Spinoza on Individuals and Individuation: Metaphysics, Morals, and Politics Matthew Ad Vid Wion Marquette University

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Spinoza on Individuals and Individuation: Metaphysics, Morals, and Politics Matthew Ad Vid Wion Marquette University Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Spinoza on Individuals and Individuation: Metaphysics, Morals, and Politics Matthew aD vid Wion Marquette University Recommended Citation Wion, Matthew David, "Spinoza on Individuals and Individuation: Metaphysics, Morals, and Politics" (2011). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 145. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/145 SPINOZA ON INDIVIDUALS AND INDIVIDUATION: METAPHYSICS, MORALS, AND POLITICS by Matthew D. Wion, B.A., M.A. A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin August 2011 ABSTRACT SPINOZA ON INDIVIDUALS AND INDIVIDUATION: METAPHYSICS, MORALS, AND POLITICS Matthew D. Wion, B.A., M.A. Marquette University, 2011 This dissertation examines Spinoza's position regarding the relationship of the individual to the community and to other individuals in the context of a particular reading of Spinoza's metaphysics as holistic. By the term “holistic metaphysics,” I refer to Spinoza's view of reality as a unified whole rather than as a collection of entirely separate parts. The latter I call a “reductionistic metaphysics.” If a reductionistic metaphysics tends to see individuals as essentially separate and only secondarily relational, a holistic metaphysics pictures individuals as primarily relational and only by means of their relations capable of any meaningful “separateness” from other individuals. The reading advanced here concludes that Spinoza holds that individuals cannot ultimately be separated from the larger environment and network of relationships of which they are always a part. This dissertation concludes with brief set of reflections on the potential implications of this “relational” understanding of individuals in the realms of morals and politics. How Spinoza might view the issue of “universal health care” in the context of his holistic metaphysics is singled out for specific consideration. i ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Matthew Wion, B.A., M.A. This dissertation would not have been possible without my dissertation committee Dr. Michael Wreen, Dr. Lee Rice, Dr. Timothy Crockett, and Dr. William Starr. These gentlemen worked with me rigorously, patiently, carefully, and always with grace and understanding. Apart from their kindness, knowledge, and discipline, this dissertation could never have been written. I am more grateful to these four professors than my words could ever convey. I wish to thank Dr. Rice in particular among my readers. Dr. Rice agreed to read my dissertation as an emeritus professor, truly going above and beyond the call of duty. He displayed great patience with me in my first flawed attempts at writing it. I have benefited immensely from his intellectual guidance, superb scholarship, impressive knowledge, and warm friendship during my entire program of doctoral studies at Marquette University. I would also like to express my sincere debt to Dr. Steven Barbone of San Diego State University. Dr. Barbone first introduced me to Spinoza many years ago at SDSU. His mentorship and guidance made it possible for me to attend graduate school and complete a Ph. D. in philosophy. He has always been there to offer advice, lend an ear, and provide encouragement and support. I would like to thank my family and friends above all for all the love and support that they have given me over the years: to my parents for supporting me emotionally, ethically, intellectually, and financially not only throughout my years of graduate study, ii but my entire life; to my brother Doug and my sister Caitlin for always being there when I need them; to Jason Parker, Arun Iyer, and Earl Cookson for not only lending me the love and support of true friends, but the thoughtful and critical ear of fellow philosophers. Among my friends I give special thanks to Daniel Esposito. Dan graciously assisted me with issues of grammar, mechanics, and formatting throughout the writing of this dissertation. Without his tireless and generous assistance, this dissertation would be far less than it is. I would also like to thank Rosa Vargas for offering me advice and guidance on MLA format. This list of acknowledgments would not be complete without expressing my debt of gratitude to my wife Erica Wion for her love, affection, kindness, and willingness to marry me. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS....................................................................................... i LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS.................................................................................... v INTRODUCTION...................................................................................................... 1 CHAPTER I. OUTLINE OF SPINOZA'S METAPHYSICS…………………………………………………................ 4 The Central Metaphysical Concepts………………………………………………………….… 4 Spinoza's Theory of Distinctions……………………………………………………........ 16 Spinoza's Metaphysical Holism................................................................................................ 36 II. SPINOZA'S INDIVIDUALS AND PROBLEMS WITH HIS ACCOUNT.................................................................................................... 46 Cartesian Physics............................................................................... 47 Spinoza on Minds and Bodies................................................................................................ 51 Spinoza's Physics............................................................................... 56 Organism and Teleonomy......................................................................................... 64 III. INDIVIDUAL AND COMMUNITY.............................................................................................. 72 Matheron's Contribution...................................................................................... 73 Spinoza's Theory of the State................................................................................................... 82 iv The State as an Individual.................................................................. 91 The State as a Metaphorical Individual ……………………….…… 95 Rice's Contribution............................................................................. 101 IV. EGOISM IN THE CONTEXT OF RELATION AND AUTONOMY ................................................................................................ 105 Curley's Case for Spinoza as Egoist.................................................................................................. 109 Bennett on Spinoza's Egoism................................................................................................ 117 Feminist Readings of Spinoza's Individuals.......................................................................................... 120 Armstrong's Contribution................................................................... 125 Spinoza on Friendship and Love.................................................................................................... 132 Rice on Spinoza's Radical Individualism...................................................................................... 137 V. SOME CLOSING NOTES ON THE POLITICAL AND MORAL IMPLICATIONS OF SPINOZA'S THEORY Of INDIVIDUALS.............................................................................................. 142 Spinoza and Health Care Coverage.............................................................................................. 153 BIBLIOGRAPHY...................................................................................................... 161 v LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS Works by Spinoza: CM – Metaphysical Thoughts E – Ethics (followed by arabic numeral for part and internal references) Ep – Letter (followed by arabic numeral) KV – Short Treatise (Korte Verhandeling) PPC – Principles of Cartesian Philosophy TP – Political Treatise (TP 1/2 is Chapter 1, Paragraph 2) TTP – Theological-Political Treatise (TTP 1/2 is Chapter 1, Paragraph 2) Works by Descartes: CSM – The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Eds. J. G. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Followed by volume and page number with parallels to Adam and Tannery texts) AT – Oeuvres de Descartes. Eds. C. Adam and P. Tannery (provided as parallel texts to CSM) Internal References for the Ethics: a – Appendix to E4 (followed by a number, e.g. E4a17) APP – Appendix (with the exception of the appendix to E4) Ax – Axiom Cor – Corollary Def – Definition Dem – Demonstration lemma – Lemma P – Propositions Pref – Preface Schol – Scholium Note on Translations: The English translations of Spinoza are those of Samuel Shirley unless specifically stated otherwise. The English translations of Descartes are taken from CSM volumes. Translations of Matheron and Zac are my own. 1 Introduction Spinoza speaks often of individuals. Indeed, the well-being of a particular set of individuals, namely human individuals, is the principal focus of his philosophy. Naturally we expect such a systematic philosopher as Spinoza to provide a theory about what, precisely, an individual is. This expectation is bound to be present with regard to any philosopher who stresses the importance of individuals. For Spinoza, however, the problem is particularly acute, for he famously argues that there is only one substance, one self-existent being. If there is only one substance, it seems to follow that there is only one individual. Since
Recommended publications
  • 'Introspectionism' and the Mythical Origins of Scientific Psychology
    Consciousness and Cognition Consciousness and Cognition 15 (2006) 634–654 www.elsevier.com/locate/concog ‘Introspectionism’ and the mythical origins of scientific psychology Alan Costall Department of Psychology, University of Portsmouth, Portsmouth, Hampshire PO1 2DY, UK Received 1 May 2006 Abstract According to the majority of the textbooks, the history of modern, scientific psychology can be tidily encapsulated in the following three stages. Scientific psychology began with a commitment to the study of mind, but based on the method of introspection. Watson rejected introspectionism as both unreliable and effete, and redefined psychology, instead, as the science of behaviour. The cognitive revolution, in turn, replaced the mind as the subject of study, and rejected both behaviourism and a reliance on introspection. This paper argues that all three stages of this history are largely mythical. Introspectionism was never a dominant movement within modern psychology, and the method of introspection never went away. Furthermore, this version of psychology’s history obscures some deep conceptual problems, not least surrounding the modern conception of ‘‘behaviour,’’ that continues to make the scientific study of consciousness seem so weird. Ó 2006 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Introspection; Introspectionism; Behaviourism; Dualism; Watson; Wundt 1. Introduction Probably the most immediate result of the acceptance of the behaviorist’s view will be the elimination of self-observation and of the introspective reports resulting from such a method. (Watson, 1913b, p. 428). The problem of consciousness occupies an analogous position for cognitive psychology as the prob- lem of language behavior does for behaviorism, namely, an unsolved anomaly within the domain of an approach.
    [Show full text]
  • Running Head: a REVIEW and EVALUATION of an OPEN 1
    Running Head: A REVIEW AND EVALUATION OF AN OPEN 1 A Review and Evaluation of an Open-Source Mood Assessment, the Brief Mood Introspection Scale Rachael M. Cavallaro University of New Hampshire Victoria Bryan University of New Hampshire John D. Mayer University of New Hampshire A REVIEW AND EVALUATION OF AN OPEN 2 Abstract The Brief Mood Introspection Scale (BMIS) is an open-source, 16-item assessment of current mood regularly used in psychological research. The scale has two sets of scales: one pair of scales assesses mood using Pleasant-Unpleasant and Arousal-Calm dimensions; the other (less used alternative) assesses mood using Positive and Negative Affect. However, since its publication in 1988, there have been no systematic reports of its usage pattern, norms or of evidence for its validity. The present meta-analysis aims to (1) identify the nature of the studies that employed the BMIS (i.e. research areas and design), (2) establish the norms for the BMIS the scale means, standard deviations, and reliabilities, and (3) evaluate for the BMIS’s validity. One hundred and fifty studies that utilized the BMIS over a five-year timespan (2016-2011) were identified, including 27 studies that reported information pertinent to the scale’s norms. Our findings indicated that BMIS was primarily used in experimental research, and that its norms were similar to those from the original report. We make recommendations for use of Likert response scales and scoring conventions. A more qualitative review suggested that the Pleasant- Unpleasant mood scale had considerable evidence for its validity from its relation to criteria.
    [Show full text]
  • Wilhelm Wundt & Herman Ebbinghaus Wilhelm Wundt & Herman
    1 2 Wilhelm Wundt & Herman Ebbinghaus Wilhelm Wundt & Herman Ebbinghaus 1. Wundt 2. Ebbinghaus A. Biographical details A. Biographical details B. Career history B. Career history C. Psychological theories C. Psychological theories D. Impact on Psychology D. Impact on Psychology Setting the Scene… 3 4 (After Darwin, Descartes (d. 1650) – psychologists William James (1890) – we consist of a preferred the study we are not automata; material body & of learning to that of consciousness selects immaterial soul consciousness) (Newton) Copernicus (1543): J.-O. la Mettrie (1748) Charles Darwin (1859) Wilhelm Wundt Sigmund Freud heliocentric theory of the L’Homme Machine – (On the Origin of Species) (1879) established (1899) – unconscious universe – Earth, and humans are just more – evolution by common first lab for study of more important than human race, are not the complex animals descent of all creatures human psychology consciousness centre of the universe Opposing views… 5 6 Humans are special. We’re not just smarter monkeys. Reflective self- consciousness (subjective experience) is unique to humans. It is too Wilhelm Wundt remarkable to have evolved for no reason. It permits selection. It creates (1832-1920) our experience of the world. It makes us care whether we live or die. William James Wilhelm Wundt Humans are not special – we are not the center of the universe. We’re just more complex animals on a little planet in an uncaring universe. Consciousness is not special (in any useful way) – it doesn’t produce our behavior; our behavior issues from unconscious processes shared with animals and generated by brains. Consciousness is an epiphenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • An Interpretation of Kant's Political Philosophy in Light of His Critical-Regulative Method
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 11-2011 Politics, history, critique: An interpretation of Kant's political philosophy in light of his critical-regulative method. Dilek Huseyinzadegan DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Huseyinzadegan, Dilek, "Politics, history, critique: An interpretation of Kant's political philosophy in light of his critical-regulative method." (2011). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 110. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/110 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. POLITICS, HISTORY, CRITIQUE: AN INTERPRETATION OF KANT’S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY IN LIGHT OF HIS CRITICAL-REGULATIVE METHOD A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October 2011 By Dilek Huseyinzadegan Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois Acknowledgements This dissertation would not have been possible without the help and support of many people. The Department of Philosophy at DePaul University provided a doctoral scholarship for eight years of graduate study. I thank the faculty for their help and support throughout this process, especially my dissertation director Avery Goldman, whose approach to Kant and his method inspired this project in the first place, my committee members Elizabeth Millàn, Kevin Thompson, and Rick Lee, whose graduate seminars gave rise to numerous fruitful discussions on German Idealism and Romanticism, history and politics, and critical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Anti-Jewish Tropes in Modern Philosophy Svenungsson, Jayne
    Enlightened Prejudices : Anti-Jewish Tropes in Modern Philosophy Svenungsson, Jayne Published in: Rethinking Time : Essays on History, Memory and Representation 2011 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Svenungsson, J. (2011). Enlightened Prejudices : Anti-Jewish Tropes in Modern Philosophy. In H. Ruin, & A. Ers (Eds.), Rethinking Time : Essays on History, Memory and Representation (Vol. 9, pp. 279-290). Södertörn Philosophical Studies. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Published in Andrus Ers and Hans Ruin (eds.), Conceptualizing History: Essays on History, Memory and Representation, Södertörn Philosophical Studies 11, Huddinge: Södertörn University, 2011, 279–290. ISBN: 978-91-86069-32-2.
    [Show full text]
  • Introspection Mark Engelbert and Peter Carruthers∗
    Advanced Review Introspection Mark Engelbert and Peter Carruthers∗ Two main questions about introspection are addressed: whether it exists, and whether it is a reliable source of self-knowledge. Most philosophers have assumed that the answers to both questions are positive, whereas an increasing number of cognitive scientists take the view that introspection is either nonexistent (with self-attributions of mental states being made on the same sort of interpretative basis as attributions of mental states to other people) or unreliable. A number of different models of self-knowledge are discussed, and the evidence bearing on the existence and reliability of introspection is reviewed. New experiments are required to tease apart some of the alternatives. 2010 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. WIREs Cogn Sci 2010 1 245–253 hilosophers have traditionally assumed that the form of noninterpretative access is what is normally Phuman mind is largely transparent to itself.1–3 referred to as ‘introspection.’ (Some reserve the term The thesis of mental transparency can be divided into ‘introspection’ for those cases where one consciously a conjunction of two claims: (1) mental states are self- and deliberately pays attention to one’s mental states.4 presenting (if one is undergoing a given mental state, We will not follow this usage.) then one knows that one is) and (2) our knowledge of A distinction should be drawn between access mental states is infallible (if one believes that one is to our own mental states that is inferential and access undergoing a given mental state, then so one is). The that is interpretive. Many cognitive processes—in- scope of this thesis has generally been restricted to cluding perceptual processes like vision and language current mental events of judging, deciding, reasoning, parsing—are thought to be inferential in that they experiencing, imagining, and feeling, however.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza on the Body Politic
    _full_journalsubtitle: A Journal for the Study of Science, Technology and Medicine in the Pre-modern Period _full_abbrevjournaltitle: ESM _full_ppubnumber: ISSN 1383-7427 (print version) _full_epubnumber: ISSN 1573-3823 (online version) _full_issue: 1 _full_issuetitle: The Body Politic from Medieval Lombardy to the Dutch Republic _full_alt_author_running_head (neem stramien J2 voor dit article en vul alleen 0 in hierna): 0 _full_alt_articletitle_running_head (rechter kopregel - mag alles zijn): From the King’s Two Bodies to the People’s Two Bodies _full_is_advance_article: 0 _full_article_language: en indien anders: engelse articletitle: 0 46 Early Science and Medicine 25 (2020) 46-72 Terpstra www.brill.com/esm From the King’s Two Bodies to the People’s Two Bodies: Spinoza on the Body Politic Marin Terpstra Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands [email protected] Abstract In this article, using Spinoza’s treatment of the image of the political body, I aim to show what happens to the concept of a healthy commonwealth linked to a monarchist model of political order when transformed into a new context: the emergence of a democratic political order. The traditional representation of the body politic becomes problematic when people, understood as individual natural bodies, are taken as the starting point in political theory. Spinoza’s understanding of the composite body, and the assumption that each body is composed, raises the question of the stability or instability of this composition. This has implications for the way one looks
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics on Identity and Individuation Author(S): Eric Lewis Source: Phronesis, Vol
    The Stoics on Identity and Individuation Author(s): Eric Lewis Source: Phronesis, Vol. 40, No. 1 (1995), pp. 89-108 Published by: Brill Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4182488 Accessed: 27-02-2017 20:30 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Brill is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis This content downloaded from 140.105.48.199 on Mon, 27 Feb 2017 20:30:04 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms The Stoics on Identity and Individuation ERIC LEWIS Gisela Striker opens her artful "Antipater, or the art of living" with the statement that "In reading the doxographical reports on Stoic philosophy, one gets the impression that the Stoics had a singular, and often irritating, predilection for identity statements."' She goes on to claim "that some of the arguments that have been handed down to us from the second-century controversy about the Stoic definitions of the goal of life depend on the improper use of identity-statements, which however the Stoics, by their predilection for such propositions, seem practically to invite."2 I agree with her that much confusion arises due to statements by Stoics which look like (and may in fact be) identity statements.
    [Show full text]
  • Framing Christian Eschatology Through Natural Teleology? Theological Possibilities and Concerns
    Framing Christian Eschatology through Natural Teleology? Theological Possibilities and Concerns Leidenhag, M. (2019). Framing Christian Eschatology through Natural Teleology? Theological Possibilities and Concerns. Heythrop Journal . https://doi.org/10.1111/heyj.13305 Published in: Heythrop Journal Document Version: Peer reviewed version Queen's University Belfast - Research Portal: Link to publication record in Queen's University Belfast Research Portal Publisher rights © 2019 Trustees for Roman Catholic Purposes Registered. Published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd. This work is made available online in accordance with the publisher’s policies. Please refer to any applicable terms of use of the publisher. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Queen's University Belfast Research Portal is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The Research Portal is Queen's institutional repository that provides access to Queen's research output. Every effort has been made to ensure that content in the Research Portal does not infringe any person's rights, or applicable UK laws. If you discover content in the Research Portal that you believe breaches copyright or violates any law, please contact [email protected]. Download date:02. Oct. 2021 Framing Christian Eschatology through Natural Teleology? Theological Possibilities and Concerns Mikael Leidenhag New College. University of Edinburgh. Mound Place. EH1 2LX. UK. [email protected]. Christian theology typically maintains that God is transforming the universe into a New Creation. Christianity is significantly forward looking with its concern with the ‘last things’ and the final destinies of individual people, human history, and the cosmos as a whole.1 The history of the world is, therefore, interpreted in light of what will come.
    [Show full text]
  • Molecules, Information and the Origin of Life: What Is Next?
    molecules Perspective Molecules, Information and the Origin of Life: What Is Next? Salvatore Chirumbolo 1,* and Antonio Vella 2 1 Department of Neurosciences, Biomedicine and Movement Sciences, University of Verona, 37134 Verona, Italy 2 Verona-Unit of Immunology, Azienda Ospedaliera Universitaria Integrata, 37134 Verona, Italy; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +39-0458027645 Abstract: How life did originate and what is life, in its deepest foundation? The texture of life is known to be held by molecules and their chemical-physical laws, yet a thorough elucidation of the aforementioned questions still stands as a puzzling challenge for science. Focusing solely on molecules and their laws has indirectly consolidated, in the scientific knowledge, a mechanistic (reductionist) perspective of biology and medicine. This occurred throughout the long historical path of experimental science, affecting subsequently the onset of the many theses and speculations about the origin of life and its maintenance. Actually, defining what is life, asks for a novel epistemology, a ground on which living systems’ organization, whose origin is still questioned via chemistry, physics and even philosophy, may provide a new key to focus onto the complex nature of the human being. In this scenario, many issues, such as the role of information and water structure, have been long time neglected from the theoretical basis on the origin of life and marginalized as a kind of scenic backstage. On the contrary, applied science and technology went ahead on considering molecules as the sole leading components in the scenery. Water physics and information dynamics may have a role in living systems much more fundamental than ever expected.
    [Show full text]
  • 8 the Organism As a Semiotic and Cybernetic System
    8 The Organism as a Semiotic and Cybernetic System In this chapter we shall deal with three main issues: (a) Organisms as semiotic systems, (b) teleonomy, information control, and teleology, (c) the notion of biological self. Organisms are essentially biological systems that are able not only to coadapt with other biological systems but also to control environmental information, that is, able to control the relevant parameters of the environment.1 To do this, they have developed specialized systems for information selection and control [Subsec. 7.6.2]. Without information control no free energy would be acquired, and the organism could not survive. A change of some parameters (of external, environmental variables) will affect the system’s stability in some way and could be dangerous, either directly by destabilizing the system, or indirectly by hiding some free-energy sources. In other words, the necessity to control environmental information arises because the environment always changes in a way that (1) cannot be predetermined by the organism and (2) often raises new problems and challenges. From a pure systemic point of view, it is this selective pressure that also produces new forms of adaptation and new solutions, like sexual reproduction at a phylogenetic level [Subsec. 7.5.2]. Therefore, adapta- tion, although going beyond the issue of information control, could not happen without the latter [Sec. 7.2]: An adaptive behavior is a special case of the behavior of a stable system [Subsec. 6.3.1], the region of stability being the region of the phase space in which all the essential variables lie within their normal limits2 (this is called homeostasis).
    [Show full text]
  • Locke's Distinctions Between Primary and Secondary Qualities
    Locke’s Distinctions Between Primary and Secondary Qualities Michael Jacovides1 Is there a distinction between primary and secondary qualities? The question may rest on a confusion. It is not obvious that it would be raised if the questioner knew what he meant by ‘primary’ and ‘secondary’ qualities. There is at least this distinction. We may distinguish between the basic explanatory features of things and the derivative features they explain. In the disciplines that gave rise to chemistry, there’s a long tradition of calling the fundamental explanatory qualities or principles ‘firsts’ (Maier 1968: 17-18, Anstey 2000: 20-30). Aristotle’s ‘first qualities’ are hot, cold, dry, and wet; Paracelsus’s tria prima (‘three firsts’) are salt, sulphur, and mercury. Boyle was willing to follow Aristotelian usage in calling hot, cold, dry, and wet ‘first qualities’; he called what he considered to be the more fundamental attributes of size, shape, motion, and rest “Primary Modes of the parts of Matter, since from these simple Attributes or Primordiall Affections all the Qualities are deriv’d” (Boyle [1670] 1999: 6.267). If Locke were only interested in advocating mechanistic physics, his discussion of primary and secondary qualities would be of marginal interest. Long before the publication of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Boyle offers a defense of the thesis that “allmost all sorts of Qualities . may be produced Mechanically—I mean by such Corporeall Agents as do not appear, either to Work otherwise than by vertue of the Motion, Size, Figure, and Contrivance of their own Parts” (Boyle [1666] 1999: 5.302) which is clearer and more developed than Locke’s defense.
    [Show full text]