Argument Structure

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Argument Structure Chapter 1 Argument Structure 1.1 WHAT IS AN ARGUMENT? Logic is the study of arguments. An argument is a sequence of statements of which one is intended as a conclusion and the others, the premises, are intended to prove or at least provide some evidence for the conclusion. Here are two simple examples: All humans are mortal. Socrates is human. Therefore, Socrates is mortal. Albert was not at the party, so he cannot have stolen your bag. In the first argument, the first two statements are premises intended to prove the conclusion that Socrates is mortal. In the second argument, the premise that Albert was not at the party is offered as evidence for the conclusion that he cannot have stolen the bag. The premises and conclusion of an argument are always statements or propositions,' as opposed to questions, commands, or exclamations. A statement is an assertion that is either true or false (as the case may be) and is typically expressed by a declarative ~entence.~Here are some more examples: Dogs do not fly. Robert Musil wrote The Man Without Qualities. Brussels is either in Belgium or in Holland. Snow is red. My brother is an entomologist. The first three sentences express statements that are in fact true. The fourth sentence expresses a false statement. And the last sentence can be used to express different statements in different contexts, and will be true or false depending on whether or not the brother of the speaker is in fact an entomologist. By contrast, the following sentences do not express any statements: Who is the author of The Man Without Qualities? Please do not call after I lpm. Come on! Nonstatements, such as questions, commands, or exclamation:;, are neither true nor false. They may sometimes suggest premises or conclusions, but they are never themselves premises or conclusions. SOLVED PROBLEM 1.1 Some of the following are arguments. Ide-ntify their premises and conclusions. (a) He's a Leo, since he was born in the first week of August. (6) How can the economy be improving? The trade deficit is rising every day. '~hiloso~herssometimes draw a distinction between statements and propositions, but it is not necessary to make that distinction here. 2The distinction between a statement or proposition and the sentence used to express it is important. A sentence can be ambiguous or context-dependent, and can therefore express any of two or more statements-even statements that disagree in their being true or false. (Our fifth example below is a case in point.) However, where there is no danger of confusion we shall avoid prolixity by suppressing the distinction. For example, we shall often use the term 'argument' to denote sequences of statements (as in our definition) as well as the sequences of sentences which express them. ARGUMENT STRUCTURE [CHAP. 1 I can't go to bed, Mom. The movie's not over yet. The building was a shabby, soot-covered brownstone in a decaying neighbor- hood. The scurrying of rats echoed in the empty halls. Everyone who is as talented as you are should receive a higher education. Go to college! We were vastly outnumbered and outgunned by the enemy, and their troops were constantly being reinforced while our forces were dwindling. Thus a direct frontal assault would have been suicidal. He was breathing and therefore alive. Is there anyone here who understands this document? Many in the U.S. do not know whether their country supports or opposes an international ban on the use of land mines. Triangle ABC is equiangular. Therefore each of its interior angles measures 60 degrees. Solution Premise: He was born in the first week of August. Conclusion: He's a Leo. Technically this is not an argument, because the first sentence is a question; but the question is merely rhetorical, suggesting the following argument: Premise: The trade deficit is rising every day. Conclusion: The economy cannot be improving. Premise: The movie's not over yet. Conclusion: I can't go to bed. Not an argument; there is no attempt here to provide evidence for a conclusion. Not an argument; 'Go to college!' expresses a command, not a statement. Yet the following argument is suggested: Premise: Everyone who is as talented as you are should receive a higher education. Conclusion: You should go to college. Premise: We were vastly outnumbered and outgunned by the enemy. Premise: Their troops were constantly being reinforced while our forces were dwindling. Conclusion: A direct frontal assault would have been suicidal. Though grammatically this is a single sentence, it makes two distinct statements, which together constitute the following argument: Premise: He was breathing. Conclusion: He was alive. Not an argument. Not an argument. Premise: Triangle ABC is equiangular. Conclusion: Each of its interior angles measures 60 degrees. Though the premises of an argument must be intended to prove or provide evidence for the conclusion, they need not actually do so. There are bad arguments as well as good ones. Argument l.l(c), for example, may be none too convincing; yet still it qualifies as an argument. The purpose of logic is precisely to develop methods and techniques to tell good arguments from bad ones3 3For evaluative purposes, it may be useful to regard the argument in l.l(c) as incomplete, requiring for its completion the implicit premise 'I can't go to bed until the movie is over'. (Implicit statements will be discussed in Section 1.6.) Even so, in most contexts this premise would itself be dubious enough to deprive the argument of any rationally compelling persuasive force. Since we are concerned in this chapter with argument structure, not argument evaluation, we shall usually not comment on the quality of arguments used as examples in this chapter. In no case does this lack of comment constitute a tacit endorsement. CHAP. 11 ARGUMENT STRUCTURE Notice also that whereas the conclusion occurs at the end of the arguments in our initial examples and in most of the arguments in Problem 1.1, in argument l.l(c) it occurs at the beginning. The conclusion may in fact occur anywhere in the argument, but the beginning and end are the most common positions. For purposes of analysis, however, it is customary to list the premises first, each on a separate line, and then to give the conclusion. The conclusion is often marked by the symbol ':.', which means "therefore." This format is called standard form. Thus the standard form of our initial example is: All humans are mortal. Socrates is human. :. Socrates is mortal. 1.2 IDENTIFYING ARGUMENTS Argument occurs only when someone intends a set of premises to support or prove a conclusion. This intention is often expressed by the use of inference indicatovs. Inference indicators are words or phrases used to signal the presence of an argument. They are of two kinds: conclusion indicators, which signal that the sentence which contains them or to which they are prefixed is a conclusion from previously stated premises, and premise indicators, which signal that the sentence to which they are prefixed is a premise. Here are some typical examples of each (these lists are by no means exhaustive): Conclusion Indicators Premise Indicators Therefore For Thus Since Hence Because So Assuming that For this reason Seeing that Accordingly Granted that Consequently This is true because This being so The reason is that It follows that For the reason that The moral is In view of the fact that Which proves that It is a fact that Which means that As shown by the fact that From which we can infer that Given that As a result Inasmuch as In conclusion One cannot doubt that Premise and conclusion indicators are the main clues in identifying arguments and analyzing their structure. When placed between two sentences to form a compound sentence, a conclusion indicator signals that the first expresses a premise and the second a conclus,ion from that premise (possibly along with others). In the same context, a premise indicator signals just the reverse. Thus, in the compound sentence He is not at home, so he has gone to the movie. the conclusion indicator 'so' signals that 'He has gone to the movie7 is a conclusion supported by the premise 'He is not at home7.But in the compound sentence He is not at home, since he has gone to the movie. ARGUMENT STRUCTURE [CHAP. 1 1.3 COMPLEX ARGUMENTS Some arguments proceed in stages. First a conclusion is drawn from a set of premises; then that conclusion (perhaps in conjunction with some other statements) is used as a premise to draw a further conclusion, which may in turn function as a premise for yet another conclusion, and so on. Such a structure is called a complex argument. Those premises which are intended as conclusions from previous premises are called nonbasic premises or intermediate conclusions (the two names reflect their dual role as conclusions of one step and premises of the next). Those which are not conclusions from previous premises are called basic premises or assumptions. For example, the following argument is complex: All rational numbers are expressible as a ratio of integers. But pi is not expressible as a ratio of integers. Therefore pi is not a rational number. Yet clearly pi is a number. Thus there exists at least one nonrational number. The conclusion is that there exists at least one nonrational number (namely, pi). This is supported directly by the premises 'pi is not a rational number' and 'pi is a number'. But the first of these premises is in turn an intermediate conclusion from the premises 'all rational numbers are expressible as a ratio of integers' and 'pi is not expressible as a ratio of integers'.
Recommended publications
  • Argumentation and Fallacies in Creationist Writings Against Evolutionary Theory Petteri Nieminen1,2* and Anne-Mari Mustonen1
    Nieminen and Mustonen Evolution: Education and Outreach 2014, 7:11 http://www.evolution-outreach.com/content/7/1/11 RESEARCH ARTICLE Open Access Argumentation and fallacies in creationist writings against evolutionary theory Petteri Nieminen1,2* and Anne-Mari Mustonen1 Abstract Background: The creationist–evolutionist conflict is perhaps the most significant example of a debate about a well-supported scientific theory not readily accepted by the public. Methods: We analyzed creationist texts according to type (young earth creationism, old earth creationism or intelligent design) and context (with or without discussion of “scientific” data). Results: The analysis revealed numerous fallacies including the direct ad hominem—portraying evolutionists as racists, unreliable or gullible—and the indirect ad hominem, where evolutionists are accused of breaking the rules of debate that they themselves have dictated. Poisoning the well fallacy stated that evolutionists would not consider supernatural explanations in any situation due to their pre-existing refusal of theism. Appeals to consequences and guilt by association linked evolutionary theory to atrocities, and slippery slopes to abortion, euthanasia and genocide. False dilemmas, hasty generalizations and straw man fallacies were also common. The prevalence of these fallacies was equal in young earth creationism and intelligent design/old earth creationism. The direct and indirect ad hominem were also prevalent in pro-evolutionary texts. Conclusions: While the fallacious arguments are irrelevant when discussing evolutionary theory from the scientific point of view, they can be effective for the reception of creationist claims, especially if the audience has biases. Thus, the recognition of these fallacies and their dismissal as irrelevant should be accompanied by attempts to avoid counter-fallacies and by the recognition of the context, in which the fallacies are presented.
    [Show full text]
  • Section 6: Reporting Likelihood Ratios Components
    Section 6: Reporting Likelihood Ratios Components • Hierarchy of propositions • Formulating propositions • Communicating LRs Section 6 Slide 2 Likelihood Ratio The LR assigns a numerical value in favor or against one propo- sition over another: Pr(EjHp;I) LR = ; Pr(EjHd;I) where Hp typically aligns with the prosecution case, Hd is a reasonable alternative consistent with the defense case, and I is the relevant background information. Section 6 Slide 3 Setting Propositions • The value for the LR will depend on the propositions chosen: different sets of propositions will lead to different LRs. • Choosing the appropriate pair of propositions can therefore be just as important as the DNA analysis itself. Section 6 Slide 4 Hierarchy of Propositions Evett & Cook (1998) established the following hierarchy of propositions: Level Scale Example III Offense Hp: The suspect raped the complainant. Hd: Some other person raped the complainant. II Activity Hp: The suspect had intercourse with the complainant. Hd: Some other person had intercourse with the complainant. I Source Hp: The semen came from the suspect. Hd: The semen came from an unknown person. 0 Sub-source Hp: The DNA in the sample came from the suspect. Hd: The DNA in the sample came from an unknown person. Section 6 Slide 5 Hierarchy of Propositions • The offense level deals with the ultimate issue of guilt/ innocence, which are outside the domain of the forensic scientist. • The activity level associates a DNA profile or evidence source with the crime itself, and there may be occasions where a scientist can address this level. • The source level associates a DNA profile or evidence item with a particular body fluid or individual source.
    [Show full text]
  • False Dilemma Wikipedia Contents
    False dilemma Wikipedia Contents 1 False dilemma 1 1.1 Examples ............................................... 1 1.1.1 Morton's fork ......................................... 1 1.1.2 False choice .......................................... 2 1.1.3 Black-and-white thinking ................................... 2 1.2 See also ................................................ 2 1.3 References ............................................... 3 1.4 External links ............................................. 3 2 Affirmative action 4 2.1 Origins ................................................. 4 2.2 Women ................................................ 4 2.3 Quotas ................................................. 5 2.4 National approaches .......................................... 5 2.4.1 Africa ............................................ 5 2.4.2 Asia .............................................. 7 2.4.3 Europe ............................................ 8 2.4.4 North America ........................................ 10 2.4.5 Oceania ............................................ 11 2.4.6 South America ........................................ 11 2.5 International organizations ...................................... 11 2.5.1 United Nations ........................................ 12 2.6 Support ................................................ 12 2.6.1 Polls .............................................. 12 2.7 Criticism ............................................... 12 2.7.1 Mismatching ......................................... 13 2.8 See also
    [Show full text]
  • INCLAN-DISSERTATION-2021.Pdf
    A METHOD FOR SYSTEM OF SYSTEMS DEFINITION AND MODELING USING PATTERNS OF COLLECTIVE BEHAVIOR A Dissertation Presented to The Academic Faculty by Eric Inclan In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the School of Aerospace Engineering Georgia Institute of Technology May 2021 COPYRIGHT © 2021 BY ERIC INCLAN A METHOD FOR SYSTEM OF SYSTEMS DEFINITION AND MODELING USING PATTERNS OF COLLECTIVE BEHAVIOR Approved by: Dr. Dimitri Mavris, Advisor Dr. Jean Charles Domerçant School of Aerospace Engineering Georgia Tech Research Institute Georgia Institute of Technology Dr. Michael J. Steffens Dr. Santiago Balestrini-Robinson School of Aerospace Engineering Georgia Tech Research Institute Georgia Institute of Technology Dr. Daniel P. Schrage School of Aerospace Engineering Georgia Institute of Technology Date Approved: April 29, 2021 DEDICATION To my family iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First and foremost, I would like to thank Dr. Mavris for his sense of humor, patience, leadership, and support. Your feedback has always been as accurate and valuable as it has been incisive. I will undoubtedly be a better scientist and engineer for it, and I am grateful for all the guidance you have given me. I want to thank all of the Georgia Tech faculty and staff that I had the privilege to learn from and work for, for embodying a level of professionalism, talent, depth of understanding, empathy, and diligence that is very hard to find, let alone in one place. I would like to thank my lab-mates, and in particular John Mines, Stephanie Zhu, Arturo Santa, and Katie Handschuh Fuerst, for listening when I needed someone to talk to.
    [Show full text]
  • Ad Hominem Fallacy Examples Donald Trump
    Ad Hominem Fallacy Examples Donald Trump Presentationism and conic Ulick economized her demolishment ohmmeter quadrupled and headreach Saunderszoologically. stipulate When hisMarve verligte platted fidges his folkmootyeomanly, sparging but Himyarite not sudden Rad neverenough, begs is Emmeryso betweentimes. divisionism? But abortion is made these ideas survive and firm Equivocation is a type of ambiguity in which a single word or phrase has two or more distinct meanings, transfer blame to others, as they often show how much the product is being enjoyed by large groups of people. Trump has also awarded Presidential Medals of Freedom to former Sen. Or a young, comments like these are reminding some people of an old Soviet tactic known as whataboutism. Some topics are on motherhood and some are not. The green cheese causes compulsive buying is when it is. While such characterizations as the one above reflect part of the reason why informal fallacies prove powerful and intellectually seductive it suffers from two weaknesses. Kennedy before he is this is an ad hominem fallacy examples donald trump uses cookies that donald trump is true than a few examples. Guilt By Association Fallacy, and music and dance and so many other avenues to help them express what has happened to them in their lives during this horrific year. And now, one of the most common is the Ad Hominem fallacy, other times the wholepat assumption proves false resulting in a fallacy of composition. If we are to make informed judgments about the candidates, which focused on. Knowing and studying fallacies is important because this will help people avoid committing them.
    [Show full text]
  • A) Bandwagon Effect the Bandwagon Effect Is a Phenomenon Whereby the Rate of Uptake of Beliefs, Ideas, Fads and Trends Increa
    A) Bandwagon effect The bandwagon effect is a phenomenon whereby the rate of uptake of beliefs, ideas, fads and trends increases the more that they have already been adopted by others. In other words, the bandwagon effect is characterized by the probability of individual adoption increasing with respect to the proportion who have already done so.[1] As more people come to believe in something, others also "hop on the bandwagon" regardless of the underlying evidence. (Wikipedia) B) Glittering generalities A glittering generality (also called glowing generality) is an emotionally appealing phrase so closely associated with highly valued concepts and beliefs that it carries conviction without supporting information or reason. Such highly valued concepts attract general approval and acclaim. Their appeal is to emotions such as love of country and home, and desire for peace, freedom, glory, and honor. They ask for approval without examination of the reason. They are typically used by politicians and propagandists. (Wikipedia) C) Plain folks A plain folks argument is one in which the speaker presents him or herself as an average Joe — a common person who can understand and empathize with a listener's concerns. The most important part of this appeal is the speaker's portrayal of themselves as someone who has had a similar experience to the listener and knows why they may be skeptical or cautious about accepting the speaker's point of view. In this way, the speaker gives the audience a sense of trust and comfort, believing that the speaker and the audience share common goals and that they thus should agree with the speaker.
    [Show full text]
  • Appendix 1 a Great Big List of Fallacies
    Why Brilliant People Believe Nonsense Appendix 1 A Great Big List of Fallacies To avoid falling for the "Intrinsic Value of Senseless Hard Work Fallacy" (see also "Reinventing the Wheel"), I began with Wikipedia's helpful divisions, list, and descriptions as a base (since Wikipedia articles aren't subject to copyright restrictions), but felt free to add new fallacies, and tweak a bit here and there if I felt further explanation was needed. If you don't understand a fallacy from the brief description below, consider Googling the name of the fallacy, or finding an article dedicated to the fallacy in Wikipedia. Consider the list representative rather than exhaustive. Informal fallacies These arguments are fallacious for reasons other than their structure or form (formal = the "form" of the argument). Thus, informal fallacies typically require an examination of the argument's content. • Argument from (personal) incredulity (aka - divine fallacy, appeal to common sense) – I cannot imagine how this could be true, therefore it must be false. • Argument from repetition (argumentum ad nauseam) – signifies that it has been discussed so extensively that nobody cares to discuss it anymore. • Argument from silence (argumentum e silentio) – the conclusion is based on the absence of evidence, rather than the existence of evidence. • Argument to moderation (false compromise, middle ground, fallacy of the mean, argumentum ad temperantiam) – assuming that the compromise between two positions is always correct. • Argumentum verbosium – See proof by verbosity, below. • (Shifting the) burden of proof (see – onus probandi) – I need not prove my claim, you must prove it is false. • Circular reasoning (circulus in demonstrando) – when the reasoner begins with (or assumes) what he or she is trying to end up with; sometimes called assuming the conclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • Type Your Frontispiece Or Quote Page Here
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Memorial University Research Repository DEFENDING THE INDEFENSIBLE? THE USE OF ARGUMENTATION, LEGITIMATION, AND OTHERING IN DEBATES ON REFUGEES IN THE CANADIAN HOUSE OF COMMONS, 2010-2012 by © James Thomas Ernest Baker A Thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Sociology Faculty of Arts Memorial University of Newfoundland April 2015 St. John’s, Newfoundland and Labrador Abstract The goal of this thesis is to investigate language use among elite parliamentarians in debates related to refugee asylum. It challenges the non-political “taken for granted” notions that many parliamentarians employ in their speeches and, using Critical Discourse Analysis, seeks to understand how argumentation, legitimation, and Othering strategies are used to support and reinforce their positions. While the Conservative government contends that Bill C-11: The Balanced Refugee Reform Act and Bill C-31: Protecting Canada’s Immigration System Act are aimed at refugee reform and designed to target “criminal middlemen,” I argue that their approach is actually aimed at restricting refugee asylum, despite the fact that it is an internationally recognized treaty right. To augment my efforts, I frame my analysis around the work of two key theorists: Antonio Gramsci and Zygmunt Bauman. The Gramscian model of cultural hegemony informs my thesis in at least two key ways: first, I argue that language use (specifically, the negative portrayal of asylum seekers) is manipulated for the sole purpose of presenting refugee claimants as criminals; second, by criminalizing certain groups, the Conservative government is able to put forward a particular worldview that portrays certain types of refugees as legitimate, and therefore deserving of protection.
    [Show full text]
  • <I>Ad Hominem</I>
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 11-3-2016 Instattack: Instagram and Visual Ad Hominem Political Arguments Sophia Evangeline Gourgiotis University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Other Communication Commons, and the Rhetoric Commons Scholar Commons Citation Gourgiotis, Sophia Evangeline, "Instattack: Instagram and Visual Ad Hominem Political Arguments" (2016). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/6508 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Instattack: Instagram and Visual Ad Hominem Political Arguments by Sophia E. Gourgiotis A thesis submitted in parital fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Master of Arts with a concentration of Rhetoric and Composition Department of English College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Meredith Johnson, Ph.D. Elizabeth Metzger, Ph.D. Joseph Moxley, Ph.D. Date of Approval: October 27, 2016 Keywords: Presidential Rhetoric, Social Networking Sites, Visual Rhetoric, Ethos Copyright © 2016, Sophia E. Gourgiotis Dedication For my Dad, whose unwavering strength continuously inspires, who taught me that happiness is life’s most important purpose and that love has no boundaries. This thesis was written for and because of you. I love and miss you. Acknowledgments I would like to thank my committee for their thoughtful feedback, encouragement, and dedication throughout the duration of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Organizing and Outlining Your Speech Copyright 2010 Cengage Learning
    Organizing 8 and Outlining Your Speech Read it • The Parts of a Speech 146 • Putting Your Ideas Together: • Organizing the Body of Your Speech 146 The Complete-Sentence Outline 160 • Connecting Your Ideas with Transitions 158 • Sample Complete-Sentence Outline for Review and Analysis 165 Watch it • Reviewing Patterns of Organization 157 Linking Effectively: Transitions 161 • ge Learning ge gag ng Cengage Learning Cengage Cen Cen Use it • Everything in Its Place 157 Polite to Point 161 • Cengage Learning Review it • Directory of Study and Review Resources 168 Copyright 2010 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it. Ch008.indd 144 07/10/10 6:53 PM hen you organize a speech well, audience members follow Wyour ideas more easily and better understand what you have to say. In addition, good organization helps you stay on track, keeping your purpose and thesis in mind. With a thoughtful plan for the order in which you want to present your points, you’ll feel more confi dent. Organizing your speech is like planning a trip: Reaching your destination is much less stressful when you know how to get there. In addition, when your speech is well organized, audience members don’t need to worry about where you are in your speech, where you’ve been, or where you’re going.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Truth-Functional Logic
    Rules and Principles used in The Many Worlds of Logic 1. Truth-Functional Logic (Chapters 2-11 of The Many Worlds of Logic) Truth-Tables Conjunction Disjunction Conditional P Q P & Q PQ P v Q PQ P Q T T T TT T TT T T F F TF T TF F F T F FT T FT T F F F FF F FF T Biconditional Negation PQ P Q P ~P TT T T F TF F F T FT F FF T Logical Status A formula is a truth-functional tautology if and only if the final column of its truth- table is all T s. A formula is a truth-functional contradiction if and only if the final column of its truth-table is all F s. A formula is truth-functionally contingent if and only if the final column of its truth- table contains at least one T and at least one F. An argument is truth-functionally valid if and only if its truth-table contains no row with all true premises and a false conclusion. An argument is truth-functionally invalid if and only if its truth-table contains at least one row with all true premises and a false conclusion. Two formulas are truth-functionally equivalent if and only if the final columns on their respective truth-tables match. Truth-functional Inference Rules Disjunctive Syllogism (DS) Modus Ponens (MP) From: P v Q From: P Q and ~P and P You may infer: Q You may infer: Q Modus Tollens (MT) Hypothetical Syllogism (HS) From: P Q From: P Q and: ~Q and Q R You may infer: ~P You may infer: P R Simplification (Simp) Conjunction (Conj) From: P & Q From: P You may infer: P and: Q You may infer: Q You may infer: P & Q Addition (Add) Constructive Dilemma (CD) From: P From: P Q You may infer: P v Q and: R S and: P v R You may infer: Q v S Rule of Indirect Proof (IP) Anywhere in a proof, you may indent, assume ~ P, derive a contradiction, end the indentation, and assert P.
    [Show full text]
  • List of Fallacies
    List of fallacies For specific popular misconceptions, see List of common if>). The following fallacies involve inferences whose misconceptions. correctness is not guaranteed by the behavior of those log- ical connectives, and hence, which are not logically guar- A fallacy is an incorrect argument in logic and rhetoric anteed to yield true conclusions. Types of propositional fallacies: which undermines an argument’s logical validity or more generally an argument’s logical soundness. Fallacies are either formal fallacies or informal fallacies. • Affirming a disjunct – concluding that one disjunct of a logical disjunction must be false because the These are commonly used styles of argument in convinc- other disjunct is true; A or B; A, therefore not B.[8] ing people, where the focus is on communication and re- sults rather than the correctness of the logic, and may be • Affirming the consequent – the antecedent in an in- used whether the point being advanced is correct or not. dicative conditional is claimed to be true because the consequent is true; if A, then B; B, therefore A.[8] 1 Formal fallacies • Denying the antecedent – the consequent in an indicative conditional is claimed to be false because the antecedent is false; if A, then B; not A, therefore Main article: Formal fallacy not B.[8] A formal fallacy is an error in logic that can be seen in the argument’s form.[1] All formal fallacies are specific types 1.2 Quantification fallacies of non sequiturs. A quantification fallacy is an error in logic where the • Appeal to probability – is a statement that takes quantifiers of the premises are in contradiction to the something for granted because it would probably be quantifier of the conclusion.
    [Show full text]