The Bipolar Longings of Thumos: a Feminist Rereading of Plato's Republic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Bipolar Longings of Thumos: a Feminist Rereading of Plato's Republic The Bipolar Longings of Thumos: A Feminist Rereading of Plato's Republic CHRISTINA TARNOPOLSKY, McGill University Plato's treatment of thumos in the Republic might seem like an odd place to look for mining fresh feminist insights into the complex and political character of human desire. 1 The dialogue itself is often seen as one in which human desire is down played in favor of the godlike and self-sufficient philosopher-kings who are quite unlike the erotic, needy, and striving Socrates of Plato's Symposium (Bloom 1968, 423; Williams 1993, 98-102). For this very reason, feminists have usually looked to the latter dialogue in order to derive a notion of classical desire, either from the Aristophanic notion of eros as a striving for one's better half or from Diotima's notion of eros as a striving for wholeness and as the desire to give birth to a new self in the presence of the beloved. More pro­ blematically, Plato's treatment of thumos in the Republic has primarily been co-opted by conservative, anti-feminist thinkers who see it as the manly and warlike passion of anger or spiritedness that animates men's souls (Berns 1984, 335-348; Bloom 1968, 355, 376). Even commenta­ tors who do not share these kinds of political views tend to see Platonic thumos as that element of the soul which counters desire or eros be­ cause it counters those desires that are lodged in the epithumetic (appetitive/desiring) part of the soul (Koziak 2000, 75, 77; Allen 2000b, 252).2 In this paper I hope to challenge all of these views of the Republic by looking at the complex bipolar longings that characterize Plato's notion of thumos. While Plato does argue that thumos is different from the kinds of appetitive desires for sex, food, and drink that are lodged in the epithumetic part of the soul, he does not see thumos as lacking its own unique desires and longings. In Book Eight he makes it clear that the most political kinds of desires are lodged in this part of the soul when he www.s-ympos-ium-journal.com declares that the thumotic element (to thumoeides) is both victory-loving and honor-loving (philonikon ... kai philotimon) (Rep. 581bl-2). Al­ though Plato uses the traditional Greek notion of philia (affection/ friend­ ship) instead of eros (love/desire) in this passage to deSignate these longings (Liddell and Scott 1996, 1934, 691), his comprehensive teaching on thumos in the Republic is meant to show how these desires are distinct from the affection for those like us (philia) and from the desire for what is different from us (eros) because it involves the simultaneous desire to assert one's difference from others and to be recognized as like 298 The Bipolar Longings of Thumos The Bipolar Longings of Thumos 299 these others.3 I will also argue that Plato's treatment of thumos and the The flipside of this critique of the Athenians consists of Plato's critique bipolar longings that constitute it resonates more with contemporary of his teacher, Socrates. In coming to a deeper understanding of the thu­ psychoanalytic and feminist challenges to the classical Freudian theory of motic element of the soul, Plato realized that if he were to effect a desire than either the complementarity of Aristophanes's teaching on change in his fellow citizens or future democrats, then he would also 4 eros or the autoeroticism of Diotima's teaching on eros. Here I will be have to change the method of his and their teacher, Socrates. He would looking at Andrew Morrison's work, Shame: The Underside of Narcissism have to temper not just the wildness and harshness of the Athenians's and Jessica Benjamin's work, The Bonds of Love: Psychoanalysis, Femi­ opposition to Socratic philosophy, but also the wildness and harshness of nism and the Problem of Domination, both of which challenge central socrates's philosophic nature (Bloom 1968, xvii) as this is dramatized in tenets of Freud's theory of desire as well as his theory of infantile nar­ the first book of the Republic. Accordingly, in the first part of this paper I cissism and omnipotence. I will argue that Plato's treatment of the turn to the problematic character of the Socratic elenchus as this comes 5 bipolar or bidirectional longings of thumos involves a notion of the subtle to light in the first book of the Republic. Here I argue that the interplay, harmony, and attunement between two needy and vulnerable aggressiveness and desire for omnipotence so central to the tyrant's soul beings, neither of whom seeks either complete domination over, or also lurks within the soul of Socrates. I also show that the diagnosis submission to, the other. Like Benjamin, Plato's theory of the funda­ Plato makes of the failed transference between Socrates and Thrasyma­ mentally social and intersubjective character of human being requires chus bears striking similarities to the failed intersubjectivity between the seeing assertion and recognition, the desire for distinction and the desire patient and therapist or the child and caretaker diagnosed by Morrison for connection, as equally primordial longings that are in productive and Benjamin, respectively. tension with one another in human life (Benjamin 1988, 12-28). Indeed, it is precisely because of Plato's deepening understanding of I will also argue that like Benjamin and Morrison, Plato saw the the bipolar desires characteristic of thumos that he is able to portray a potential for a breakdown of this productive tension or mutuality into the gentler, more musical, and more caring Socrates in Books Two through problematic desires for domination and submission (Benjamin) or omni­ Ten of the Republic. It is this Platonic Socrates whose newfound qualities potence (Morrison). Indeed my revision of the traditional interpretation will then reverberate in the souls of Glaucon and Adeimantus through a of Platonic thumos also requires a reorientation in our way of thinking much more positive process of transference. In the second section of the about the Republic and of Plato's complex relationship both to demo­ paper, I argue that the characters of Glaucon and Adeimantus dra­ cratic Athens and to his teacher, Socrates. Instead of reading the matically illustrate the two different elements of thumos, which need to Republic as an unambiguous defense of Socrates and his particular brand be harmonized properly and balanced in human life in order to avoid the of philosophy, and as a total rejection of Athenian democratic politics, I problematic desires for either total domination of (Glaucon) or sub­ see the Republic as actually containing Plato's own diagnosis of what it servience to (Adeimantus) others. In the third section of the paper, I was about Socratic philosophy and Plato's Athenian contemporaries that argue that Platonic thumos is distinct from both philia (fondness for resulted in such a problematic relationship between them. In Book One those like ourselves) and eros (desire for what is different from our­ of the Republic Plato actually shows that there is a problematic desire for selves) because it involves the simultaneous recognition of our similarity omnipotence and domination lurking in the souls of both Socrates and and differences from others. In the conclusion of the paper I show pre­ Socrates's interlocutors who secretly or not so secretly (Thrasymachus) cisely why the new Platonic musical education of thumos involves admire the tyrant's domination of everyone around him. For Plato, such maintaining a harmonious balance or tension between its two poles of fantasies of omnipotence and domination were central to the Athenian harshness and gentleness, self-assertion and caring for others. The mas­ imperialistic democratic imaginary, which predisposed the Athenians both culine, war-like and angry guardian, so often taken as the paradigm of collectively and individually to admire covertly the tyrant and his freedom Platonic thumos, can now be seen as an overdevelopment of just one of from all forms of restraint as the model for a false kind of democratic the two poles or musical modes that ought to comprise the delicate freedom (Tarnopolsky 2004, 482-3). I believe that the next nine books harmony of a well-balanced and finely tuned thumos. of the Republic represent Plato's attempt to replace this very problematic normative imaginary with one that instantiates more reasonable norms of engagement between needy and vulnerable beings. 300 The Bipolar Longings of Thumos The Bipolar Longings of Thumos 301 The Limitations of the Socratic Elenchus in RepublicOne kind of immoderation that can plague this dialectical interaction, thus harming both the "patient" and the "doctor" or "therapist." In Book One of the Republic, Socrates's arguments with Cephalus, I want to argue that Socrates's gluttony and indigestion dramatically Polemarchus, and Thrasymachus dramatically illustrate that the Socratic illustrate Plato's own diagnosis of the limitations of his teacher's method elenchus cannot suffice to persuade one's interlocutors to change their of comportment towards others. In Book One, Socrates never allows views even when they have been shown to be contradictory or either himself or his interlocutors to come to a fully adequate under­ inconsistent by this logical method of refutation. The most it can do is to standing of what justice is before proceeding to investigate whether it is make the person perplexed, and they may, like Cephalus, laugh the a virtue or a vice, and then whether it is profitable or unprofitable for refutation off and run away to make sacrifices (Rep. 331dl-8), or like human beings (Rep. 354b2-10). What has been said about justice in Polemarchus simply switch their views in response to the twists and Book I might well be truthful, but it has come out in such a way that turns of an argument (Rep.
Recommended publications
  • Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected]
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 3-20-2014 Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Coakley, Melissa Marie, "Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature" (2014). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/4999 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aeschynē in Aristotle’s Conception of Human Nature by Melissa M. Coakley A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Science University of South Florida Major Professor: Joanne Waugh, Ph.D. Bruce Silver, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Date of Approval: March 20, 2014 Keywords: Shame, Anaeschyntia, Aidōs, Aischynē, Ancient Greek Passions Copyright © 2014, Melissa M. Coakley DEDICATION This manuscript is dedicated to my husband Bill Murray and to my parents: Joan and Richard Coakley. Thank you for your endless support, encouragement, and friendship. To Dr. John P. Anton, I have learned from you the importance of having a “ton of virtue and a shield of nine layers for protection from the abysmal depths of vice.” Thank you for believing in me, my dear friend.
    [Show full text]
  • Second Edition Neel Burton Bsc, MBBS, Mrcpsych, MA (Phil), AKC Green Templeton College University of Oxford, Oxford, UK
    Psychiatry Psychiatry Second edition Neel Burton BSc, MBBS, MRCPsych, MA (Phil), AKC Green Templeton College University of Oxford, Oxford, UK A John Wiley & Sons, Ltd., Publication This edition fi rst published 2010, © 2006, 2010 by Neel Burton Blackwell Publishing was acquired by John Wiley & Sons in February 2007. Blackwell’s publishing program has been merged with Wiley’s global Scientifi c, Technical and Medical business to form Wiley-Blackwell. Registered offi ce: John Wiley & Sons Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK Editorial offi ces: 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK 111 River Street, Hoboken, NJ 07030-5774, USA For details of our global editorial offi ces, for customer services and for information about how to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at www.wiley.com/wiley-blackwell The right of the author to be identifi ed as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher. Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books. Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks.
    [Show full text]
  • Moving Thumos: Emotion, Image, and the Enthymeme Eric D
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2007 Moving Thumos: Emotion, image, and the enthymeme Eric D. Mason University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons Scholar Commons Citation Mason, Eric D., "Moving Thumos: Emotion, image, and the enthymeme" (2007). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/2279 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Moving Thumos: Emotion, Image, and the Enthymeme Eric D. Mason A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of English College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Co-Major Professor: Lynn Worsham, Ph.D. Co-Major Professor: Debra Jacobs, Ph.D. Gary Olson, Ph.D. Elizabeth Hirsh, Ph.D. William A. Kealy, Ph.D. Date of Approval: March 29, 2007 Keywords: rhetoric, affect, politics, visual, composition © Copyright 2007, Eric D. Mason Table of Contents Abstract ............................................................................................................iii Chapter 1 – Introduction: A Vision of Thumos .................................................. 1 Internal Di-visions .................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Glory-Seeking: a Timeless and Puzzling Craving of the Human Soul
    Glory-Seeking: A Timeless and Puzzling Craving of the Human Soul Author: Eric Marturano Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3865 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2014 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. BOSTON COLLEGE GLORY-SEEKING: A TIMELESS AND PUZZLING CRAVING OF THE HUMAN SOUL A Senior Honors Thesis Submitted to The College of Arts and Sciences Philosophy Department By ERIC MARTURANO May 1, 2014 © Copyright by ERIC THOMAS MARTURANO 2014 ABSTRACT Glory-seeking: A Timeless & Puzzling Craving of the Human Soul Written by: Eric Marturano Advised by: Professor Christopher Constas Philosophers throughout the ages have grappled with the concept of glory-seeking and have offered many different references, analyses, insights, and explanations. Three great thinkers in particular stand out above the rest: Plato, Thomas Hobbes, and Jean-Paul Sartre. While these three minds span from circa 420 BC all the way up to 1980 AD, they all would agree that glory-seeking certainly matters – they would most likely argue over the following: In what way? For Plato, glory-seeking is an inherent part of the human soul. It matters because it is an essential part of our being. Plato’s model for the soul found in The Republic as well as a comparable illustration in the Phaedrus expresses this claim most thoroughly. Additional support for the idea of glory-seeking being an existing precondition of humanity can be found in other ancient works as well, most notably Homer’s Iliad.
    [Show full text]
  • The Passions of Achilles
    The Passions of Achilles and Aeneas: Translating Greece into Rome The great critic I.A. Richards produced an abridged translation of Homer's Iliad under the title, The Wrath of Achilles (1950), and to most scholars, the title will seem well chosen (cf. Robert Graves' translation of the entire poem, under the title, The Anger of Achilles [1959]). The poem begins, famously, with the word mênis, an elevated term that, like wrath, is often associated with divine anger: the anger is that of Achilles, who, enraged by the demeaning treatment he receives at the hands of Agamemnon, withraws from the war and nurses his resentment until his dearest friend, Patroclus, is slain by the Trojan leader Hector; at this point, overcome by grief, he returns to battle to avenge the death by killing Hector. In his anguish, Achilles abuses the corpse of his enemy, until even the gods are appalled at his inhumanity; in the end, he accepts a ransom from Hector's father, Priam, and the poem concludes on a note of reconciliation, though it is mixed with mourning among the Trojans over the loss of their champion. Virgil's Aeneid, which is modelled on both Homeric epics, the Iliad and the Odyssey, in almost obsessive detail and yet transforms them at every turn, begins and ends with anger. Instead of the mutual regard between Achilles and Priam that 1 characterizes the final scene of the Iliad, Virgil chose to conclude with a duel between the champions on either side, Trojan and Latin: Aeneas slaughters Turnus in an access of fury brought on by an accidental reminder of the death of his young ally, Pallas, at Turnus' hands.
    [Show full text]
  • Bipolar Disorder
    Bipolar Disorder PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Thu, 08 Dec 2011 00:32:40 UTC Contents Articles Overview 1 Bipolar disorder 1 History 18 History of bipolar disorder 18 Emil Kraepelin 20 Karl Leonhard 24 John Cade 26 Mogens Schou 29 Frederick K. Goodwin 31 Kay Redfield Jamison 33 Symptoms 36 Hallucination 36 Delusion 44 Emotional dysregulation 50 Anhedonia 51 Dysphoria 53 Suicidal ideation 55 Sleep disorder 58 Hypersomnia 63 Insomnia 66 Psychosis 78 Racing thoughts 89 Bipolar spectrum 90 Bipolar spectrum 90 Bipolar I 91 Bipolar II 93 Cyclothymia 101 Dysthymia 103 Major depressive disorder 108 Schizoaffective disorder 138 Mania 147 Mixed state 153 Hypomania 155 Major depressive episode 159 Treatment 163 Treatment of bipolar disorder 163 Carbamazepine 170 Gabapentin 176 Lamotrigine 186 Oxcarbazepine 195 Topiramate 199 Valproic acid 206 Sodium valproate 215 Valproate semisodium 220 Lithium pharmacology 222 Lithium carbonate 229 Lithium citrate 232 Lithium sulfate 234 Non-pharmaceutical treatment 236 Clinical psychology 236 Electroconvulsive therapy 253 Involuntary commitment 274 Light therapy 285 Psychotherapy 291 Transcranial magnetic stimulation 304 Related subjects 311 Affective spectrum 311 List of people with bipolar disorder 312 Bipolar disorder in children 324 Organisations 330 International Society for Bipolar Disorders 330 Icarus Project 332 References Article Sources and Contributors 335 Image Sources, Licenses and Contributors 343 Article
    [Show full text]
  • Daniel-M.-Haybron-The-Pursuit-Of
    THE PURSUIT OF UNHAPPINESS This page intentionally left blank The Pursuit of Unhappiness The Elusive Psychology of Well-Being DANIEL M. HAYBRON 1 1 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Daniel M. Haybron 2008 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2008 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available Typeset by Laserwords Private Limited, Chennai, India Printed in Great Britain on acid-free paper by Biddles Ltd, King’s Lynn, Norfolk ISBN 978–0–19–954598–8 13579108642 In memory of Alice and Ron This page intentionally left blank Preface We cannot think clearly about a plant or animal until we have a name for it.
    [Show full text]
  • Epinician Precepts
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by University of Birmingham Research Archive, E-theses Repository EPINICIAN PRECEPTS: A STUDY OF CHIRON AND THE WISE ADVISER IN PINDAR By JONATHAN MILES HALLIWELL A Thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham For the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Classics School of Historical Studies The University of Birmingham September 2008 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. EPINICIAN PRECEPTS: A STUDY OF CHIRON AND THE WISE ADVISER IN PINDAR ABSTRACT This thesis offers a fresh appraisal of the wise adviser in Pindar's epinician poetry. By focusing on the prominent figure of Chiron, it shows how Pindar engages with the paraenetic tradition in a way that reveals the distinctive character of the epinician poet. The first part of the study explores the function of Chiron as an interactive model for Pindar as poet-teacher. Chapter 1 examines how the mythical pedagogue enhances the status of the poet as wise adviser by illuminating the moral character of his advice. It shows how the relationship between teacher and pupil in the myth provides a model for that of poet and addressee and enables the poet to present his advice indirectly.
    [Show full text]
  • Thumos and Doxa As Intermediates in the Republic
    OLIVIER RENAUT | 71 Thumos and doxa as intermediates in the Republic Olivier Renaut Université Paris Nanterre [email protected] ABSTRACT Broadly speaking, something can be called intermediate for Plato insofar as it occupies a place between two objects, poles, places, time, or principles. But this broad meaning of the intermediate has been eclipsed by the Aristo- telian critique of the intermediate objects of the dianoia, so that it has become more difficult to think of the intermediates as functions of the soul. The aim of this paper is to show how, in the Republic, thumos is analogously treated as an intermediate with other kinds of intermediate ob- jects, and tentatively to relate this psychological intermediate in a broader theory with doxa, as its epistemological ground in the course of action. Keywords: intermediate, thumos, doxa, opinion, spirit, metaxu https://doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_18_6 72 | Thumos and doxa as intermediates in the Republic INTRODUCTION soul (with reason and desire) to a tripartition, thumos introduces a new way of thinking of When it comes to “intermediates” in Plato, the relation between reason and desire: thumos one is tempted to think solely of mathematical is immediately thought to be a metaxu. As for intermediates, the objects of dianoia in book 6 doxa, which we take to mean opinion, but also of the Republic. Whether or not it comes from belief, this is certainly an ubiquitous concept Aristotle’s critique on such intermediates, one in Plato’s dialogues which is not tied with any must admit that he himself forgets to describe systematic presentation; nevertheless, as it will as intermediates some of the most important be shown, doxa is presented in the Republic as a aspects of Plato’s psychology and ethical the­ metaxu too, between knowledge and ignorance, ory1.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Nature in Hobbes and Thucydides
    Human Nature in Hobbes and Thucydides by Jonathan Wensveen A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Political Science Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario Canada © 2013 Jonathan Wensveen Abstract As a close reader, translator, and self-professed admirer of Thucydides, Thomas Hobbes was heavily influenced by the former’s account of human nature, provided in his History of the Peloponnesian War. In fact, many scholars (in both political theory and international relations) have been keen to point out just this. Passages, they argue, such as the Plague at Athens and the Civil War at Corcyra, both of which reveal human nature at its darkest, undoubtedly shaped Hobbes’s own understanding and conception of man, the most comprehensive account of which appears in the first part of his most famous and mature work, Leviathan. What many of these scholars fail to acknowledge, however, is that for all of their similarities Thucydides’ account of human nature is also somewhat different from that of Hobbes. Indeed, although Thucydides often describes man at his worst, his History also provides moving examples of man at his best. In contrast to passages such as the Plague at Athens and the Civil War at Corcyra, passages such as the Mytilenean Debate and Pericles’ Funeral Oration highlight the human concern and capacity for virtue and justice, and indicate a recognition on the part of Thucydides (as opposed to Hobbes) that, despite what the primordial imposes on human beings they nevertheless and at the same time yearn for something higher.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and the Hero
    PLATO AND THE HERO Plato's thinking on courage, manliness and heroism is both profound and central to his work, but these areas of his thought remain under-explored. This book examines his developing critique of both the notions and embodiments of manliness prevalent in his culture (particularly those in Homer), and his attempt to redefine them in accordance with his own ethical, psychological and metaphysical principles. It further seeks to locate the discussion within the framework of his general approach to ethics, an approach which focuses chiefly on concepts of flourishing and virtue. The question of why courage is necessary in the flourishing life in its turn leads to Plato's bid to unify the noble and the beneficial, and the tensions this unification creates between human and di- vine ideals. The issue of manliness also raises problems of gender: does Plato conceive of the ethical subject as human or male? ANGELA HOBBS is Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Warwick. PLATO AND THE HERO Courage, Manliness and the Impersonal Good ANGELA HOBBS University of Warwick CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521417334 © Cambridge University Press 2000 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind and Brain: Toward an Understanding of Dualism
    Chapter 18 Mind and Brain: Toward an Understanding of Dualism Kristopher G. Phillips , Alan Beretta , and Harry A. Whitaker 18.1 The Views of Antiquity Starting two and half millennia ago in Greek antiquity and continuing to twenty- fi rst century paradoxes, the story of dualism – the mind-brain problem – has many varia- tions but retains some common themes. One of the earliest natural- philosophical investigations of the mind can be found in Homer’s Iliad and Odyssey, epic poems thought to have been written in the seventh or eighth century BCE (Green and Groff 2003 ). While one assumes that Homer’s main intention was to write heroic poetry and not to describe a psychological theory, his work nevertheless contains some interesting insights into the precursors of Western theories of mind. First, the Homeric Greeks appear not to have had a cohesive conception of mind nor of body (Jaynes 1990 ); there are no terms in Homer for words comparable to “soul” or “mind” or “thinking” or “perceiving” (Russo and Simon 1968 ). Instead in the Iliad and Odyssey we fi nd terms such as psyche , thymos , menos , phrenes , a n d ate (Green and Groff 2003 ) . The word psyche appears in the fi rst sentence of the Iliad. In both the Iliad and the Odyssey, psyche is compared to a “phantasm” or eidolon (Sandywell 1996 ). Like a phantasm, psyches are capable of haunting people after they have departed the body, as Patroclus haunts Achilles until Achilles will properly care for Patroclus’ body. The psyche is ostensibly useless while inhabiting a living body; it does not appear to engage in cognition, emotion, or will.
    [Show full text]