T He Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

T He Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles volume 19, no. 42 he Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles (henceforth: october 2019 PII) — the principle that no two numerically distinct things T are perfectly alike — features prominently in Leibniz’s meta- physics. Leibniz uses it when he discusses atoms, the vacuum, the nature of space and time, and the nature of individual substances, to name just a few of its applications. Despite its centrality to his philo- sophical system, however, it is surprisingly difficult to determine what Is Leibniz’s Principle of the modal status Leibniz ascribes to the PII. On the one hand, there are many occasions throughout his philosophical career where he says or implies that scenarios with numerically distinct indiscernibles are im- Identity of Indiscernibles possible. This suggests that he endorses a necessary version of the PII. On the other hand, there are several key passages — in particular in (but not limited to) his correspondence with Samuel Clarke — where Necessary or Contingent? Leibniz seems to say or imply that scenarios with numerically distinct indiscernibles are possible (albeit not actual). This suggests that he en- dorses a merely contingent version of the PII. Thus, Leibniz’s attitude towards the modal status of the PII appears to be inconsistent. How should we deal with this apparent inconsistency? Can it be resolved? And if so, what is Leibniz’s considered view? In short, what is the mod- al status of Leibniz’s PII? Given the unclear and seemingly contradictory textual situation, it is unsurprising that there is no consensus among commentators on what Leibniz’s view is. Some argue that he endorses the necessary ver- sion of the PII throughout his philosophical career, including the late Sebastian Bender correspondence with Clarke.1 Others are so impressed by the mixed textual evidence that they read Leibniz as having no consistent view Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin on the issue.2 Recently, however, a third view has gained in popularity, 1. This interpretation goes all the way back at least to Russell 1992 [1937], 65 (Russell also explicitly acknowledges though that there is a prima facie ten- sion in Leibniz’s texts that requires to be settled). Other proponents who con- sider Leibniz’s PII a necessary principle include Rescher 1967, 48; Broad 1975, 40−41; Frankel 1981; Jolley 2005, 86; Futch 2008, 147; and Rodriguez-Pereyra © 2019 Sebastian Bender 2014, chapter 9. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons 2. See, for example, Chernoff 1981, 137, who writes: “Any attempt to interpret PII, as it appears in the correspondence with Clarke, as a unique principle that Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License. accords with all of Leibniz’s relevant remarks is doomed to failure.” Similarly, <www.philosophersimprint.org/019042/> Cover and O’Leary-Hawthorne argue that different arguments lead Leibniz sebastian bender Is Leibniz’s PII Necessary or Contingent? according to which at least the mature Leibniz rejects the necessity of 1. Leibniz’s PII 3 the PII. It has been argued, in particular by Julia Jorati and Martin Lin, In this section, I will briefly explain what Leibniz takes the PII to say, that reading Leibniz as defending a merely contingent version of the bracketing the question of what modal status he ascribes to the prin- PII not only fits the texts better, but also makes the most philosophical ciple. A standard contemporary formulation of the PII goes as follows: sense. In this paper, I will argue against this view. Contrary to many recent (PII) F(Fx ↔ Fy) → x = y (If, for every property F, object x has F if and only if object y has F, then x is identical to y.)4 commentators, I claim that Leibniz is firmly committed to the neces- ∀ sity of the PII. In particular, I will argue that he subscribes to a mod- In other words, if x and y share all their properties, then x and y are ally robust version of the PII even in his correspondence with Clarke, identical. Leibniz is not a fan of this way of putting the PII. He typi- and that the recent attempts to refute such a reading are unsuccessful. cally avoids quantification over properties and prefers instead to state On the face of it, my interpretation of the Clarke correspondence may the principle in terms of resemblance, difference, or indiscernibility.5 come as a surprise, since Leibniz there appears to tie the PII to God’s Here are three representative passages from three different periods of wisdom, which would make the PII contingent. A detailed analysis of Leibniz’s career: the relevant passages, however, will reveal Leibniz’s deep and ongo- ing commitment to a modally strong version of the PII even in these [N]ever will be found two eggs, or two drops of milk, or very late texts. two leaves, or two animals, and in general two things so The paper is structured as follows: Section 1 briefly explains how similar that after an accurate examination, no difference 6 Leibniz understands the PII, independently of its modal status. Sec- can be noticed. (Letter to Casati in 1689, A 2.2.289) tion 2 surveys several arguments for the contingency of Leibniz’s PII and shows why they are not conclusive. Section 3 argues for the neces- [A]ll substances are of different natures, and […] there sity of Leibniz’s PII, with a special focus on the correspondence with are no two things in nature that differ in number alone. Clarke. Section 4 responds to three objections that might be raised (Letter to De Volder on 21 January 1704, G II 264/LDV against my interpretation. Section 5 concludes. 291) [T]here are not in nature two real, absolute beings, indis- cernible from each other. (LC 5.21) to different views about the modal status of the PII. They conclude that “it is not surprising that Leibniz vacillates between more and less modally com- mittal ways of speaking in connection with PII” (Cover and O’Leary-Haw- thorne 1999, 212). Anja Jauernig, who carefully analyses many of Leibniz’s 4. This formulation is taken from Forrest 2016. The converse of the PII is the arguments for the PII, refrains from making a judgement on the modal status Indiscernibility of Identicals: if x is identical to y, then, for every property F, of the PII (see Jauernig 2008). Stephen Steward, in a review of Rodriguez- object x has F if and only if object y has F. Leibniz endorses both. Pereyra’s recent book, takes a similar view and concludes “that the modal status of the PII is far from settled” (Steward 2015, 118). 5. On this point, see Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, 22−25. 3. See Della Rocca 2015; Mugnai 2016, 379; Jorati 2017; and Lin (unpublished 6. For a thorough discussion of this letter, see Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, chapter manuscript). 6. philosophers’ imprint – 2 – vol. 19, no. 42 (october 2019) sebastian bender Is Leibniz’s PII Necessary or Contingent? By stating the PII without mentioning (the sharing of) properties or should keep in mind, I will for the most part deal with Leibniz’s PII as it accidents, Leibniz remains faithful to his nominalist framework, ac- applies to the fundamental entities of his mature metaphysics, namely, cording to which “everything, apart from individual substances, is a (simple) individual substances, or monads. Whatever the mature Leib- mere name.”7 While he generally does not seem much bothered by niz takes the ontological status of eggs, leaves, and other bodies to talk of accidents,8 there are many passages where he makes clear that be, it is clear that all of their features are ultimately grounded in, or all there really is are individual substances and their modifications or constituted by, the fundamental entities of his ontology. Hence, what- affections.9 Presumably, Leibniz thinks that speaking of accidents is ever qualitative difference there may be between your breakfast egg acceptable, as long as one does not reify them and take them to be and my breakfast egg is ultimately due to whatever differences there entities over and above individual substances.10 Given that accidents are in the two distinct sets of monads that constitute or ground each do not constitute an ontological category distinct from substances for of the two eggs.14 Furthermore, it is quite plausible that the reverse is Leibniz, it makes sense for him to avoid formulations of the PII which also true and that each difference in the grounding entities leads to a presuppose that there is something (properties or accidents) which difference in the grounded entities. Therefore, if the PII as restricted to substances have in common or share. Stating what one wants to state monads turns out to be necessary (or contingent), then presumably (in this case, the PII) in terms of similarity or difference instead is of the unrestricted version of the PII, ranging over all things — including course a typical nominalist strategy. eggs, leaves, etc. — is necessary (or contingent) as well. What is the scope of Leibniz’s PII? It is clearly pretty wide. In just One should expect that the PII, if it is necessary, applies not just the three passages quoted above, Leibniz includes in it “eggs,” “leaves,” to actual substances but also to merely possible ones, i.e., mere pos- “animals,” “drops of milk,” “substances,” “real beings,” and “things.” In sibilia. This is true, if understood correctly. Leibniz’s official position is other texts, he also states that the PII ranges over (besides many other that possibilia are ideas or concepts in the divine intellect.15 While the entities) “individuals,”11 “beings,” and “monads.”12 All of this suggests PII presumably applies to such ideas as well — it would be quite odd that Leibniz’s PII has the widest possible scope and applies to any if God had two numerically distinct but indiscernible ideas of Peter in thing, and any kind of thing, whatsoever.13 While this is something we his mind — this is not the case that raises questions about the modal status of the principle.
Recommended publications
  • Mark Schroeder [email protected] 3709 Trousdale Parkway Markschroeder.Net
    ___________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ USC School of Philosophy 323.632.8757 (mobile) Mudd Hall of Philosophy Mark Schroeder [email protected] 3709 Trousdale Parkway markschroeder.net Los Angeles, CA 90089-0451 Curriculum Vitae philosophy.academy ___________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ EDUCATION Ph.D., Philosophy, Princeton University, November 2004, supervised by Gideon Rosen M.A., Philosophy, Princeton University, November 2002 B.A., magna cum laude, Philosophy, Mathematics, and Economics, Carleton College, June 2000 EMPLOYMENT University of Southern California, Professor since December 2011 previously Assistant Professor 8/06 – 4/08, Associate Professor with tenure 4/08 – 12/11 University of Maryland at College Park, Instructor 8/04 – 1/05, Assistant Professor 1/05 – 6/06 ___________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ RESEARCH INTERESTS My research has focused primarily on metaethics, practical reason, and related areas, particularly including normative ethics, philosophy of language, epistemology, philosophy of mind, metaphysics, the philosophy of action, agency, and responsibility, and the history of ethics. HONORS AND AWARDS Elected to USC chapter of Phi Kappa Phi, 2020; 2017 Phi Kappa Phi Faculty
    [Show full text]
  • To Appear in Synthese Probability and Proximity in Surprise
    Page 1 of 19 To appear in Synthese Probability and Proximity in Surprise Tomoji Shogenji1 Abstract This paper proposes an analysis of surprise formulated in terms of proximity to the truth, to replace the probabilistic account of surprise. It is common to link surprise to the low (prior) probability of the outcome. The idea seems sensible because an outcome with a low probability is unexpected, and an unexpected outcome often surprises us. However, the link between surprise and low probability is known to break down in some cases. There have been some attempts to modify the probabilistic account to deal with these cases, but they are still faced with problems. The new analysis of surprise I propose turns to accuracy (proximity to the truth) and identifies an unexpected degree of inaccuracy as reason for surprise. The shift from probability to proximity allows us to solve puzzles that strain the probabilistic account of surprise. Keywords Qualitative hypothesis ∙ Quantitative hypothesis ∙ Probabilistic hypothesis ∙ Inaccuracy ∙ Scoring rules ∙ Expected inaccuracy 1. Introduction This paper proposes an analysis of surprise formulated in terms of proximity to the truth, to replace the probabilistic account of surprise. It is common to link surprise to the low (prior) probability of the outcome.2 The idea seems sensible because an outcome with a low probability is unexpected, and an unexpected outcome often surprises us. However, the link between surprise and low probability is known to break down in some cases. There have been some attempts to modify the probabilistic account to deal with these cases, but as we shall see, they are still faced with problems.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Arguments to Think That Faith Does Not Entail Belief
    THREE ARGUMENTS TO THINK THAT FAITH DOES NOT ENTAIL BELIEF BY DANIEL HOWARD-SNYDER Abstract: On doxastic theories of propositional faith, necessarily, S has faith that p only if S believes that p. On nondoxastic theories of propositional faith, it’sfalse that, necessarily, S has faith that p only if S believes that p. In this article, I defend three arguments for nondoxastic theories of faith and I respond to published crit- icisms of them. 1. Introduction Pistology is on the rise. The study of the nature and value of faith was once the domain of biblical scholars, theologians, and the occasional philosopher of religion. Not anymore. Epistemologists, moral psychologists, and classicists, along with many philosophers of religion, have gotten into the act, in no small part because faith has become more readily seen as a widespread human phenomenon, rather than just a religious one, something at the center of human flourishing, not just religious flourishing – aviewthe ancient Greeks and Romans held, a view in recovery today (Morgan, 2015; Preston-Roedder, 2018; Tsai, 2017). This renewed scholarly interest in faith thought of as a psychological atti- tude, state, orientation, or trait that can have secular contents or objects, not just religious ones, parallels recent social trends. One example: in his farewell speech, Barack Obama uses the faith lexicon seven times, but only once with religious content. He speaks of ‘faith in reason and enterprise, and the pri- macy of right over might,’ of ‘faith in America and in Americans,’ of ‘faith … in the power of ordinary Americans to bring about change,’ and the like.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • August 9, 2001 Word Count: 7015 Words Abstract There Is A
    PRESENTISM AND QUANTUM GRAVITY1 August 9, 2001 word count: 7015 words Abstract There is a philosophical tradition of arguing against presentism, the thesis that only presently existing things exist, on the basis of its incompatibility with fundamental physics. I grant that presentism is incompatible with special and general relativity, but argue that presentism is not incompatible with quantum gravity, because there are some theories of quantum gravity that utilize a fixed foliation of spacetime. I reply to various objections to this defense of presentism, and point out a flaw in Gödel’s modal argument for the ideality of time. This paper provides an interesting case study of the interplay between physics and philosophy. 1I have given talks based on previous versions of this paper at Princeton University, the American University of Beirut, California Polytechnic State University, and the University of Kentucky. I thank the audiences at these presentations for helpful discussion. I also thank Gordon Belot, Mauro Dorato, Brian Kierland, Steven Savitt, Bas van Fraassen, Steve Weinstein, and an anonymous referee for helpful comments. 1 1. Introduction. I am a presentist: I believe that only presently existing things exist.2 Contrast presentism with eternalism: the eternalist believes that past, present, and future things all exist. Assuming that there are three spatial dimensions, the eternalist believes that the universe is four- dimensional, and while there are different events in different regions of this so-called “block universe”, the universe as a whole does not change. The presentist, in contrast, believes that the universe is three-dimensional. I am also a Heraclitean: I believe that change is a fundamental aspect of reality.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz and the Foundations of Physics: the Later Years
    Leibniz and the Foundations of Physics: The Later Years The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation McDonough, Jeffrey K. 2016. Leibniz and the Foundations of Physics: The Later Years. Philosophical Review 125, no. 1: 1–34. doi:10.1215/00318108-3321711. Published Version doi:10.1215/00318108-3321711 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:30780190 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Open Access Policy Articles, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#OAP Leibniz and the Foundations of Physics: The Later Years Jeffrey K. McDonough 0. Introduction In the opening paragraphs of his now classic paper “Leibniz and the Foundations of Physics: The Middle Years,” Daniel Garber suggests that Leibniz must seem something of a paradox to contemporary readers (1985, 27). On the one hand, Leibniz is commonly held to have advanced a broadly idealist metaphysics according to which the world is ultimately grounded in mind-like monads whose properties are exhausted by their perceptions and appetites. On such a picture, physical bodies would seem to be nothing more than the perceptions or thoughts (or contents thereof) enjoyed by immaterial substances.1 On the other hand, it is generally recognized (if perhaps less clearly) that Leibniz was also a prominent physicist in his own day and that he saw his work in physics as supporting, and being supported by, his metaphysics.2 But how, in light of his idealism, could that be? How could Leibniz think that his pioneering work in physics might lend support to his idealist metaphysics, and conversely that his Earlier versions of this essay were presented to audiences at the Westfälische Wilhelms-Universität Münster, Yale University, Brown University, and Dartmouth College.
    [Show full text]
  • An Aristotelian Interpretation of Practical Wisdom: the Case of Retirees
    University of Wollongong Research Online Faculty of Business - Papers Faculty of Business January 2019 An Aristotelian interpretation of practical wisdom: the case of retirees Peter R. Massingham University of Wollongong, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ro.uow.edu.au/buspapers Recommended Citation Massingham, Peter R., "An Aristotelian interpretation of practical wisdom: the case of retirees" (2019). Faculty of Business - Papers. 1640. https://ro.uow.edu.au/buspapers/1640 Research Online is the open access institutional repository for the University of Wollongong. For further information contact the UOW Library: [email protected] An Aristotelian interpretation of practical wisdom: the case of retirees Abstract This paper aims to improve understanding of the concept of practical wisdom. The theoretical lens used is Aristotle's practical rationality or 'phronesis'. Researchers argue that practical wisdom should be used as an organising framework for professional knowledge. Aristotle believed that practical wisdom as the highest intellectual virtue. Phronesis is the complicated interactions between general (theory) and practical (judgement). The contribution of this paper is to discuss the properties of practical wisdom and how they interact based on an interpretation of retirees' knowledge. The paper summarises in-depth face- to-face interviews with nine retirees, i.e., nine separate case studies. A structured interview guideline based on a conceptual framework derived from literature was used to examine the nature of retirees' practical wisdom. People with wisdom make better decisions. Whereas episteme's technical knowledge may address complicated tasks, techne's wisdom enables people to resolve truly complex tasks. Techne provides personal judgement which enables the professional to judge their actions from an external and internal perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming in Erkenntnis INTERNALISM AND
    Page 1 Forthcoming in Erkenntnis INTERNALISM AND EXTERNALISM IN MELIORATIVE EPISTEMOLOGY Tomoji Shogenji ABSTRACT This paper addresses the meta-epistemological dispute over the basis of epistemic evaluation from the standpoint of meliorative epistemology. Meliorative epistemology aims at guiding our epistemic practice to better results, and it comprises two levels of epistemic evaluation. At the social level (meliorative social epistemology) appropriate experts conduct evaluation for the community, so that epistemic evaluation is externalist since each epistemic subject in the community need not have access to the basis of the experts’ evaluation. While at the personal level (meliorative personal epistemology) epistemic evaluation is internalist since each member of the community must evaluate the reliability of the (apparent) experts from the first-person perspective. I argue that evaluation at the social level should be the primary focus of meliorative epistemology since meliorative personal epistemology does not provide informative epistemic norms. It is then pointed out that epistemic evaluation at the social level can be considered internalist in the extended sense (social internalism) in that every component of the evaluation needs to be recognized by some members of the community at some points. As a result, some familiar problems of internalist epistemology, such as regress and circularity of epistemic support, carry over to meliorative social epistemology. 1. INTRODUCTION One of the most heavily contested issues in recent epistemology is the meta- epistemological dispute over the proper basis of epistemic evaluation. The internalist camp favors the restriction that the basis of epistemic evaluation must be conditions internal to the epistemic subject, while the externalist camp rejects this restriction.
    [Show full text]
  • August 11, 2014 Prepared for the Associate Editors, 2014 Hypatia
    August 11, 2014 ANNUAL REPORT FOR 2013 Prepared for the Associate Editors, 2014 Hypatia Editor Sally J. Scholz, Villanova University Book Review Editor Shelley Wilcox, San Francisco State University OVERVIEW (2013) Hypatia published Volume 28 in 2013. Volume 28 included a six-essay cluster on Embodiment (28.1), a special issue on Crossing Borders guest edited by Sally Scholz (28.2), a found cluster of six papers on Luce Irigaray edited by Linda Alcoff (28.3), and the 2013 Diversity Prize Essay “Basements and Intersections” by Anna Carastathis (28.4). Fifty-two full-length articles were published in the volume year; thirty-one were open issue articles. The year included a number of notable events and transitions. Hypatia issued its first ever moratorium on submissions from January 15 - July 15, 2013. Once lifted, the Editorial Office continued to receive sporadic queries about the moratorium for an additional 6-8 months. Nevertheless, submissions began to come in again quite regularly by August and the year ended only slightly lower than half of the number of submissions the previous year. All signs are positive in 2014 for not only hitting but perhaps also surpassing previous yearly submission numbers. Hypatia’s Editorial Offices moved to Villanova University on July 1, 2013. The transition began in November 2012 when the new team was selected and participated in the renegotiation of the contract with Wiley-Blackwell. Alison Wylie and her team spent many hours preparing for a smooth transition. Notably, they ensured that many of the forthcoming issues were complete or near complete for the coming year.
    [Show full text]
  • Cavellian Meditations1
    CONVERSATIONS 2! Cavellian Meditations1 ROBERT SINNERBRINK 1. Film and Philosophy Stanley Cavell’s coming to philosophy was inspired, as he recounts, by the contingent encounter between philosophical and non-philosophical texts. He singles out Witt- genstein’s Philosophical Investigations, for example, as one that “staked its teaching on showing that we do not know, or make ourselves forget, what reading is.”2 He also names three films — Bergman’s Sommarnattens leende (Smiles of a Summer Night, 1955), Resnais and Duras’ Hiroshima Mon Amour (1959), and Antonioni’s L’Avventura (1960) — that suggested to him what philosophy might become should it re-orient itself towards different modes of thought.3 These three films, for Cavell, not only altered American perceptions of what “foreign” (indeed “Continental”) films could do, they also opened up the question of what constitutes “a medium of thought.” Indeed, they were films that served “to alter the iconography of intellectual conversation,”4 not least the possibility that film might be a partner to philosophy, or that some kind of marriage between the two might be possible. I take Cavell’s anecdote to be significant for understanding the possibilities of our philosophical engagement with film. It raises the question of how we should ap- proach film-philosophy, understood as a distinctive way of writing philosophically about film that Cavell, more than most, has made intelligible. By “film-philosophy” I mean aesthetically-receptive writing that develops philosophical insights from our experience of film rather than by applying to film the traditional problems or techni- !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1. A longer, modified version of this paper will appear in the journal Film-Philosophy, “The Stanley Cavell Issue” (2014).
    [Show full text]
  • Space and Time in Leibniz's Early Metaphysics
    Space and Time in Leibniz’s Early Metaphysics1 Timothy Crockett, Marquette University Abstract In this paper I challenge the common view that early in his career (1679-1695) Leibniz held that space and time are well-founded phenomena, entities on an ontological par with bodies and their properties. I argue that the evidence Leibniz ever held that space and time are well-founded phenomena is extremely weak and that there is a great deal of evidence for thinking that in the 1680s he held a position much like the one scholars rightly attribute to him in his mature period, namely, that space and time are merely orders of existence and as such are purely abstract and occupy an ontological realm distinct from that of well-founded phenomena. In the course of arguing for this interpretation, I offer an account of the nature of Leibnizian phenomena which allows Leibniz to hold the view that space and time are phenomena, while at the same time thinking of them as abstract, ideal orders of existence. I. Introduction n his mature philosophical writings, Leibniz is careful to distinguish two ontological realms: the realm of well-founded phenomena such as bodies and theirI properties, and the realm of purely ideal things such as space and time. Ideal things, he insists, are abstract, imaginary, indeterminate and continuous, whereas well-founded phenomena are real, completely determinate, and discrete. In his earlier metaphysical writings, however, he sometimes says that space and time are phenomena akin to rainbows and parhelia, and he suggests that in this respect they are in the same ontic category as extension and motion.
    [Show full text]
  • Barnett-Philosophy Without Belief
    PHILOSOPHY WITHOUT BELIEF ABSTRACT: Should we believe our controversial philosophical views? Recently, several authors have argued from broadly Conciliationist premises that we should not. If they are right, we philosophers face a dilemma: If we believe our views, we are irrational. If we do not, we are not sincere in holding them. This paper offers a way out, proposing an attitude we can rationally take toward our views that can support sincerity of the appropriate sort. We should arrive at our views via a certain sort of “insulated” reasoning – that is, reasoning that involves setting aside certain higher- order worries, such as those provided by disagreement – when we investigate philosophical questions. I. INTRODUCTION In general, we philosophers think that philosophical questions have right answers. We think that there are facts of the matter about whether there are ordinary objects, or about whether it can ever be rational to have inconsistent beliefs, or about whether a person would survive if each of her brain cells were replaced with an artificial functional duplicate. We also think of philosophy, traditionally, as a truth-seeking enterprise. Our research and discussion is not just for fun. We expect, or at least hope, that all of this work will eventually deliver at least some of the answers that we take philosophical questions to have. One very pessimistic outlook is that this expectation of truth-deliverance is simply unreasonable. On this picture, we should expect that virtually all important philosophical questions will remain unsettled, forever. Whether such skepticism is warranted is a matter of some controversy.1 But in this paper, I set this radical skepticism to the side.
    [Show full text]