Of the Causelessnessof

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Of the Causelessnessof The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies Jburnal ofindiaH andBudd]leist Stttdies Vbl. 58, No.3, March 2010 (125) Dharmottara's Interpretation of the Causelessness of Destruction SAKAi Masamichi O. Introduction It goes without saying that the new proof of momentariness systematized by Dharrnak- irtiO (ca.6oo-66o) dctermines the direction ofthe later development ofthe proofofmomcn- tariness.2) In this prooC the existent (sat) is defined as being causally efficacious, and thereby the lack of causal efficacy ofthe non-momentary (aksaptku) is deduced, fbr the way a thing produces an effect i's either gradual or simultaneous and the non-momentary can produce its effect neither gradually nor simultameously. Thus, it is proven by negating the existence ofthe non-momentary that all that is existent is momentary. Meanwhile, ow- ing to the appearance of the new prooC the traditional proof of mornentariness fbunded upen the causelessness of destruction (vinljSas.va-ahetutva) was moved outside the main- stream proofs for momentariness. In this traditional proof whose object of application is restricted to the produced (k.rtako) and which always requires the imperrnanence (anityatva) ofthe produced as its presupposition, it is only possible to infer momcntariness ofthe pro- duced from its impermanence by virtue of the causelessness of destruction. Therefore, in the traditional proog the ascertainment of the pervasion (io,liptinis'eaya) of the property of being produced (k.rtakatva) by the property ofbeing impermanent (anioTatva) is not the top- ic in the first place. On the contrary, in the new proof not only the momentariness itselg but also the pervasion of the property of being existent (sattva) by the preperty of being impermanent or being momentary (ksanikzxtva) is established. Therefbre, from the logical point ofview, it may be no exaggeratien to say that the appearance ofthe ncw proofmakes the existence of the traditional proof cempletcly superfTuous. In spite of this fact, however, in the actual history of Indian Buddhism, the traditional proof never disappeared. One pos- sible reason fbr this can be found in the activities of Dharmakirti's successors. For exam- ple, Dharrnottara (ca.740-8oo) is engaged in the traditional proof in a unique way. That is, 1241 NII-Electronic Library Service The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies (126) Dharmottara's Intcrpretation ofthe Causelessness ofDestructien (M, SAK,AL) he places the causelessness of destruction, which is the very backbone of the traditional prooC in the framework of the new proof and thereby gives jt a ncw function. Thc aim of this paper is to introduce one interpretation, unique to Dharmottara, ofthe causelessness of dcstruction by focusing on the argument that appears in an indepcndent werk ofhis, the Kl,gatiabhaftgasiddhi (henceforth: KBhS) with the great help of Mukt5kalaSa's (ca.1000?) commentary the K,ya4abhafigasidcthivivatraea KBhSV) (henceforth: . 1. 0bjection of the opponent In KBhS, Dharmottara's uniquc interpretation appears in the course of the discussion where he confironts a very distinctive objection of (all) opponent(s) . The fbllewing is the outlinc ofthe opponent's assertion: (1) What the opponent asserts is that the legical reason "being (hetu) existent (satn7a)" characterized as having the nature ofbeing eausally effica- cious, from which the momentariness is inferred, is inconclusive (anaikdnttha) because the exclusion ofthis logical reason from the dissimilar (vipaksa) is doubtfu1. (2) Namely, cven the non-rnomeritary can produce an effect gradnally by depending on a gradually cooperat- ing cause (sakakarin>. Therefore, the non-momentary is eausally efficacious and hcnce can be considered existent. (3) Jn order to illustrate this theory by an examplc (d.rsgdinta) of such a coopcrating cause, the opponent points to a hammer as a cause ofdestruction (i,in`-s'- ahetu). According to the opponent, there is a certain similarity between the causcs of de- struction and the cooperating causes that the non-momentary requires when it produces its "to cffbct, that is, do nothing (akim. citkaffa) to a material cause (toptzddina)." The opponcnt thinks according to the fbllowing sehema: Anon-momentary thing as material cause + a cooperating cause => produce an efTect In this casc, however, a cooperating cause does not de anything to a material cause, namely, it nei- ther gives supcriority in quality (atisF(u?a) to a material eause nor does it refine (saeis-V7k.r) a ma- terial causc so that it produces an efiioct. A pot as matcrial cause + a hammer : > di sappear In this casc, bowever, a hammer does not do anything to a pet, namely, it neither gives superiority in qu ality to a material cause nor does it refinc a pot so that it disappears. (4) MQreover, according to the opponent, one must not say that a hammer is not a cause of destruction of a pot because it does not do anything to a pot, because destruction of a pot fbllows the presence and absence ofa hammcr. (5) In order to exernplify this theory, the opponent gives a further example, that is, tlic causal relation between seed and sprout. The - - 1242 NII-Electronic Library Service The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies Dhamiottara's Interprctatien ofthe Causelessness ofDestmction (M, SAK,4i) (l27) opponent thinks as fbllows: Although a seed does not refine a sprout so that it arises, a sprout is suhjcct to the existence and non-existence ofa seed. Therefbre, a seed can be called the cause ofasprout, in the same way that it can bc sajd: Althoughahaminer does not refine a pot so that it disappears, destruction ofa pot is subject to the existence and non-existence of a hammer. Therefbre, a hamnier is a causc of destruction.3) Thus, it is proven that just ]ike the fact that a pot disappears in dependence on a hammer, evcn the non-momentary produces its cffect dependent on a cooperating cause. Therefore, the logi- "being cal reason existent" is a pseudo-reason that is inconclusive, fbr the exclusion from the dissimilar is doul)tfu1. That is the assertion of the opponcnt. 2. New function of the causelessness of destruction Answcring this objection in the KBhS, Dharmottara rebuts this attack of the opponent "being eoncerning the logical reason cxistent" by rejecting the cause of destruction as an example of a cooperating cause. Muktakalaga commcnts upon this very negation of the cause of destruction by Dharmottara as fo11ows: In order to prove the [ogical reason ["bcing existcnt"] conclusive, [Dharmottara,] aiming to refute the cause ofdestruction as thc cxample brought up by the opponent, repeats [thc above-mentioned objection] with vvrords "as opponent's the has been said." ... Just as seil in case of the seed ofrice, the pot caznot depend on a thing as a cause ef destruction Thcrefore, apot is unestablished as the example of [the theory] that a thing as a cooperating cause is, though it does not do anything to a material cause, llccded [by it]. [-[ence, that which is explained by an example ("da-rsganta) is unestablished. Ihereforc, the statement concerning thc inconc]usiveness [of the logicul Tcason of "being existenV'] that cven the non-momentary can be an agent [that preduces an effect] gradually is pulled up ("uddh.rta)4) by its roots ('samtilam), and that is the content ef this treatise (Le., KBhS) in totality.5) This means that, when Dhar nottara negates the cause ofdestruction as an example ofa co- operating cause, his rejecting the cause of destmction is motivated by the special aim of "being proving that the logical reason existen" is conclusive <aiktintika). In ether words, when Dharmottara negates the cause of destmction as an example and thereby proves it to be unestablished, then the theory explained by this example, that even the non-momentary can produce its efft:ct gradually by depending on a gradually cooperating cause, is also p. roven to be wiestablished, since the cxample is unestablished (d.rs. tantdsiddha). Accord- `Cbeing ingly, the critiquc by the opponent that the logical reason existent" is inconclusive -1243- NII-Electronic Library Service The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies (128) Dharmottara's Interpretatien ofthe Causelessness ofDestruction (M. SAKAi) is invalidated. Thus, this logical reason tt}rns out to be conclusive. Moreover, Mulct5kalaSa makes a conclusive remark of Dharinottara's argument to re- ject the cause of destruction : "therefore" With the words and se on, [Dharmettara] summarizes the purpose to which the above- mentioned [argumentation to reject the cause ofdestruction] centributes. This kind ofrejection of the cause ofdestruction is [taught] by the tbrmer teachers ("ptiJvactiryaih. ), [and it] is taughL by another person (*parerp,a, i.e., Dharrnaklrti) as thc prinuiple of the proof of momentarincss as `tSincc fo11ows ("iti): thcrc is no causc uf dcstruction, destructioll is cenncctcd with [things] en 'tu) of nature auther ofthis the basis [their] (==PV 1.193cd)."However (ni, , forthe trcatisc(i.c., Dharmottara), thc strcngth [, of this kind ofrejcction of the cause of destruction] should be "bcing understood through the very iogical rcason existent,T' Land this kind ofrejection of the cause of destmction] is brought forward [by him], in ordcr to clear away its fault [i.e. the fault that this 6) logical reason should be inconclusive] . r!The Hcrc, M. uktEkalaga is pointing out the fo11owing three important facts: (1) notion of the causelessness of destruction is ascribed to the fbrmcr tcachcrs. (2) This traditional no- tion is formulated by Dharmakirti as the principle ofthe proof ofmomentariness in his PV 1.193cd. (3) For Dharmottara, however, its value and strength should be understood "being through the very logical reason existent." What is striking in this commcntary of "an- MuktakalaSa is that he ealls Dharmakirti not a teacher (acdrva) and so on, but merely other person (gzhan,fpara)." 3. Conclusion observed above, causelessness of dcstruction has the special As fbrDharmottara the "being role of eradicating the fault that the logical reason existent" is inconclusive.
Recommended publications
  • Studies in Buddhist Hetuvidyā (Epistemology and Logic ) in Europe and Russia
    Nataliya Kanaeva STUDIES IN BUDDHIST HETUVIDYĀ (EPISTEMOLOGY AND LOGIC ) IN EUROPE AND RUSSIA Working Paper WP20/2015/01 Series WP20 Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studies Moscow 2015 УДК 24 ББК 86.36 K19 Editor of the series WP20 «Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studies» Vitaly Kurennoy Kanaeva, Nataliya. K19 Studies in Buddhist Hetuvidyā (Epistemology and Logic ) in Europe and Russia [Text] : Working paper WP20/2015/01 / N. Kanaeva ; National Research University Higher School of Economics. – Moscow : Higher School of Economics Publ. House, 2015. – (Series WP20 “Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studiesˮ) – 52 p. – 20 copies. This publication presents an overview of the situation in studies of Buddhist epistemology and logic in Western Europe and in Russia. Those studies are the young direction of Buddhology, and they started only at the beginning of the XX century. There are considered the main schools, their representatives, the directions of their researches and achievements in the review. The activity of Russian scientists in this field was not looked through ever before. УДК 24 ББК 86.36 This study (research grant № 14-01-0006) was supported by The National Research University Higher School of Economics (Moscow). Academic Fund Program in 2014–2015. Kanaeva Nataliya – National Research University Higher School of Economics (Moscow). Department of Humanities. School of Philosophy. Assistant professor; [email protected]. Канаева, Н. А. Исследования буддийской хетувидьи (эпистемологии и логики) в Европе и России (обзор) [Текст] : препринт WP20/2015/01 / Н. А. Канаева ; Нац. исслед. ун-т «Высшая школа экономи- ки». – М.: Изд. дом Высшей школы экономики, 2015. – (Серия WP20 «Философия и исследо- вания культуры»).
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Buddhist Philosophy
    A HISTORY OF B U D D H IS T P H ILO S O P H Y Continuities and Discontinuities * DAVID J. KALUPAHANA A HISTORY OF BUDDHIST PHILOSOPHY Continuities and Discontinuities David J. Kalupahana MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLISHERS PRIVATE LIMITED • DELHI Reprint: Delhi, 2006 First Indian Edition: Delhi, 1994 © 1992 University of Hawaii Press First Published by the University of Hawaii Press, 1992 ISBN: 81-208-1191-7 MOTILAL BANARSIDASS 41 U A Bungalow Road, Jawahar Nagar, Delhi 110 007 8 Mahalaxmi Chamber, 22 Bhulabhai Desai Road, Mumbai 400 026 236, 9th Main III Block, Jayanagar, Bangalore 560 011 203 Royapettah High Road, Mylapore, Chennai 600 004 Sanas Plaza, 1302 Baji Rao Road, Pune 411 002 8 Camac Street, Kolkata 700 017 Ashok Rajpath, Patna 800 004 Chowk, Varanasi 221 001 For sale in India only Printed in India BY JAINENDRA PRAKASH JAIN AT SHR1JAINENDRA PRESS, A-45 NARAINA, PHASER, NEW DELHI 110 028 AND PUBLISHED BYNARENDRA PRAKASH JAIN FOR MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLISHERS PRIVATE LIMITED, BUNGALOW ROAD, DELHI -110 007 This work, completed three days before an accident that left our youngest son, Milinda, paralyzed, is dedicated to our friends and well-wishers, at home and abroad, especially my colleagues Eliot Deutsch and Larry Laudan, whose gracious support lessened the trauma for both Milinda and the family. CONTENTS Introduction ix Abbreviations xv Part One: Early Buddhism I Indian Philosophy and the Search for Ultimate Objectivity 3 II Life of the Buddha 22 III Knowledge and Understanding 30 IV Experience and Theory (Paficcasamuppana and Pa(iccasamuppclda)
    [Show full text]
  • Positing Subtle Impermanence
    20 ??7?? Positing Subtle Impermanence In general “impermanence” is posited on the basis of whether some- thing undergoes change, and conditioned phenomena are subject to change owing to their causes and conditions.347 So if something has causes and conditions, it is subject to change, and if it does not have causes and conditions, it is not subject to change. [384] The fact of such conditioned phenomena being subject to change is primarily a function of the pro- ductive causes that produce them. As such, all conditioned phenomena continuously undergo change without remaining static for even a single moment. For example, owing to the change of a tree’s leaves, they fall to the ground with the arrival of cold in winter. It is not that they transform spontaneously, but rather they transform each day and week until in the end they fall to the ground. Those leaves that transform over many days do so naturally through merely being established. Therefore they transform moment by moment, and even though the eye does not see it, in reality they continuously transform. If subtle change did not exist moment by moment, then coarse transformation also could not arise. With respect to how the four characteristics of conditioned phenom- ena are understood, the Vaibhāṣikas, for example, assert that when the three characteristics of conditioned phenomena—arising, enduring, and disintegrating—illustrate the conditioned nature of something, such as the form aggregate, they do not do so on the basis of something arising and so on. They do so by way of demonstrating that the given phenomenon possesses characteristics such as arising that are distinct from it.
    [Show full text]
  • Studies in Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda Idealism I: the Interpretation of Vasubandhu’S Viṃśikā
    ASIA 2014; 68(3): 709 – 756 Birgit Kellner and John Taber Studies in Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda idealism I: The interpretation of Vasubandhu’s Viṃśikā Abstract: In recent scholarship there has been a persistent tendency, especially among North-American scholars, to deny that Indian Yogācāra philosophy is a form of idealism. The discussion has naturally focused on the interpretation of Vasubandhu’s Viṃśikā, a foundational text of the school, as well as one of the most accessible, which other researchers have taken to be denying the existence of a material world external to consciousness. In this article, after noting some of the points in favor of a non-idealist read- ing of the Viṃśikā, we shall offer a new reading that supports the old “standard”, but still widespread, interpretation that it indeed intends to deny the existence of physical objects outside of consciousness. We suggest that Vasubandhu develops in the Viṃśikā an extended argumentum ad ignorantiam where the absence of external objects is derived from the absence of evidence for their existence. This reading is the result of examining argumentation strategy rather than investigat- ing the logical structure of individual proofs in isolation, and it takes cues from Vasubandhu’s strategy for refuting the existence of a self in Abhidharma- kośabhāṣya IX. In addition, our reading looks at the entire Viṃśikā, rather than isolating a purported argumentative “core” (vv. 11–15), and draws attention to the relevance of some of its subtleties. Finally, we also suggest that Vasubandhu might have opted for a less direct argumentation strategy to prove the non- existence of the external world because of specific soteriological aspects of the doctrine of vijñaptimātratā.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Philosophy of Logics and Epistemology in Theravada Perspective
    © 2018 JETIR October 2018, Volume 5, Issue 10 www.jetir.org (ISSN-2349-5162) Understanding Philosophy of Logics and Epistemology in Theravada Perspective Prof. L. UdayaKumar* Vo Xuan Tam* P.Sreekant* P.Kesalu* 1. Introduction In Indian tradition of epistemology, the analysis of knowledge has been the main feature of many famous systems of thought like Nyaya, Vaisesika, Samkhya, Yoga. Purva-Mimamsa, Jain, Buddhism and Vedanta. Different kinds of means of knowledge (pramanas) which have been discussed by these traditions are: (i) direct knowledge or perception (pratyaksa), (ii) inference (anumana),(iii) knowledge by similarity (upamana), (iv) verbal testimony (sahda), including scriptural testimony (sastra or agama), (v) presumption (arthapatti), (vi) implication (sambhava), (vii) non-existence (abhava), and (viii) tradition (aitihya). The number of these means of knowledge accepted by each tradition, however, is different. The signs of epistemology are traceable as early as some of the hymns of the Rgveda. Many of philosophical schools then introduced and develop own analysis of epistemology. Buddhist tradition of logic and epistemology started with Dinnaga approximately one thousand years after the mahaparinirvana of the Sakyamuni Buddha. Though the topics of this tradition were traced back to the earliest teachings of the Buddha in Nikaya literature and some philosophical works of many famous Buddhist thinkers like Nagarjuna, Asanga, Vasubandhu, it was Dinnaga who officially founded this logico- epistemological system. We must recognize that the contribution of Buddhism to profound system of logic and epistemology of Indian philosophy began with Dinnaga. Dinnaga was the fist Buddhist thinker who set up and systematized the Buddhist theory of knowledge which has been definitely the foundation of later Buddhist development of epistemology carried our by Dharmakirti, Dharmottara, Santaraksita, Kamalasila.
    [Show full text]
  • The Yogācāra Philosophy of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti Georges Dreyfus University of Virginia & Christian Lindtner University of Copenhagen
    27 The Yogācāra Philosophy of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti Georges Dreyfus University of Virginia & Christian Lindtner University of Copenhagen Introduction We would like in this article to examine one of the most difficult points in Dharmakīrti’s thought, his presentation of the result of valid cognition (pramāṇa-phala, tshad ma’i ’bras bu). This part of Dharmakīrti’s work has been mostly ignored by modern scholars. The source of this neglect is not difficult to understand, having to do both with the difficulty of the relevant passages1 and the bizarre feature of the position that Dignāga and Dharmakīrti adopt. We are convinced, however, that these passages are quite important for understanding Dignāga’s Pramāṇa-Samuccaya (PS) and Dharmakīrti’s two main works, the Pramāṇa-Vārttika (PV) and the Pramāṇa-Viniścaya (PVin), as products of a unified intention. Up to this date, Dharmakīrti has often been understood in a piecemeal fashion. We think that it is time to attempt to understand not only his interesting views on epistemology, logic, and philosophy of language, but also to take a look at Dharmakīrti as an author of texts expressing a unified thought. From this perpective, some of the most relevant passages in the corpus of Dharmakīrti’s works concern the result of valid cognition. It is clear that we do not intend within such a short space to give a complete explanation of Dharmakīrti’s difficult thought on the subject. Hattori and Vetter have already done good preliminary work concerning Dignāga and Dharmakīrti’s treatment of this subject,2 but we shall nevertheless have to take some of their presuppositions and results up for revision.
    [Show full text]
  • Reverberations of Dharmakīrti's Philosophy
    The proceedings volume of the Fifth International Dharmakirti Conference (Heidelberg, August 2014) is concerned with the logico-epistemological school of Buddhism, a long- Birgit Kellner, Patrick McAllister, lasting tradition that pursued the analysis of knowledge, inference and proof within a Horst Lasic, Sara McClintock (eds.) Buddhist soteriological framework based on the works of the Indian epistemologist and logician Dharmakirti (6th–7th c. CE). Having been shaped in the environment of medieval India, with its multiple mutually interacting and partly competing religio-philosophical schools, the methods and approaches of Buddhist logic and epistemology had lasting impact on the intellectual history of Tibetan Buddhism and were also received in China and Japan. The 30 papers in this volume offer a snapshot of an international research landscape with centers in Vienna and Japan. They address historical and philological problems raised by important recent manuscript discoveries, pursue specific research questions in the history of philosophy, and undertake philosophical reconstructions and critical examinations relating to individual theories and arguments. By focusing on currents in Asia that developed and Reverberations applied rigorous philosophical methods, the volume aims to contribute to the formation of a better-founded global historical awareness in the field of philosophy. of Dharmakīrti‘s Birgit Kellner is the director of the Institute for the Cultural and Intellectual History of Asia at the Austrian Academy of Sciences. Patrick
    [Show full text]
  • Dharmakīrti's Apoha-Theory of Concept Formation
    Dharmakīrti’s Apoha-theory of Concept Formation: Some Key Features (Forthcoming from Columbia U. Press in a volume edited by M. Siderits and T. Tillemans) John D. Dunne Emory University The apoha-theory contains a number of occasionally technical and even counter-intuitive elements, and the main purpose of this chapter is to present its most fundamental features in a straightforward fashion. At the outset it is critical to note that, while certainly unified in its overall scope, the apoha-theory undergoes historical development that led to divergent interpretations among its formulators, and any single, unified account of the theory would be problematic. Hence, this chapter will focus on a pivotal historical moment in the theory’s development, namely, its articulation by the Buddhist philosopher Dharmakīrti (fl. 625), especially as interpreted by his immediate commentators, Devendrabuddhi (fl. 675) and Śākyabuddhi (fl. 700). To contextualize this particular layer of interpretation, I will begin with a brief historical overview and then present some contextual material under two headings: Dharmakīrti’s causal model of cognition along with the minimalism about concepts that such a model encourages; and the basics of his ontology. With these matters in place, I will then examine the fundamental points of Dharmakīrti’s apoha-theory. 1 Historical Overview The apoha-theory finds its first explicit articulation in the work of Dignāga (fl. 425), the first Buddhist philosopher to employ rigorously the style of discourse that we may call pramāṇavāda or “pramāṇa theory.” This style of discourse, which appears to arise primarily from the early efforts of the Nyāya school, focuses on what constitutes a pramāṇa, i.e., the reliable means or (literally) “instrument” for arriving at a trustworthy or reliable cognition (pramiti).
    [Show full text]
  • Meditation and Metaphysics on Their Mutual Relationship in South Asian Buddhism1
    E l i F r a n c o Meditation and Metaphysics On their mutual relationship in South Asian Buddhism1 It is well known that Buddhism developed and prescribed a large number of meditative exercises. It is equally well known that Buddhism developed some highly original metaphysical doctrines, such as the anātman-doctrine, i.e., the doctrine that there is no soul and no substance, the doctrine of momentariness, i.e., the doctrine that all things, even those that seem permanent such as stones and mountains, last for only a moment, the doctrine of Emptiness of the Madhyamaka according to which nothing really exists and all things are but an illusion, or the idealism of the Yogācāra which professes that the external world is merely an image in our consciousness. However, it may be less well known that all metaphysical doctrines of Buddhism have their correspondence in meditative practice, and some of them may even have arisen from such practice. There are at least two main reasons for this state of affairs. First the general tendency in Indian thought to presuppose a correspondence theory of truth. In other words, if the objects visualized by the yogi during meditation are to be considered true, they must have a correspondence in reality. In this respect, the perception or awareness of yogis is not different from any other perception. 1 I would like to thank Lambert Schmithausen for personal and written comments on a previous draft of this paper and for being, as Halbfass once said of J.L. Mehta, “an ideal partner in dialogue.” 2 ELI FRANCO The second reason is that in the majority of Buddhist traditions, Enlightenment, or liberating insight, consists in a right insight into the true nature of reality.
    [Show full text]
  • Dharmakirti's Dualism: Critical Reflections on a Buddhist Proof Of
    Philosophy Compass 3/5 (2008): 1079–1096, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00175.x Dharmakirti’s Dualism: Critical Reflections on a Buddhist Proof of Rebirth Dan Arnold* University of Chicago Abstract Dharmak}rti, elaborating one of the Buddhist tradition’s most complete defenses of rebirth, advanced some of this tradition’s most explicitly formulated arguments for mind-body dualism. At the same time, Dharmak}rti himself may turn out to be vulnerable to some of the same kinds of arguments pressed against physicalists. It is revealing, then, that in arguing against physicalism himself, Dharmak}rti does not have available to him what some would judge to be more promising argu- ments for dualism (arguments, in particular, following Kant’s 2nd Critique) – and indeed, that these arguments actually cut against Dharmak}rti’s own position. After elaborating and characterizing Dharmak}rti’s case for rebirth, then, this article briefly considers an argument that Dharmak}rti cannot himself enlist for this purpose. 1. Introduction: How Reductionists Can be Dualists ‘Eastern philosophies’, one sometimes hears people say, ‘are generally nondualist’. While it requires little effort to disabuse reasonable inter- locutors of the idea that ‘eastern philosophy’ is a useful category – it usually suffices to note the tremendous internal complexity of both the Indian and Chinese philosophical traditions, not to mention the enormous dif- ferences between these two broad streams of thought – the ‘nondualist’ characterization nonetheless sticks persistently to Buddhism, in particular. A passing acquaintance with Buddhist thought makes it easy to appreciate why this might be so; Buddhists, after all, are proponents chiefly of the ‘without self’ (anâtma) doctrine, and surely nothing could be more anti- Cartesian than thus to hold (as Buddhists do in elaborating this idea) that every moment of experience can be shown to depend upon a host of causal factors, none of which is what we ‘really’ are.
    [Show full text]
  • The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India
    A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE DAVID SEYFORT RUEGG THE LITERATURE OF THE MADHYAMAKA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY IN INDIA OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE EDITED BY JAN GONDA VOLUME VII Fasc. 1 1981 OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN DAVID SEYFORT RUEGG THE LITERATURE OF THE MADHYAMAKA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY IN INDIA 1981 OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE Contents of Vol. VII Vol. VII: Buddhist and Jaina Literature Fasc. 1: D. Seyfort Ruegg The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India CIP-KurztlteTaufnahtne der Deutschen Bibliothek A history of Indian literature / ed. by Jan Gonda. - Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz. NE: Gonda, Jan [Hrsg.] Vol. 7. Buddhist and Jaina literature Vol. 7. Fasc. 1. -> Ruegg, David Seyfort: The literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India Ruegg, David Seyfort: The literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India / David Seyfort Ruegg. — Wiesbaden : Harrassowitz, 1981. (A history of Indian literature ; Vol. 7, Fasc. 1) ISBN 3-447-02204-3 © Otto Hatrassowitz, Wiesbaden 1Q81. Alle Hecate vorbehalteu. Photographische und photomechatusche Wiedergabe nur mit ausdrucklicher Genehmigung des Verlages. Gesamtherstellung: Allgauer Zeitungsverlag GmbH, Kempten. Printed in Germany. Sigel: HIL CONTENTS Introduction 1 The early period: the formation of the Madhyamaka school 4 Nagarjuna 4 Commentaries on Nagarjuna's works 47 Aryadeva 50 Rahulabhadra 54 'Naga' 56 The middle period: the systematization of the Madhyamaka school .. .. 58 Buddhapalita 60 Bhavaviveka
    [Show full text]
  • 906C95b689c88a77985f8f573
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Shinshu University Institutional Repository 1 Adhyavasāya and Imagination Shinya Moriyama When the student of Indian philosophy is faced by the task of finding an equivalent for a conception which is familiar to him, because he meets it often used in his texts, he may nevertheless be often quite perplexed about how to render it in translation because there is no corresponding term available. In philosophy and logic all European languages form common stock, because they have a common ancestor in the writings of Aristotle. But Indian philosophy has developed independently from this influence. It has its own Aristotle and its own Kant. It constitutes an independent line of development which runs parallel to the European one. It is therefore of the highest historical interest to note the cases when both currents agree on a common conception or a common theory. It may be an indirect, partial proof of its truth, because truth is one, and error is many. (Stcherbatsky 1932: 226) I The primary goal of this article is to investigate adhyavasāya, a complex notion of Buddhist epistemology, from a comparative philosophical viewpoint. This notion, which is usually translated as “determination,” was first examined by Th. Stcherbatsky, a pioneer Russian scholar of Buddhist epistemology, as a mediator that bridges the gap between perception (pratyakṣa) and inference (anumāna), the two sources of our valid cognition. As is well known, in the Buddhist epistemological tradition founded by Dignāga (ca. 480-540) and Dharmakīrti (ca. 600-660), while perception is defined by the characteristic of “non-conceptual” or “without conceptual construction,” inference is considered to be a conceptual thought that is based on the necessary relation between two concepts or items being connected through causality or identity.
    [Show full text]