ON the UNIVERSAL LAW and HUMANITY FORMULAS by Sven R

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

ON the UNIVERSAL LAW and HUMANITY FORMULAS by Sven R ON THE UNIVERSAL LAW AND HUMANITY FORMULAS by Sven R. Nyholm A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in the University of Michigan 2012 Doctoral Committee: Professor Elizabeth S. Anderson, Co-Chair Associate Professor Sarah Buss, Co-Chair Professor Peter A. Railton Professor Donald H. Regan © Sven R. Nyholm 2012 To my grandmother ! ii! ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would first like to thank my committee – Liz Anderson, Sarah Buss, Peter Railton, and Don Regan – for their support. During my time at Michigan I have also benefited greatly from the course work I did – especially under Allan Gibbard, Stephen Darwall, and Victor Caston – so I would like to thank my other teachers at Michigan, too. My approach to the study of the history of philosophy is very strongly influenced by what I learned in some of these courses, but also greatly inspired by the Ancient Philosophy reading group whose concern with the proper and precise translation of the great historical works has served as a model for me in my engagement with Kant’s texts. In the preparation of these chapters I have been particularly helped by comments on an earlier draft by Liz Anderson, and also by the discussions about Kant’s ethics I had with Sarah Buss in Zürich in the summer of 2011. I was also particularly helped by the feedback I received by Peter Railton, Rich Thomason, and Gordon Belot when I presented parts of chapter two as a practice job talk in September of last year. Since I wrote these chapters away from Ann Arbor – in Berlin and Stupferich in Germany, Borgholm in Sweden, and Durham, NC – I haven’t had a chance to discuss their content with my fellow Michigan graduate students. But during my time at Michigan I have certainly learned a lot from Steve Campbell, Jason Konek, Nathaniel Coleman, Dave Wiens, Lina Jansson, and all the others. Finally I would also like to thank Katharina Uhde, her family, and my own family. ! iii! TABLE OF CONTENTS DEDICATION ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS iii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS vii CHAPTER I. Introduction: The Human Nature Formula 1 Why Yet Another Dissertation on How to Interpret Kant’s Ethical Theory? 1 Korsgaard on Self-Constitution in The Ethics of Plato and Kant 6 How Kant’s Constitutivism (as I understand it) Differs from Korsgaard’s 10 The Role of Kant’s Constitutivism in the Groundwork (and the Human Nature Formula) 15 The Kantian View of Categorical Imperatives of Practical Reason 24 On the Coming Chapters 28 II. Rediscovering the Universal Law Formula 32 Introduction 32 On the Standard Readings 34 Seven Objections to the Universal Law Formula 41 Two Radically Different Conclusions We Can Draw 49 Eight Steps Towards a New Understanding of the Universal Law Formula 54 Eight Steps Towards a New Reading, Continued 64 ! iv! How to Understand the Universal Law Formula (and Its Relation to the Humanity Formula) 70 Why the Seven Objections Discussed Above All Misfire 74 Why the Seven Objections Misfire, Continued 81 Looking Ahead 88 III. Kant’s Real Argument for the Humanity Formula 90 Introduction 90 Kant’s Argument for the Humanity Formula in His Own Words 94 The Reconstructions of Korsgaard, Wood, and Other Members of the American School: Preliminaries 101 The Reconstructions of Korsgaard, Wood, and Other Members of the American School, Continued 104 Three Objections to the Just-Reviewed Reconstructions of Kant’s Reasoning 115 On the Absolute Value of a Good Will and the Worthiness to Be Happy 126 How to Understand Kant’s Argument for the Humanity Formula 133 Is Our Reconstruction Uncharitable to Kant? 141 IV. Permissibility, Virtue, and the Highest Good 155 Some Distinctions 155 Scanlon and Parfit’s Objections to the Humanity Formula as a Test for Permissibility 163 Why Scanlon and Parfit’s Objections Fail 170 A Kantian Moral Saint? 176 Human Flourishing and the Highest Good 188 Human Flourishing and the Highest Good, Continued 197 Concluding Remarks 202 ! v! BIBLIOGRAPHY 207 ! vi! LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS The translations of passages from the works whose abbreviations in the footnotes are listed below are all mine. When I have translated the given passages I have consulted Mary J. Gregor and Werner S Pluhar’s English translations of Kant’s works as well as Jeanette Emt, Fredrik Linde, and Joachim Retzlaff’s Swedish translations. The German versions I have used are all from the widely available Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Wissenschaft Immanuel Kant Werkausgabe in 12 Bänden edition whose editor is Willhelm Weischedel. In what follows I cite Kant’s works by giving the abbreviations below (if and only if the works in question are among those for which I use my own translations) and the volume numbers and page numbers in the Immanuel Kant: Gesammelte Schriften (Akademie-Ausgabe), as is customary, except for in the case of the first Critique, where I give the page numbers in the original first and second editions (which is also fairly customary). Here, in the order in which the works were published, are my abbreviations along with the original German titles and, within brackets, the English titles most often used: KrV: Kritik der reinen Vernuft (Critique of Pure Reason) P: Prolegomena zu jeden künftigen Metaphysik (Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics) G: Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (Groundwork for the Metaphysics ! vii! of Morals) MN: Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft (Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science) KpV: Kritik der Praktischen Vernuft (Critique of Practical Reason) KU: Kritik der Urteilskraft (Critique of the Power of Judgment) R: Die Religion Innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernuft (Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone) TP: Über den Gemeinspruch: Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht für die Praxis (Concerning the Common Saying: That May Work in Theory, though Not in Practice) MS: Die Metaphysik der Sitten (The Metaphysics of Morals) ÜVR: Über ein Vermeintes Recht aus Menschenliebe zu Lügen (On a Supposed Right to Lie out of Benevolence) AP: Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht (Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View) ! viii! CHAPTER I Introduction: The Human Nature Formula 1. Why Yet Another Dissertation on How to Interpret Kant’s Ethical Theory? Our topic is how to understand Immanuel Kant’s “universal law” and “humanity” formulations of the categorical imperative, and the exact relation between the two. The former reads (in the formulation used in the Metaphysics of Morals) “act on the basis of a maxim that could hold as a universal law”1; the second “so act that you treat the humanity in your own person, as well as in every other person, always at the same time as an end, and never as a means only.”2 Since my choice of topic is in itself everything but groundbreaking, the first thing I need to do is to motivate this choice. I shall limit myself to offering two main motivating reasons. Before doing so I will, however, first note another limitation I have placed myself under: namely, to engage exclusively with the discussion of Kant’s ethics within Anglophone moral philosophy, and in particular fairly recent contributions to this discussion. This leads directly to the first motivation behind the discussion that follows. Firstly, although Kant’s ethical theory is very widely discussed and often severely criticized both by those who sympathize with Kant and those who don’t, Kant’s ethical !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1 (MS: 6:225) 2 (G: 4:429) ! 1! theory is not, I believe, well understood within contemporary moral philosophy. This means that many of the criticisms that are directed at Kant’s ethical system misfire and that, insofar as Kant has anything to teach us, many of Kant’s intended contributions to ethical theory go unappreciated. That Kant’s ethical theory isn’t well understood within contemporary moral philosophy isn’t surprising. It does of course most of all have to do with the fact that Kant’s texts are simply hard to understand.3 It is, to use our own main topic as our example, all but immediately obvious how subjecting ourselves to guiding principles (or “maxims”) that could hold as universal laws is equivalent, as Kant argues that is, to always treating the humanity in each person as a purpose in itself, and never as a means only. As we will see in the chapters to follow, most commentators believe that these formulas have different practical implications, and therefore find this claim to be, as one commenter puts it, “puzzling”.4 But Kant’s ethics’ not being well-understood within contemporary Anglophone moral philosophy also has to do with how many of Kant’s readers read the ethical works by Kant that they do read (which is often limited to a sub- set of these) in light of contemporary discussions of ethics within Anglophone analytical philosophy (which tend to focus exclusively on the mere permissibility of candidate !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 3 Kant’s works are also hard to translate into English. Indeed, the major translations that tend to be used are, I will argue, questionable at key points in the texts, which is part of what has led to some of the major misconceptions about how to understand Kant’s theory. 4 Though she’s initially “puzzled” by this claim – most of all since the two formulas contain very different concepts – Onora O’Neill eventually argues her way to an interpretation on which the formulas can be reconciled (O’Neill 1989). Thomas Hill and Christine Korsgaard are two prominent writers who argue that these formulas differ in their practical applications (Hill 1980); (Korsgaard, 1996). Derek Parfit argues that while the humanity formula implies that the permissibility of actions is dependent of what the agent’s attitudes are, the universal law formula can be interpreted so as to not have this implication.
Recommended publications
  • How to Get a Norm from a Speech Act Rae Langton
    How to Get a Norm from a Speech Act Rae Langton The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy lectureP 10, 2015 http://www.amherstlecture.org/ the amherst lecture in philosophyP Lecture 10, 2015 How to Get a Norm from a Speech Act Rae Langton Preferred citation Langton, Rae. “How to Get a Norm from a Speech Act.” The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy 10 (2015): 1–33. <http://www.amherstlecture.org/langton2015/>. Abstract Doing things with words can create an ought that was not there before: Jones makes a promise, a master orders a slave. With the former example, Searle ‘derived’ an ought from an is. With the latter, Lewis showed that permissibility follows a ‘rule of accommodation’. The parallel between promise and order suggests that norms, good and bad, can be got from speech acts by accommodation: what is said ‘requires and thereby creates’ what is required, given certain conditions. Authority is such a condition: of a slave master, a desert island leader, a doctor, a quack doctor, a father, or a presidential candidate who ‘normalizes’ a behaviour. Authority can be pre-established, or gained by accommodation. It can be practical, or epistemic. It can belong to the speaker, or be outsourced. These cross-cutting distinctions allow for weakened authority, but a power to enact directives remains. Hearers can assist: in a two-part process, hearers accommodate presupposed authority, which in turn accommodates a speech act, cre- ating a norm. As hearers we may need, sometimes, to stop helping. The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy (ISSN: 1559-7199) is a free on-line journal, published by the Department of Philosophy, Amherst College, Amherst, MA 01002.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Narrative, Feminist Theory and Writing Practice
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by ResearchArchive at Victoria University of Wellington ON SHIFTING GROUND: Self-narrative, feminist theory and writing practice By Anne Else A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Victoria University of Wellington 2006 To Susan Moller Okin 1946-2004 Abstract This thesis centres on a problem that stands at the heart of feminist theory: how women may come to understand themselves as speaking subjects located within historically specific, discursive social structures, to question those structures aloud, and to seek to change them. It combines self-narrative, feminist theory and writing practice to make sense of a body of published work which I produced between 1984 and 1999, with a consistent focus on some form of gendered discourse, by setting it in its personal, historical, and theoretical contexts. Although the thesis is built around published work, it is not primarily about results or outcomes, but rather about a set of active historical processes. Taking the form of a spirally structured critical autobiography spanning five and a half decades, it traces how one voice of what I have termed feminist oppositional imagining has emerged and taken its own worded shape. First, it constructs a double story of coming to writing and coming to feminism, in order to explore the formation of a writing subject and show the critical importance of the connections between subjectivity and oppositional imagining, and to highlight the need to find ways of producing knowledge which do not rely on the notion of the detached observer.
    [Show full text]
  • In This Issue of KRITIKE: an Online Journal of Philosophy
    KRITIKE VOLUME FIVE NUMBER TWO (DECEMBER 2011) i-iii Editorial In this Issue of KRITIKE: An Online Journal of Philosophy Roland Theuas DS. Pada hilology of the future! An insult thrown at Friedrich Nietzsche by his contemporary philologist, Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, whose P polemics dampened the reception of Nietzsche’s The Birth of Tragedy, is one of the reasons why philosophy should be keenly aware with the difference between the idea of doing philosophy and understanding philosophy. On the one hand, doing philosophy in the sense of elucidation and exposition falls at the border between doing philosophy and philology. On the other hand, contributing something different to a discourse is one of the ways in which philosophy is able to live on and move towards the future. On a related note, the movement of philosophy is dynamic and unpredictable, a discourse at one time may be in vogue or in fashion, only to be eventually left as archive fodder. This is not to say that what we leave in an archive is entirely useless, rather this assertion speaks more of how we should overcome the very shoulders in which we erected our own philosophical edifice. Just as Heidegger had the anxiety of overcoming Kant in Sein und Zeit, and Derrida moving beyond Heidegger’s Destruktion, we must continue to think about the future of philosophy and to maintain an invisible thread that can tie and connect other discourses and disciplines together. I am very ecstatic to present the following papers for the tenth issue of KRITIKE: An Online Journal of Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • PGR Faculty List 2021 ALL Departments 24August2021 Draft
    Faculty Lists fall 2021 Email: [email protected] for corrections. Current update: 8/24/2021 #=75 or older in 2021 (* was over 70 in 2017 list) Part-time faculty are half-time, unless otherwise noted. UNITED STATES (the top 50 will be ranked) FACULTY # Arizona Faculty: Sara Aronowitz, Thomas Christiano, Stewart Cohen, Juan Comesaña, Reza Hadisi, RiChard Healey, Laura, Howard, J. Christopher Maloney, MiChael McKenna, Bill OberdiCK, Guido PinCione, Marga Reimer, Daniel Russell, Carolina Sartorio, David SChmidtz, Houston Smit, MarK Timmons, Joseph Tolliver, Jason Turner, Steven Wall, Jonathan Weinberg. Part-time faculty: *Allen Buchanan (.25 time) Cognate faculty and philosophers in other units: Martin FriCKe, Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini, Christopher Robertson, Simone Sepe. FACULTY # Arizona State Faculty: RiChard Amesbury, Brad Armendt, Thomas BlaCKson, Cheshire Calhoun, Peter de Marneffe, Typer DesRoChes, MarCello Di Bello, Peter Kung, Joan MCGregor, Shyam Nair, Ben Phillips, Nestor Ángel Pinillos, Douglas W. Portmore, Maura Priest, Steven Reynolds. Part-time faculty: Cognate faculty and philosophers in other units: RiChard Creath, Tyler DesRoChes, ZaChary Horne, Ted Humphrey, PatriCia J. Huntingon, Manfred LaubiChler, Jane MainesChein, Martin BeCK MatuštíK, Ben A. Minteer, *Jeffrie G. Murphy, BeCKett Sterner, Jason Robert, Hava Tirosh-Samuelson, Norbert Samuelson, BeCKett Sterner. FACULTY # BerKeley Faculty: Olivia Bailey, John Campbell, Timothy ClarKe, Shamik Dasgupta, Johann FriCK, Hannah Ginsborg, Florian Grosser, Wesley H. Holliday, NiKo Kolodny, Geoffrey Lee, John MaCFarlane, Paolo ManCosu, Alva Noë, Andreja NovaKoviC, Kristin Primus, R. Jay WallaCe, Daniel Warren, Seth Yalcin, Xueyin (Snow) Zhang. Part-time Faculty: Joshua Cohen (.25 time), MiChael (M.G.F.) Martin, Veronique Munoz Darde, Kwong-Loi Shun. Cognate Faculty and Philosophers in Other Units: Asad Q.
    [Show full text]
  • How Propaganda Works How Works
    HOW PROPAGANDA WORKS HOW WORKS PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS JASON STANLEY Princeton Oxford Copyright © 2015 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press 6 Oxford Street, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TW press.princeton.edu Jacket design by Chris Ferrante Excerpts from Victor Kemperer, The Language of the Third Reich: LTI, Lingua Tertii Imperii, translated by Martin Brady © Reclam Verlag Leipzig, 1975. Used by permission of Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing PLC. All Rights Reserved ISBN 978– 0– 691– 16442– 7 Library of Congress Control Number: 2014955002 British Library Cataloging- in- Publication Data is available This book has been composed in Sabon Next LT Pro and League Gothic Printed on acid- free paper. ∞ Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 This will always remain one of the best jokes of democracy, that it gave its deadly enemies the means by which it was destroyed. — JOSEPH GOEBBELS, REICH MINISTER OF PROPAGANDA, 1933– 45 CONTENTS Preface IX Introduction: The Problem of Propaganda 1 1 Propaganda in the History of Political Thought 27 2 Propaganda Defined 39 3 Propaganda in Liberal Democracy 81 4 Language as a Mechanism of Control 125 5 Ideology 178 6 Political Ideologies 223 7 The Ideology of Elites: A Case Study 269 Conclusion 292 Acknowledgments 295 Notes 305 Bibliography 335 Index 347 PREFACE In August 2013, after almost a decade of teaching at Rutgers University and living in apartments in New York City, my wife Njeri Thande and I moved to a large house in New Haven, Connecticut, to take up positions at Yale University.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletters NEWSLETTER on FEMINISM and PHILOSOPHY
    APA Newsletters NEWSLETTER ON FEMINISM AND PHILOSOPHY Volume 11, Number 1 Fall 2011 FROM THE EDITOR, CHRISTINA M. BELLON ABOUT THE NEWSLETTER ON FEMINISM AND PHILOSOPHY SUBMISSION GUIDELINES AND INFORMATION NEWS FROM THE COMMITTEE ON THE STATUS OF WOMEN, PEGGY DESAUTELS ARTICLES MARGARET URBAN WALKER “Why So Stuck?” PEGGY DESAUTELS “Is the Climate any Warmer for Women in Philosophy?” LINDA MARTÍN ALCOFF “A Call for Climate Change” MICHELLE SAINT “Women, the Profession, and the Blogs” RAE LANGTON “Women in Philosophy: An Australian Initiative” BOOK REVIEWS Lauren Rosewarne: Cheating on the Sisterhood:Infidelity and Feminism REVIEWED BY CELINA M. BRAGAGNOLO Wendy Lynne Lee: Contemporary Feminist Theory and Activism: Six Global Issues REVIEWED BY MARGARET A. CROUCH © 2011 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN 2155-9708 Kate Gilhuly: The Feminine Matrix of Sex and Gender in Classical Athens REVIEWED BY LISA A. WILKINSON Sarah Ahmed: The Promise of Happiness REVIEWED BY AMI HARBIN Brooke A. Ackerly: Universal Human Rights in a World of Difference REVIEWED BY JANE MUMMERY Christine de Pizan: The Book of Peace REVIEWED BY SARAH TYSON CONTRIBUTORS APA NEWSLETTER ON Feminism and Philosophy Christina M. Bellon, Editor Fall 2011 Volume 11, Number 1 associations and societies outside and apart from the APA, in ROM THE DITOR hallways and department meeting rooms across the continent, F E and increasingly in the blogosphere. Finally, we are talking openly. Finally, we are letting our voices be heard, some of us more loudly and assertively than others. Finally, also, we Dear readers, this is the last editorial I will write in my capacity are asking questions—not merely of those who produced the as editor of the Newsletter.
    [Show full text]
  • Ayala Structural Explanation Norms
    A structural explanation of injustice in conversations: It’s about norms Saray Ayala-López California State University Sacramento – [email protected] Draft. Forthcoming in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. Abstract In contrast to individualistic explanations of social injustice that appeal to implicit attitudes, structural explanations are unintuitive: they appeal to entities that lack clear ontological status, and the explanatory mechanism is similarly unclear. This makes structural explanations unappealing. The present work proposes a structural explanation of one type of injustice that happens in conversations, discursive injustice. This proposal meets two goals. First, it satisfactorily accounts for the specific features of this particular kind of injustice; and second, it articulates a structural explanation that overcomes their unattractiveness. The main idea is that discursive injustice is not the result of biased interlocutors, but of problematic discursive norms. 0. Intro In the current debate on explanations of social injustice we find two important elements. First, individuals’ explicit and implicit attitudes towards those who are the target of injustice; and second, social structures and the material reality beyond individuals’ minds that constraint individuals’ judgements, decisions and actions. Depending on the explanatory weight given to each of these elements, explanations of social injustice lean towards either the individualistic or the structural side of the spectrum. Individualistic approaches proceed by identifying causally relevant mental states in individuals’ minds. Jennifer Saul (2013), for example, has argued that what 1 explains the underrepresentation of women in philosophy is, at least in part, implicit bias, that might result, amongst other things, in unfair evaluations of women philosophers’ work. Implicit attitudes have also been said to explain racial/ethnic health disparities (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • 0287.1.00.Pdf
    rough notes to erasure Before you start to read this book, take this moment to think about making a donation to punctum books, an independent non-profit press, @ https://punctumbooks.com/support/ If you’re reading the e-book, you can click on the image below to go directly to our donations site. Any amount, no matter the size, is appreciated and will help us to keep our ship of fools afloat. Contri- butions from dedicated readers will also help us to keep our commons open and to cultivate new work that can’t find a welcoming port elsewhere. Our ad- venture is not possible without your support. Vive la Open Access. Fig. 1. Hieronymus Bosch, Ship of Fools (1490–1500) rough notes to erasure: white male privilege, my senses, and the story i cannot tell. Copyright © 2020 by Dolsy Smith. This work carries a Creative Commons BY-NC-SA 4.0 International license, which means that you are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and you may also remix, transform and build upon the material, as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors (but not in a way that suggests the authors or punctum books endorses you and your work), you do not use this work for commercial gain in any form whatsoever, and that for any remixing and transformation, you distribute your rebuild under the same license. http://creativecommons.org/li- censes/by-nc-sa/4.0/ First published in 2020 by punctum books, Earth, Milky Way. https://punctumbooks.com ISBN-13: 978-1-950192-79-3 (print) ISBN-13: 978-1-950192-80-9 (ePDF) doi: 10.21983/P3.0287.1.00 lccn: 2020936034 Library of Congress Cataloging Data is available from the Library of Congress Book design: Vincent W.J.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletter on Feminism and Philosophy, Vol. 20, No. 2 (Fall 2020)
    NEWSLETTER | The American Philosophical Association Feminism and Philosophy FALL 2020 VOLUME 20 | NUMBER 2 EDITOR’S INTRODUCTION BOOK REVIEWS Lauren Freeman Andrea J. Pitts, Mariana Ortega, and José Medina, eds.: Theories of the Flesh: Latinx and ABOUT THE NEWSLETTER ON Latin American Feminisms, Transformation, and FEMINISM AND PHILOSOPHY Resistance Reviewed by Michael Monahan SUBMISSION GUIDELINES AND INFORMATION Megan Burke: When Time Warps: The Lived Experience of Gender, Race, and Sexual Violence Reviewed by Caleb Ward ARTICLES Mari Mikkola Noelle Chaddock and Beth Hinderliter, eds.: Précis to Pornography: A Philosophical Antagonizing White Feminism: Intersectionality’s Introduction Critique of Women’s Studies and the Academy Reviewed by Shay Welch Esa Díaz-Len Is Feminist Pornography Possible? Serene Khader: Decolonizing Universalism: A Transnational Feminist Ethic A. W. Eaton Thoughts on Mikkola: Pornography, Artifacts, Reviewed by Jamie Ritzo and Pictures Robin S. Dillon and Armen T. Marsoobian, eds.: Hans Maes Criticism and Compassion: The Ethics and Politics of Claudia Card Pornography and Melancholy Reviewed by Spencer Nabors Katharine Jenkins Pornography, Social Ontology, and Feminist CONTRIBUTORS Philosophy Mari Mikkola Pornography: A Philosophical Introduction: Response to Commentators VOLUME 20 | NUMBER 1 FALL 2020 © 2020 BY THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION ISSN 2155-9708 APA NEWSLETTER ON Feminism and Philosophy LAUREN FREEMAN, EDITOR VOLUME 20 | NUMBER 2 | FALL 2020 EDITOR’S INTRODUCTION SUBMISSION GUIDELINES AND Lauren Freeman INFORMATION UNIVERSITY OF LOUISVILLE 1. Purpose: The purpose of the newsletter is to publish This issue is dedicated to a critical engagement with information about the status of women in philosophy Mari Mikkola’s 2016 book, Pornography: A Philosophical and to make the resources of feminist philosophy more Introduction (Oxford University Press).
    [Show full text]
  • HANDOUT Lecture 1. Accommodating Authority
    I. ACCOMMODATING AUTHORITY Rae Langton 1. Accommodating injustice. As theorizers of idealized speech, we don’t sufficiently accommodate injustice, i.e. acknowledge it and make space for it. As speakers and hearers, we accommodate injustice rather well, i.e. adjust to it, and help it along. Authority, norms and knowledge can follow patterns of accommodation, enabling some speech acts, and silencing others, for good and ill. 2. Two pictures of speech and its defects. Brandeis on speech, its defects, and remedies for these. Authoritative speech can pose different problems. Subordinating speech acts are not just ‘falsehoods and fallacies’, but acts of ‘authoritatively saying someone is inferior’ (MacKinnon): they rank as inferior, legitimate discrimination, deprive of powers, rights, authority, e.g. Alabama slave law, Nazi propaganda. ‘Free and fearless reasoning’ can’t straightforwardly answer it. (Important factors to be set aside: slurs and epithets, in locution; disgust and hatred in perlocution.) Can more informal hate speech subordinate? Perhaps, if it can gain authority in informal ways. 4. Accommodation. A routine process of adjustment that makes speech acts count as ‘correct play’ (Austin, Lewis). ‘Illocutionary’ speech acts distinct from their content (‘locution’) and their effects (‘perlocution’). A sports analogy, and disanalogy. Naming: ‘I hereby name this ship the Queen Elizabeth’. Permissibility: master to slave, ‘You are now permitted to cross the white line’. Presupposition: ‘Even George could win.’ 5. A three-part pattern Requirement: at t, something is required for ‘correct play’ (e.g. permissibility, presupposition) Felicity Conditions: certain conditions hold (e.g. master has authority, hearer does not block) Felicitous Outcome: ‘correct play’—at t, what is required comes into being (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Lectures and Seminars, Trinity Term 2019
    WEDNESDAY 24 APRIL 2019 • SUPPLEMENT (1) TO NO 5236 • VOL 149 Gazette Supplement Lectures and Seminars, Trinity term 2019 Cyril Foster Lecture 350 Social Sciences 357 Colleges, Halls and Societies 363 Anthropology and Museum Ethnography Green Templeton Humanities 350 Saïd Business School Hertford Rothermere American Institute Education Keble Classics International Development Kellogg English Language and Literature Law Linacre History Politics and International Relations Lincoln History/Modern Languages/Voltaire Social Policy and Intervention Magdalen Foundation Socio-legal Studies Mansfield History of Art Sociology Oriel Linguistics, Philology and Phonetics St Anne’s Music Institutes, Centres and St Antony’s Oriental Studies Museums 360 St Hilda’s Philosophy St Hugh’s Ashmolean Museum Theology and Religion St Peter’s Bodleian Libraries Somerville Mathematical, Physical and China Centre University College Life Sciences 354 Hebrew and Jewish Studies Wolfson History of Science Museum Worcester Chemistry International Gender Studies Centre Blackfriars Hall Earth Sciences Islamic Studies Engineering Science St Stephen’s House Reuters Institute for the Study of Mathematical Institute Journalism Physics Latin American Centre Other Groups 366 Foundation for Law, Justice and Society Friends of the Bodleian Medical Sciences 355 Oxford Centre for Life-Writing Friends of the Pitt Rivers Museum Oxford Martin School Pathology Oxford Institute for Population Ageing Pharmacology Physiology, Anatomy and Genetics Population Health Psychiatry 349 350 University of Oxford Gazette • Supplement (1) to No 5236 • 24 April 2019 Cyril Foster Lecture American Literature Research Seminar Faculty of Classics Dr Emily Coit, Bristol Annual lectures This event has been cancelled due to 2 May: ‘Pure English: Edith Wharton’s unforeseen circumstances. American elect’ The following lectures will take place at 5pm in the Ioannou Centre for Classical and Professor Philip Gould, Brown Byzantine Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Authority of Hate Speech Rae Langton
    The Authority of Hate Speech Rae Langton (Draft: final version to appear in Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, Vol. 3) 1. Hate speech as doing things with words When we speak, we ‘do things with words’, and often we do things with words to people: advise them, marry them, warn them, and more, as J. L. Austin observed. Our topic here is hate speech, a category absent from Austin’s otherwise generous catalogues.1 But his insight that saying is doing applies to hate speech, as much as to anything else. When hate speech is minimized, or psychologized, shrunk down to expression of unpopular ideas, or injury of sensitive feelings, it is worth recalling that ‘the harm in hate speech’ involves its force as a speech act: it is in large part ‘performative’, as Jeremy Waldron, among others, has recently agreed.2 What is done with words can depend on patterns of authority. An Alabama slave law said, in 1861, that slaves are people and things: as ‘rational human beings, they are capable of committing crimes; and in reference to acts which are crimes, are regarded as persons’, but ‘because they are slaves, they are incapable of performing civil acts, and, in reference to all such, they are things, not persons’.3 The law turned people into property that could be bought and sold, like things, and sent to jail, like rational human beings. The harm in slave law depended, in part, on its authority. This illustrates Catharine MacKinnon’s observation that— Together with all its material supports, authoritatively saying someone is inferior is largely how structures of status and differential treatment are demarcated and actualized.
    [Show full text]