Fifth International Dharmakīrti Conference Abstracts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Fifth International Dharmakīrti Conference Abstracts Fifth International Dharmakīrti Conference Abstracts Heidelberg, 26–30 August, 2014 Crowne Plaza Hotel Abstracts are arranged in alphabetical order according to the speaker’s last name. Please consult the conference program, available from the conference website http://idhc5.uni-hd.de, for information on the order of presentations. The organizers gratefully acknowledge the assistance of Liudmila Olalde-Rico in the production of this document. 1 Balcerowicz, Piotr: Dharmakīrti and Samantabhadra University of Warsaw; [email protected] The paper analyses certain doctrinal points in the oeuvre of the Jaina Śvetāmbara thinker Samantabhadra who seems to respond to, to criticize and to be influenced by Dharmakīrti. The issues involve the idea of identity, the use of the delimiting particle eva in the sense of vyavaccheda (exclusion, delimitation), and certain passages in some of Samantabhadra’s works which reveal his knowledge of the Pramāṇavārttika. Samantabhadra – the author of such works as Āptamīmāṁsā, Devāgamastotra, Yuk- tyanuśāsana, Svayambhūstotra, Stutividyā – is traditionally considered to have lived around 500–550, maybe slightly later. Sometimes he is also thought to be contem- poraneous with Mallavādin Kṣamāśramaṇa, alias Vādimukhya (before 600 CE), the author of the Dvādaśāranayacakra, the source of plethora of quotations from Diṅnāga’s Pramāṇasamuccaya, who had apparently had no knowledge of Dhar- makīrti. The analysis of the historical correlation of Dharmakīrti and Samantabhadra may have possible implications for the dating of Dharmakīrti. 2 Choi, Kyeongjin: The indeterminate role of bādhakapramāṇa in the Pramāṇaviniścaya University of Tokyo; [email protected] 1 No one may be suspicious of the thought that bādhakapramāṇa validates pervasion (vyāpti) of sattvānumāna or dispute the idea that it materialized in complete form for the first time in the Pramāṇaviniścaya. Dharmottara proclaims the former in his commentary on the Pramāṇaviniścaya, and we also have Dharmakīrti’s Vādanyāya where he makes the proof of momentariness based on sattvānumāna whose perva- sion is certified by bādhakapramāṇa. If this were the case, the traditional proof of momentariness, which is supported by the idea of nirapekṣatva, that is, the cause- lessness of extinction, would be nothing more than a redundant demonstration in the Pramāṇaviniścaya. But if one does not have a biased impression of bādhakapramāṇa and just relies on the sentences which Dharmakīrti actually set forth in the Pramāṇaviniścaya, is it possible to see the position on bādhakapramāṇa pointed out by Dharmottara? In this paper, I would like to reconsider the aforementioned popular belief regarding bādhakapramāṇa and the proof of momentariness in the Pramāṇaviniścaya, with the assistance of rNgog Blo ldan shes rab’s commentary. rNgog understands the cause- lessness of extinction as the primary reason for the establishment of pervasion in the proof of impermanence. Further, in his opinion, bādhakapramāṇa is a secondary supportive attestation which works to stabilize the validity of the logic of causeless- ness. That is why he denies Dharmottara’s assertion, saying his stance on the cause- lessness of extinction is contradictory to Dharmakīrti’s intention. My aim in this paper is to indicate that the role of bādhakapramāṇa cannot be de- termined only based in the Pramāṇaviniścaya since Dharmakīrti did not yet make the purpose of bādhakapramāṇa clear in that text. I would like to carefully suggest that we must presume that this issue was still developing in Dharmakīrti’s mind at the time when he wrote this work. I will point out that, instead, what he mainly in- tended to establish is the effectiveness of svabhāvahetu as a logical reason, and that he only refers to the proof of impermanence based on the idea of causelessness as a prototypical example, not simply for the sake of proving impermanence, itself. 3 Chu, Junjie: Jitāri’s Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi University of Leipzig; [email protected] In this paper the author presents an analysis of Jitāri’s Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi, a short philosophical treatise that is up to now unknown. In this work, Jitāri refutes the bahirarthavāda with regard to the image of object (ākāra). At the start of the treatise, Jitāri divides bahirarthavāda into sākāravijñāna- vāda and nirākāravijñānavāda. He does not pay much attention to the sākāra- vijñānavāda-branch of the bahirarthavāda, saying that it is not in conformity with the whole set of the generally established worldly communicative convention and is nothing but a false determination (mithyābhiniveśa). In the remaining part he con- centrates on refuting the nirākāravijñānavāda-branch of the bahirarthavāda. 2 The refutation begins with a formal reasoning: “What illuminates [in cognition] is cognition [itself], such as the conceptualization of a blue thing; and [a sensory ob- ject] like visible matter illuminates [in cognition, therefore, it is cognition with the image of object]. This is the essential reason.” Then, he sets forth a long discussion to prove that the reason is valid, as he does in many other works of him, in the form of proving that the reason is not non-established (asiddhiḥ), is not contradictory (viruddhatvaṃ), and is not inconclusive (anaikāntikatā). In proving that the reason is not inconclusive, Jitāri tries to prove that the shining of cognition is exclusively a self-shining, not in the sense that an external thing is illuminated by cognition; he uses the pattern of “four alternatives” (catuskoṭi) to discuss the relationship between shining and object, i.e., “shining is different from the object-referent,” “shining is non-different from the object-referent,” “shining is both different and non-different from the object-referent,” and “shining is neither different nor non-different from the object-referent.” The conclusion of this discussion is: “Since it is not correct that one thing is illuminated by another thing, the necessary conclusion (ekānta) is: That which shines is exclusively itself, that which is not itself does never shine.” In the last part of the treatise, in order to explain that the shining of cognition is only self-shining, a further discussion is advanced on the temporal relationship between the cognition and the shining of object as the cause and effect from gram- matical point of view; in doing so, the opinions of Kumārila (ŚVK pratyakṣasūtra 54–55 quoted in TS 2923–2924) and Śubhagupta (BS 192b2: quoted in JNĀ 23,23– 24, 351,17–18; TSP(K) 569,15–17; TSP(Ś) 486,14–17) are also refuted. 4 Coseru, Christian: Consciousness and causal explanation – Śāntarakṣita against physicalism College of Charleston; [email protected] The Buddhist epistemologist’s justification for taking reflexivity as the condition for the possibility of warranted states of cognitive awareness is simply an extension of theoretical commitments to a certain conception of the mental. One place where this theory comes into particularly sharp focus is Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla’s chal- lenge of Cārvāka physicalism (in the chapter XXII of Tattvasaṅgraha). The Cār- vāka’s objection to any presumed continuity of reflexive self-awareness is framed by some easily recognizable arguments. First, if an individual is nothing but a bundle of aggregates that are in turn reducible to more basic material substrata (viz., atoms), then conscious awareness must be an emergent property (that is, conscious- ness must be regarded as nothing more than a product of the type of material organ- ization that is constitutive of biological organisms). Second, since consciousness takes the form of an apprehension of objects (that is, since it is inherently inten- tional), and apprehension only occurs in specific modes of cognizing such as per- ceiving or reasoning, consciousness cannot be present either when the sensory sys- tems are not yet developed (as in the embryonic stage) or when they are not re- sponsive (as in a state of comatose). Finally, the physicalist argues for what seems like an obvious point: different types of bodies (for instance, those of humans and 3 nonhuman animals), and different tokens of the same human body, manifest differ- ent types of consciousness. Assuming otherwise would be akin to postulating that consciousness can apprehend that which is contrary (viruddha) – a problematic pos- ition (for the Buddhist) given our lack of direct access to the minds of others (and to the interior life of nonhuman animals). In this paper, I review the Cārvāka argu- ments and Śāntarakṣita’s response, and consider whether the Buddhist can answer the challenge of physicalism without undermining the explanatory function of caus- al explanation. I then offer an innovative way to conceive of the notion of material causation (upādānakāraṇa) that builds on some recent debates at the intersection of phenomenology and philosophy of mind. 5 David, Hugo: Maṇḍana Miśra on omniscience (sarvajña- tva) and the perception of yogins (yogipratyakṣa) – On the early appropriation of a few Buddhist concepts in the Mīmāṃsā tradition University of Cambridge (UK); [email protected] Philosophical reflection on the nature of the perception of yogins (yogipratyakṣa), as well as on its quality of being “valid knowledge” (pramāṇa), stems back to the very early stages of the “epistemological” school of Buddhism, to the works of Dignāga and, above all, Dharmakīrti. It is not, however, until a much later date that this topic received a systematic treatment as part of a proof of the Buddha’s omniscience (sarvajñatva)
Recommended publications
  • Studies in Buddhist Hetuvidyā (Epistemology and Logic ) in Europe and Russia
    Nataliya Kanaeva STUDIES IN BUDDHIST HETUVIDYĀ (EPISTEMOLOGY AND LOGIC ) IN EUROPE AND RUSSIA Working Paper WP20/2015/01 Series WP20 Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studies Moscow 2015 УДК 24 ББК 86.36 K19 Editor of the series WP20 «Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studies» Vitaly Kurennoy Kanaeva, Nataliya. K19 Studies in Buddhist Hetuvidyā (Epistemology and Logic ) in Europe and Russia [Text] : Working paper WP20/2015/01 / N. Kanaeva ; National Research University Higher School of Economics. – Moscow : Higher School of Economics Publ. House, 2015. – (Series WP20 “Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studiesˮ) – 52 p. – 20 copies. This publication presents an overview of the situation in studies of Buddhist epistemology and logic in Western Europe and in Russia. Those studies are the young direction of Buddhology, and they started only at the beginning of the XX century. There are considered the main schools, their representatives, the directions of their researches and achievements in the review. The activity of Russian scientists in this field was not looked through ever before. УДК 24 ББК 86.36 This study (research grant № 14-01-0006) was supported by The National Research University Higher School of Economics (Moscow). Academic Fund Program in 2014–2015. Kanaeva Nataliya – National Research University Higher School of Economics (Moscow). Department of Humanities. School of Philosophy. Assistant professor; [email protected]. Канаева, Н. А. Исследования буддийской хетувидьи (эпистемологии и логики) в Европе и России (обзор) [Текст] : препринт WP20/2015/01 / Н. А. Канаева ; Нац. исслед. ун-т «Высшая школа экономи- ки». – М.: Изд. дом Высшей школы экономики, 2015. – (Серия WP20 «Философия и исследо- вания культуры»).
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Buddhist Philosophy
    A HISTORY OF B U D D H IS T P H ILO S O P H Y Continuities and Discontinuities * DAVID J. KALUPAHANA A HISTORY OF BUDDHIST PHILOSOPHY Continuities and Discontinuities David J. Kalupahana MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLISHERS PRIVATE LIMITED • DELHI Reprint: Delhi, 2006 First Indian Edition: Delhi, 1994 © 1992 University of Hawaii Press First Published by the University of Hawaii Press, 1992 ISBN: 81-208-1191-7 MOTILAL BANARSIDASS 41 U A Bungalow Road, Jawahar Nagar, Delhi 110 007 8 Mahalaxmi Chamber, 22 Bhulabhai Desai Road, Mumbai 400 026 236, 9th Main III Block, Jayanagar, Bangalore 560 011 203 Royapettah High Road, Mylapore, Chennai 600 004 Sanas Plaza, 1302 Baji Rao Road, Pune 411 002 8 Camac Street, Kolkata 700 017 Ashok Rajpath, Patna 800 004 Chowk, Varanasi 221 001 For sale in India only Printed in India BY JAINENDRA PRAKASH JAIN AT SHR1JAINENDRA PRESS, A-45 NARAINA, PHASER, NEW DELHI 110 028 AND PUBLISHED BYNARENDRA PRAKASH JAIN FOR MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLISHERS PRIVATE LIMITED, BUNGALOW ROAD, DELHI -110 007 This work, completed three days before an accident that left our youngest son, Milinda, paralyzed, is dedicated to our friends and well-wishers, at home and abroad, especially my colleagues Eliot Deutsch and Larry Laudan, whose gracious support lessened the trauma for both Milinda and the family. CONTENTS Introduction ix Abbreviations xv Part One: Early Buddhism I Indian Philosophy and the Search for Ultimate Objectivity 3 II Life of the Buddha 22 III Knowledge and Understanding 30 IV Experience and Theory (Paficcasamuppana and Pa(iccasamuppclda)
    [Show full text]
  • Positing Subtle Impermanence
    20 ??7?? Positing Subtle Impermanence In general “impermanence” is posited on the basis of whether some- thing undergoes change, and conditioned phenomena are subject to change owing to their causes and conditions.347 So if something has causes and conditions, it is subject to change, and if it does not have causes and conditions, it is not subject to change. [384] The fact of such conditioned phenomena being subject to change is primarily a function of the pro- ductive causes that produce them. As such, all conditioned phenomena continuously undergo change without remaining static for even a single moment. For example, owing to the change of a tree’s leaves, they fall to the ground with the arrival of cold in winter. It is not that they transform spontaneously, but rather they transform each day and week until in the end they fall to the ground. Those leaves that transform over many days do so naturally through merely being established. Therefore they transform moment by moment, and even though the eye does not see it, in reality they continuously transform. If subtle change did not exist moment by moment, then coarse transformation also could not arise. With respect to how the four characteristics of conditioned phenom- ena are understood, the Vaibhāṣikas, for example, assert that when the three characteristics of conditioned phenomena—arising, enduring, and disintegrating—illustrate the conditioned nature of something, such as the form aggregate, they do not do so on the basis of something arising and so on. They do so by way of demonstrating that the given phenomenon possesses characteristics such as arising that are distinct from it.
    [Show full text]
  • Studies in Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda Idealism I: the Interpretation of Vasubandhu’S Viṃśikā
    ASIA 2014; 68(3): 709 – 756 Birgit Kellner and John Taber Studies in Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda idealism I: The interpretation of Vasubandhu’s Viṃśikā Abstract: In recent scholarship there has been a persistent tendency, especially among North-American scholars, to deny that Indian Yogācāra philosophy is a form of idealism. The discussion has naturally focused on the interpretation of Vasubandhu’s Viṃśikā, a foundational text of the school, as well as one of the most accessible, which other researchers have taken to be denying the existence of a material world external to consciousness. In this article, after noting some of the points in favor of a non-idealist read- ing of the Viṃśikā, we shall offer a new reading that supports the old “standard”, but still widespread, interpretation that it indeed intends to deny the existence of physical objects outside of consciousness. We suggest that Vasubandhu develops in the Viṃśikā an extended argumentum ad ignorantiam where the absence of external objects is derived from the absence of evidence for their existence. This reading is the result of examining argumentation strategy rather than investigat- ing the logical structure of individual proofs in isolation, and it takes cues from Vasubandhu’s strategy for refuting the existence of a self in Abhidharma- kośabhāṣya IX. In addition, our reading looks at the entire Viṃśikā, rather than isolating a purported argumentative “core” (vv. 11–15), and draws attention to the relevance of some of its subtleties. Finally, we also suggest that Vasubandhu might have opted for a less direct argumentation strategy to prove the non- existence of the external world because of specific soteriological aspects of the doctrine of vijñaptimātratā.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Philosophy of Logics and Epistemology in Theravada Perspective
    © 2018 JETIR October 2018, Volume 5, Issue 10 www.jetir.org (ISSN-2349-5162) Understanding Philosophy of Logics and Epistemology in Theravada Perspective Prof. L. UdayaKumar* Vo Xuan Tam* P.Sreekant* P.Kesalu* 1. Introduction In Indian tradition of epistemology, the analysis of knowledge has been the main feature of many famous systems of thought like Nyaya, Vaisesika, Samkhya, Yoga. Purva-Mimamsa, Jain, Buddhism and Vedanta. Different kinds of means of knowledge (pramanas) which have been discussed by these traditions are: (i) direct knowledge or perception (pratyaksa), (ii) inference (anumana),(iii) knowledge by similarity (upamana), (iv) verbal testimony (sahda), including scriptural testimony (sastra or agama), (v) presumption (arthapatti), (vi) implication (sambhava), (vii) non-existence (abhava), and (viii) tradition (aitihya). The number of these means of knowledge accepted by each tradition, however, is different. The signs of epistemology are traceable as early as some of the hymns of the Rgveda. Many of philosophical schools then introduced and develop own analysis of epistemology. Buddhist tradition of logic and epistemology started with Dinnaga approximately one thousand years after the mahaparinirvana of the Sakyamuni Buddha. Though the topics of this tradition were traced back to the earliest teachings of the Buddha in Nikaya literature and some philosophical works of many famous Buddhist thinkers like Nagarjuna, Asanga, Vasubandhu, it was Dinnaga who officially founded this logico- epistemological system. We must recognize that the contribution of Buddhism to profound system of logic and epistemology of Indian philosophy began with Dinnaga. Dinnaga was the fist Buddhist thinker who set up and systematized the Buddhist theory of knowledge which has been definitely the foundation of later Buddhist development of epistemology carried our by Dharmakirti, Dharmottara, Santaraksita, Kamalasila.
    [Show full text]
  • The Yogācāra Philosophy of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti Georges Dreyfus University of Virginia & Christian Lindtner University of Copenhagen
    27 The Yogācāra Philosophy of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti Georges Dreyfus University of Virginia & Christian Lindtner University of Copenhagen Introduction We would like in this article to examine one of the most difficult points in Dharmakīrti’s thought, his presentation of the result of valid cognition (pramāṇa-phala, tshad ma’i ’bras bu). This part of Dharmakīrti’s work has been mostly ignored by modern scholars. The source of this neglect is not difficult to understand, having to do both with the difficulty of the relevant passages1 and the bizarre feature of the position that Dignāga and Dharmakīrti adopt. We are convinced, however, that these passages are quite important for understanding Dignāga’s Pramāṇa-Samuccaya (PS) and Dharmakīrti’s two main works, the Pramāṇa-Vārttika (PV) and the Pramāṇa-Viniścaya (PVin), as products of a unified intention. Up to this date, Dharmakīrti has often been understood in a piecemeal fashion. We think that it is time to attempt to understand not only his interesting views on epistemology, logic, and philosophy of language, but also to take a look at Dharmakīrti as an author of texts expressing a unified thought. From this perpective, some of the most relevant passages in the corpus of Dharmakīrti’s works concern the result of valid cognition. It is clear that we do not intend within such a short space to give a complete explanation of Dharmakīrti’s difficult thought on the subject. Hattori and Vetter have already done good preliminary work concerning Dignāga and Dharmakīrti’s treatment of this subject,2 but we shall nevertheless have to take some of their presuppositions and results up for revision.
    [Show full text]
  • Reverberations of Dharmakīrti's Philosophy
    The proceedings volume of the Fifth International Dharmakirti Conference (Heidelberg, August 2014) is concerned with the logico-epistemological school of Buddhism, a long- Birgit Kellner, Patrick McAllister, lasting tradition that pursued the analysis of knowledge, inference and proof within a Horst Lasic, Sara McClintock (eds.) Buddhist soteriological framework based on the works of the Indian epistemologist and logician Dharmakirti (6th–7th c. CE). Having been shaped in the environment of medieval India, with its multiple mutually interacting and partly competing religio-philosophical schools, the methods and approaches of Buddhist logic and epistemology had lasting impact on the intellectual history of Tibetan Buddhism and were also received in China and Japan. The 30 papers in this volume offer a snapshot of an international research landscape with centers in Vienna and Japan. They address historical and philological problems raised by important recent manuscript discoveries, pursue specific research questions in the history of philosophy, and undertake philosophical reconstructions and critical examinations relating to individual theories and arguments. By focusing on currents in Asia that developed and Reverberations applied rigorous philosophical methods, the volume aims to contribute to the formation of a better-founded global historical awareness in the field of philosophy. of Dharmakīrti‘s Birgit Kellner is the director of the Institute for the Cultural and Intellectual History of Asia at the Austrian Academy of Sciences. Patrick
    [Show full text]
  • Dharmakīrti's Apoha-Theory of Concept Formation
    Dharmakīrti’s Apoha-theory of Concept Formation: Some Key Features (Forthcoming from Columbia U. Press in a volume edited by M. Siderits and T. Tillemans) John D. Dunne Emory University The apoha-theory contains a number of occasionally technical and even counter-intuitive elements, and the main purpose of this chapter is to present its most fundamental features in a straightforward fashion. At the outset it is critical to note that, while certainly unified in its overall scope, the apoha-theory undergoes historical development that led to divergent interpretations among its formulators, and any single, unified account of the theory would be problematic. Hence, this chapter will focus on a pivotal historical moment in the theory’s development, namely, its articulation by the Buddhist philosopher Dharmakīrti (fl. 625), especially as interpreted by his immediate commentators, Devendrabuddhi (fl. 675) and Śākyabuddhi (fl. 700). To contextualize this particular layer of interpretation, I will begin with a brief historical overview and then present some contextual material under two headings: Dharmakīrti’s causal model of cognition along with the minimalism about concepts that such a model encourages; and the basics of his ontology. With these matters in place, I will then examine the fundamental points of Dharmakīrti’s apoha-theory. 1 Historical Overview The apoha-theory finds its first explicit articulation in the work of Dignāga (fl. 425), the first Buddhist philosopher to employ rigorously the style of discourse that we may call pramāṇavāda or “pramāṇa theory.” This style of discourse, which appears to arise primarily from the early efforts of the Nyāya school, focuses on what constitutes a pramāṇa, i.e., the reliable means or (literally) “instrument” for arriving at a trustworthy or reliable cognition (pramiti).
    [Show full text]
  • Meditation and Metaphysics on Their Mutual Relationship in South Asian Buddhism1
    E l i F r a n c o Meditation and Metaphysics On their mutual relationship in South Asian Buddhism1 It is well known that Buddhism developed and prescribed a large number of meditative exercises. It is equally well known that Buddhism developed some highly original metaphysical doctrines, such as the anātman-doctrine, i.e., the doctrine that there is no soul and no substance, the doctrine of momentariness, i.e., the doctrine that all things, even those that seem permanent such as stones and mountains, last for only a moment, the doctrine of Emptiness of the Madhyamaka according to which nothing really exists and all things are but an illusion, or the idealism of the Yogācāra which professes that the external world is merely an image in our consciousness. However, it may be less well known that all metaphysical doctrines of Buddhism have their correspondence in meditative practice, and some of them may even have arisen from such practice. There are at least two main reasons for this state of affairs. First the general tendency in Indian thought to presuppose a correspondence theory of truth. In other words, if the objects visualized by the yogi during meditation are to be considered true, they must have a correspondence in reality. In this respect, the perception or awareness of yogis is not different from any other perception. 1 I would like to thank Lambert Schmithausen for personal and written comments on a previous draft of this paper and for being, as Halbfass once said of J.L. Mehta, “an ideal partner in dialogue.” 2 ELI FRANCO The second reason is that in the majority of Buddhist traditions, Enlightenment, or liberating insight, consists in a right insight into the true nature of reality.
    [Show full text]
  • Dharmakirti's Dualism: Critical Reflections on a Buddhist Proof Of
    Philosophy Compass 3/5 (2008): 1079–1096, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00175.x Dharmakirti’s Dualism: Critical Reflections on a Buddhist Proof of Rebirth Dan Arnold* University of Chicago Abstract Dharmak}rti, elaborating one of the Buddhist tradition’s most complete defenses of rebirth, advanced some of this tradition’s most explicitly formulated arguments for mind-body dualism. At the same time, Dharmak}rti himself may turn out to be vulnerable to some of the same kinds of arguments pressed against physicalists. It is revealing, then, that in arguing against physicalism himself, Dharmak}rti does not have available to him what some would judge to be more promising argu- ments for dualism (arguments, in particular, following Kant’s 2nd Critique) – and indeed, that these arguments actually cut against Dharmak}rti’s own position. After elaborating and characterizing Dharmak}rti’s case for rebirth, then, this article briefly considers an argument that Dharmak}rti cannot himself enlist for this purpose. 1. Introduction: How Reductionists Can be Dualists ‘Eastern philosophies’, one sometimes hears people say, ‘are generally nondualist’. While it requires little effort to disabuse reasonable inter- locutors of the idea that ‘eastern philosophy’ is a useful category – it usually suffices to note the tremendous internal complexity of both the Indian and Chinese philosophical traditions, not to mention the enormous dif- ferences between these two broad streams of thought – the ‘nondualist’ characterization nonetheless sticks persistently to Buddhism, in particular. A passing acquaintance with Buddhist thought makes it easy to appreciate why this might be so; Buddhists, after all, are proponents chiefly of the ‘without self’ (anâtma) doctrine, and surely nothing could be more anti- Cartesian than thus to hold (as Buddhists do in elaborating this idea) that every moment of experience can be shown to depend upon a host of causal factors, none of which is what we ‘really’ are.
    [Show full text]
  • The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India
    A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE DAVID SEYFORT RUEGG THE LITERATURE OF THE MADHYAMAKA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY IN INDIA OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE EDITED BY JAN GONDA VOLUME VII Fasc. 1 1981 OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN DAVID SEYFORT RUEGG THE LITERATURE OF THE MADHYAMAKA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY IN INDIA 1981 OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE Contents of Vol. VII Vol. VII: Buddhist and Jaina Literature Fasc. 1: D. Seyfort Ruegg The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India CIP-KurztlteTaufnahtne der Deutschen Bibliothek A history of Indian literature / ed. by Jan Gonda. - Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz. NE: Gonda, Jan [Hrsg.] Vol. 7. Buddhist and Jaina literature Vol. 7. Fasc. 1. -> Ruegg, David Seyfort: The literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India Ruegg, David Seyfort: The literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India / David Seyfort Ruegg. — Wiesbaden : Harrassowitz, 1981. (A history of Indian literature ; Vol. 7, Fasc. 1) ISBN 3-447-02204-3 © Otto Hatrassowitz, Wiesbaden 1Q81. Alle Hecate vorbehalteu. Photographische und photomechatusche Wiedergabe nur mit ausdrucklicher Genehmigung des Verlages. Gesamtherstellung: Allgauer Zeitungsverlag GmbH, Kempten. Printed in Germany. Sigel: HIL CONTENTS Introduction 1 The early period: the formation of the Madhyamaka school 4 Nagarjuna 4 Commentaries on Nagarjuna's works 47 Aryadeva 50 Rahulabhadra 54 'Naga' 56 The middle period: the systematization of the Madhyamaka school .. .. 58 Buddhapalita 60 Bhavaviveka
    [Show full text]
  • 906C95b689c88a77985f8f573
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Shinshu University Institutional Repository 1 Adhyavasāya and Imagination Shinya Moriyama When the student of Indian philosophy is faced by the task of finding an equivalent for a conception which is familiar to him, because he meets it often used in his texts, he may nevertheless be often quite perplexed about how to render it in translation because there is no corresponding term available. In philosophy and logic all European languages form common stock, because they have a common ancestor in the writings of Aristotle. But Indian philosophy has developed independently from this influence. It has its own Aristotle and its own Kant. It constitutes an independent line of development which runs parallel to the European one. It is therefore of the highest historical interest to note the cases when both currents agree on a common conception or a common theory. It may be an indirect, partial proof of its truth, because truth is one, and error is many. (Stcherbatsky 1932: 226) I The primary goal of this article is to investigate adhyavasāya, a complex notion of Buddhist epistemology, from a comparative philosophical viewpoint. This notion, which is usually translated as “determination,” was first examined by Th. Stcherbatsky, a pioneer Russian scholar of Buddhist epistemology, as a mediator that bridges the gap between perception (pratyakṣa) and inference (anumāna), the two sources of our valid cognition. As is well known, in the Buddhist epistemological tradition founded by Dignāga (ca. 480-540) and Dharmakīrti (ca. 600-660), while perception is defined by the characteristic of “non-conceptual” or “without conceptual construction,” inference is considered to be a conceptual thought that is based on the necessary relation between two concepts or items being connected through causality or identity.
    [Show full text]