY AND STOCHASTIC PROCESSES Lecture Notes José Melo, Susana Cruz Faculdade de Engenharia da Universidade do Porto Programa Doutoral em Engenharia Electrotécnica e de Computadores March 2011 Contents 1 Probability Space3 1 Sample space Ω .....................................4 2 σ-eld F .........................................4 3 Probability Measure P .................................6 3.1 Measure µ ....................................6 3.2 Probability Measure P .............................7 4 Learning Objectives..................................7 5 Appendix........................................8 2 Chapter 1 Probability Space Let's consider the experience of throwing a dart on a circular target with radius r (assuming the dart always hits the target), divided in 4 dierent areas as illustrated in Figure 1.1. 4 3 2 1 Figure 1.1: Circular Target The circles that bound the regions 1, 2, 3, and 4, have radius of, respectively, r , r , 3r , and . 4 2 4 r Therefore, the probability that a dart lands in each region is: 1 , 3 , 5 , P (1) = 16 P (2) = 16 P (3) = 16 7 . P (4) = 16 For this kind of problems, the theory of discrete probability spaces suces. However, when it comes to problems involving either an innitely repeated operation or an innitely ne op- eration, this mathematical framework does not apply. This motivates the introduction of a measure-theoretic probability approach to correctly describe those cases. We dene the proba- bility space (Ω; F;P ), where Ω is the sample space, F is the event space, and P is the probability 3 measure. Each of them will be described in the following subsections. 1 Sample space Ω The sample space Ω is the set of all the possible results or outcomes ! of an experiment or observation. -
Borel Structure in Groups and Their Dualso
BOREL STRUCTURE IN GROUPS AND THEIR DUALSO GEORGE W. MACKEY Introduction. In the past decade or so much work has been done toward extending the classical theory of finite dimensional representations of com- pact groups to a theory of (not necessarily finite dimensional) unitary repre- sentations of locally compact groups. Among the obstacles interfering with various aspects of this program is the lack of a suitable natural topology in the "dual object"; that is in the set of equivalence classes of irreducible representations. One can introduce natural topologies but none of them seem to have reasonable properties except in extremely special cases. When the group is abelian for example the dual object itself is a locally compact abelian group. This paper is based on the observation that for certain purposes one can dispense with a topology in the dual object in favor of a "weaker struc- ture" and that there is a wide class of groups for which this weaker structure has very regular properties. If .S is any topological space one defines a Borel (or Baire) subset of 5 to be a member of the smallest family of subsets of 5 which includes the open sets and is closed with respect to the formation of complements and countable unions. The structure defined in 5 by its Borel sets we may call the Borel structure of 5. It is weaker than the topological structure in the sense that any one-to-one transformation of S onto 5 which preserves the topological structure also preserves the Borel structure whereas the converse is usually false. -
Data Monoids∗
Data Monoids∗ Mikolaj Bojańczyk1 1 University of Warsaw Abstract We develop an algebraic theory for languages of data words. We prove that, under certain conditions, a language of data words is definable in first-order logic if and only if its syntactic monoid is aperiodic. 1998 ACM Subject Classification F.4.3 Formal Languages Keywords and phrases Monoid, Data Words, Nominal Set, First-Order Logic Digital Object Identifier 10.4230/LIPIcs.STACS.2011.105 1 Introduction This paper is an attempt to combine two fields. The first field is the algebraic theory of regular languages. In this theory, a regular lan- guage is represented by its syntactic monoid, which is a finite monoid. It turns out that many important properties of the language are reflected in the structure of its syntactic monoid. One particularly beautiful result is the Schützenberger-McNaughton-Papert theorem, which describes the expressive power of first-order logic. Let L ⊆ A∗ be a regular language. Then L is definable in first-order logic if and only if its syntactic monoid ML is aperiodic. For instance, the language “words where there exists a position with label a” is defined by the first-order logic formula (this example does not even use the order on positions <, which is also allowed in general) ∃x. a(x). The syntactic monoid of this language is isomorphic to {0, 1} with multiplication, where 0 corresponds to the words that satisfy the formula, and 1 to the words that do not. Clearly, this monoid does not contain any non-trivial group. There are many results similar to theorem above, each one providing a connection between seemingly unrelated concepts of logic and algebra, see e.g. -