8 the Organism As a Semiotic and Cybernetic System
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
8 The Organism as a Semiotic and Cybernetic System In this chapter we shall deal with three main issues: (a) Organisms as semiotic systems, (b) teleonomy, information control, and teleology, (c) the notion of biological self. Organisms are essentially biological systems that are able not only to coadapt with other biological systems but also to control environmental information, that is, able to control the relevant parameters of the environment.1 To do this, they have developed specialized systems for information selection and control [Subsec. 7.6.2]. Without information control no free energy would be acquired, and the organism could not survive. A change of some parameters (of external, environmental variables) will affect the system’s stability in some way and could be dangerous, either directly by destabilizing the system, or indirectly by hiding some free-energy sources. In other words, the necessity to control environmental information arises because the environment always changes in a way that (1) cannot be predetermined by the organism and (2) often raises new problems and challenges. From a pure systemic point of view, it is this selective pressure that also produces new forms of adaptation and new solutions, like sexual reproduction at a phylogenetic level [Subsec. 7.5.2]. Therefore, adapta- tion, although going beyond the issue of information control, could not happen without the latter [Sec. 7.2]: An adaptive behavior is a special case of the behavior of a stable system [Subsec. 6.3.1], the region of stability being the region of the phase space in which all the essential variables lie within their normal limits2 (this is called homeostasis). I finally stress that at the level of unicellular organisms, especially the bacterial level, a localized information-control instance does not exist. This function is executed by the whole organism as both a distributed and an integrated system. 8.1 The Concept of Sign We have considered how problematic the classical concept of information-processing is [Sec. 6.1 and Subsec. 7.4.5]. The true mystery of life is how living beings are able to control environmental information by treating it as a sign of something that is fundamental for their own survival3 and act accordingly. For example, a certain chemical gradient is a sign of a certain free-energy resource. Signs are any form of being or activity in which some pattern (icon) and an indexical relation to a referent (an object or event) are connected [Fig. 8.1]. According to Peirce’s formulation,4 a sign is any physical event or object that stands for something in a certain respect or capacity. Summing up, there are two different features to be distinguished in any sign: 1[AULETTA 2008a]. 2[ASHBY 1952]. 3[VON HELMHOLTZ 1867, p. 586]. 4[PEIRCE CP, 2.228, 2.247–8, 2.304, and 1.540] [PEIRCE 1903c] [PEIRCE 1907]. Peirce was the father of semiotics. 248 The Concept of Sign 249 SIGN referent icon Fig. 8.1 General nature of the sign. The icon can be any pattern that can be associated with a certain referent. The referent can be any object, system, event, or outcome which can be physically interacted with. Ogden and Richards were the first scholars to make use of such triangles [OGDEN/RICHARDS 1923], but C. Cherry introduced this form [CHERRY 1957]. (1) The referent,5 i.e. the thing that a sign stands for. A sign has an indexical relation with its referent: A mark expresses this relation6 [Subsec. 5.1.4]. (2) A sign has such a relation with its referent in a certain respect. The icon is this respect, and it is the instructional or representational content of the sign, according to whether the direction is [Fig. 8.2] • From codified information (starting from the genome [Sec. 7.4]) to a referent (here repre- sented by a specific goal to be attained [Sec. 5.3], for instance the production of a protein displaying a certain function) or • From some external stimuli that are codified in informational terms at the membrane (for instance, for a receptor to be activated or not) [Sec. 7.6], or also in some peripheral sensory system (sensory coding [Subsec. 3.3.1]), to an internal representational or quasirepresen- tational pattern or function. This is the way in which information acquisition serves the needs of the organism. The assumption here is that ANY external signal or variation in the environment can in principle be codified in this way. In both cases, codification always occurs at the source [Subsec. 2.3.2], which is internal in the first case and external (rather at the surface) in the second one. In any case, only codified information at the source allows for the kind of information control that is necessary for the organism and that will be described below. This is the evolutionary pressure that explains the emergence [Subsec. 2.4.2] of a new classical information codification. The iconic content does not need to be an analogue of, or similar to, the referent. Anything to which the organism is sensitive can in principle stand for anything else if it is in a proper indexical relation with this something else and in a proper iconic respect relative to the organism and its needs. Speaking of animals’ dealing with signs, D. Premack asserts that a piece of plastic becomes a sign whenever the properties ascribed to the item are not those of the piece of plastic but of the object that it denotes.7 This is a very important intuition that can be generalized in this way: A 5[FREGE 1892a, FREGE 1892b]. 6Kripke thematized this referential relation in terms of the rigid indexicality of proper names [KRIPKE 1972] [AULETTA 2003a]. 7[PREMACK 1976]. 250 The Organism as a Semiotic and Cybernetic System INFORMATION SOURCE Fig. 8.2 There are two main information sources: One inside the organism and the other outside [see Sec. 7.2]. If we schematically depict the organism as a cell having a core, representing the genetic information (which is also true to a certain extent for unicellular eukaryotes), the first source is located in the most inner part of it (representing its program). The other source is the result of the interaction of the organism with the exterior environment and is depicted here as information codification taking place at the membrane (at the interface between interior and exterior). sign does not represent physical or chemical properties but the function a certain item has, plays, or represents for the organism.8 We can say that classical information-acquiring deals with the acquiring of information from a source, while representational semiotics, being a guess about the vital significance of an information source, can be conceived as kind of reversed Bayesian inference [Subsec. 6.1.1 and again Sec. 7.6]: This inference is expressed by the probability that, given a certain transduction, the parameters that may have caused it are those that the organism expects. For this reason, physical laws and semiotic controls require disjointed, complementary modes of description.9 Laws are global and inexorable [Sec. 2.4]. Controls are local and conditional. Life’s semiotical activity is born for the purpose of allowing the organism’s goal-directed activity,10 which is the true core of the cybernetic research program [Subsecs. 3.2.2 and 6.1.5]. Semiotic controls require several aspects, none of which are functionally describable by physical laws that, unlike semiotic systems which rely on an information source, are based on parameters like energy, time, and rates of change. However, they are structurally describable in the language of physics in terms of constraints, degenerate states and processes, information-sharing and selecting, differential timing, and irreversible dissipative events. The fact that semiotics cannot be dissociated from codified information (even if it is not by itself information but only dealing-with-information comprehending functions, outcomes, and processes that are not themselves codified) is of great relevance [Subsec. 7.4.5]. I mention here that some scholars have tried to build a theory of living beings in semiotic terms (so-called biosemiotics), but very often in sharp opposition to (at least classical) information theory.11 It seems to me that in 8[AULETTA et al. 2008]. 9[PATTEE 1995]. 10[PATTEE 1997]. 11[SEBEOK 1991, SEBEOK 2001] [HOFFMEYER 1996, HOFFMEYER 1997]. The Organism as a Teleonomic and Teleologic System 251 this way no significant result can be obtained. For instance, we have already considered [Sec. 7.2] how the concept of a new complex system may arise through a new level of integration of previous aspects (information processing, regulating, and selecting) that are already present at the level of the pure information-acquisition processes [Subsec. 2.3.2]. Moreover, I have said that the most basic relation that grounds the semiotic processes of life can be found in the connection between codified information and function in the activation–transcription–translation process. Among the first scholars to have understood life in semiotic terms was J. von Uexk¨ull.12 Indeed, only living beings grasp and produce signs. In the physical world there are patterns [Subsec. 6.3.1], but there is no agent other than an organism that is able to refer these patterns to objects, events, or operation outcomes through a proper indexical relation,13 which is another way of saying that it is only organisms that can show adaptation processes.14 This means that physical (or informational) patterns (i.e. signals) cannot be interpreted as signs if not through a biological system able to treat them as signs. 8.2 The Organism as a Teleonomic and Teleologic System 8.2.1 Teleonomy We have remarked that prebiotic self-organizing systems like B´enard cells are dependent on entropic fluxes that are not controlled by themselves, and this is the main relation they have with the environment [Subsecs.