Burke's Philosophical Enquiry and Wollstonecraft's Rights Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Burke's Philosophical Enquiry and Wollstonecraft's Rights Of Burke’s Philosophical Enquiry and Wollstonecraft’s Rights of Men : Aesthetics Applied to the Debate on Manners Sora Sato Introduction This essay1) discusses Edmund Burke’s early aesthetic work, Philosophical Enquiry2) and Mary Wollstonecraft’s Vindication of the Rights of Men.3) Although the Rights of Men is a critical response to Burke’s most famous work, Reflections on the Revolution in France,4) it deserves particular attention that she also discusses Burke’s aesthetics. Actually, the Rights of Men was the first published work to discuss the Enquiry and Reflections simultaneously, as well as the earliest published response to Reflections. The present essay will argue that the Enquiry might have been put into the eighteenth- century debate on manners, especially forming a part of Wollstonecraft’s view of manners by her reading of Burke’s aesthetics, although the intention of Burke in the Enquiry was scarcely linked to such a debate. In order to demonstrate this argument, we will consider I) what Burke intended in the Enquiry, and II) Wollstonecraft’s reception of the Enquiry. Although this paper considers the present particular case, what is important is that the analysis should be closely related to the more general phenomenon of intellectual history, which will briefly be discussed in the final section. Ⅰ. Intellectual Contexts of Burke’s Aesthetics and Politics (a) Philosophical Enquiry Burke had speculated on the subject of Enquiry since he was in college.5) As he 1) The earlier version was submitted to University of Essex (Department of History) as a part of MA dissertation in September 2008. The author wishes to thank Professor James Raven (University of Essex) and an anonymous referee of this journal for their helpful comments. 2) Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful (1757-9), edited with an Introduction by J.T. Boulton (London, 1958). Hereafter, Enquiry. About Boulton’s introduction in this book, hereafter, Boulton (1958). 3) Mary Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Men (1790), in The Works of Mary Wollstonecraft, ed. Marilyn Butler and Janet Todd (London, 1989), V. Hereafter, VRM. 4) Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790), in The Writings and Speeches of Edmund Burke, eds., Paul Langford and others (Oxford, 1981-), VIII. Hereafter, Reflections, WS. ― 36 ― mentions in the 1757 preface of Enquiry, ‘it is four years now since this enquiry was finished’: he had completed his treatise as the most ambitious literary project of his early days in 1753.6) In general, Burke was rooted in his empirical age, in which the Newtonian tradition and John Locke’s philosophy were influential. 7) In particular, the Enquiry belongs to the philosophical tradition of Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690).8) What has often been pointed out is that the introductory section ‘On Taste’, which was added to the second edition of the Enquiry, may be intended to oppose David Hume’s view on taste in his Dissertation on Taste.9) His discussion on ‘sympathy’ also suggests Hume’s influence, although we must take account of a general increasing interest in the significance of sympathy in this period. 10) However, Burke was under the influence not only of Hume, but also the earlier philosophers such as Locke, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury, and Francis Hutcheson. For instance, the pleasure-pain principle had been a theme discussed by several previous philosophers. Burke may have referred to Hutcheson in his comments on the emotion of sex. 11) Besides, when he discusses the qualities of beautiful objects, his emphasis on sight suggests that he follows the tradition of Aristotle, Locke and Joseph Addison. 12) While sharing a lot of themes of philosophy and aesthetics with his predecessors, Burke criticized or tried to overcome their theories. He criticizes the theories ‘which connect beauty with proportion, with fitness (or utility), and with goodness or perfection’ supported since the time of Plato. 13) Boulton concludes about Burke’s theory of beauty that although Burke agrees with his predecessors in some respects, ‘he departs from orthodoxy’.14) Burke’s theory of words, which attracts many modern researchers, also ‘represents a reaction against the distrust of language among post-Baconian writers in the previous century’. Although such writers claim that ‘words would simply be marks of things’ and ‘emotional and historical associations would be non -existent’,15) 5) F.P. Lock, Edmund Burke Volume I, 1730-1784 (Oxford, 1998), p.91. 6) Enquiry, p.2. Burke continues: ‘during which time the author found no cause to make any material alteration in his theory’. See also Lock (1998), pp.87, 92. 7) Boulton (1958), pp.xxviii, lvii. 8) Lock (1998), p.92. ‘Burke was familiar with Locke’s Essay from his student days’. (p.93). 9) Boulton (1958), pp.xxviii-xxix. 10) Boulton (1958), pp.xli-xlii. 11) Boulton (1958), pp.xl-xli. 12) Boulton (1958), pp.lxxii-lxxiii. According to Lock, the lectures given by the oculist John Taylor, which Burke attended in 1745, ‘could have started him thinking about the physiology of perception, and about the experiences of the blind, which provide important evidence for his theory’. See Lock (1998), p.91. 13) Boulton (1958), p.lx. See also pp.lxii-lxiii. For example, Addison accepted the proportionist theory in the Spectator, and the theory which links beauty with moral perfection was supported by Plato, Aquinas and Shaftesbury. 14) Boulton (1958), p.lxxii. 15) Boulton (1958), p.lxxvii. ― 37 ― Burke asserts that words can excite and convey emotion or ideas. 16) While the younger Burke relied on inherited ideas, he also tried to overcome them. For the discussion of the present paper, it is significant that the early Burke read Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Hume and Addison because they were the writers who discussed (male) manners being reformed in the eighteenth century. To what extent would Burke’s aesthetics be linked to contemporary debate on manners? To answer this question, we need to grasp the intention of his book. Lock argues that the purpose of Enquiry is ‘to explain how the mind receives and responds to the categories of ideas that he calls ‘the sublime’ and ‘the beautiful’’: to find out the laws of the operations of human mind. 17) According to Bullard, the particular polemical purpose was to demonstrate the incompatibility of the aesthetic categories of the sublime and beautiful.18) In other words, the aim of the Enquiry was ‘to refute those writers who treated them as synonyms, or at least, to caution those who combined them as a collocation’.19) While the topic of ‘sublimity’ was, as well as ‘beauty’, popular among eighteenth-century critics and aestheticians, only Shaftesbury, before Burke, had brought the two words into the single collocation ‘sublime and beautiful’.20) Burke tried to distinguish the sublime from the beautiful, attacking Shaftesbury’s view of aesthetics. Nevertheless, Bullard also argues that the purpose of the treatise is not absolutely clear. Despite the fact that the project of the Enquiry ‘began as a rejection of Shaftesbury’s moral philosophy, the later stages of its composition had shifted it into the realm of aesthetic and critical discourse’. 21) Although the intention of Burke’s aesthetics is not completely comprehensible, if Burke wrote the Enquiry to search the reaction of human mind to the aesthetic categories, or criticize critics who confuse the sublime and the beautiful, his aesthetics may not be explicitly connected to contemporary debate on manners. (b) Burke’s Political Writings It is also significant to consider what intellectual traditions his political writings relied upon, in order to deepen our understanding about difference between Burke’s aesthetics and politics, or about Wollstonecraft’s reception of Burke, although there is no simple answer to this question. 22) As we will see, the intellectual contexts of Burke’s politics are not the same as those of his aesthetics. 16) See the fifth and final part of the Enquiry, pp.161-177. 17) Lock (1998), pp.93, 98. 18) Paddy Bullard, ‘The Meaning of the ‘Sublime and Beautiful’: Shaftesburian Contexts and Rhetorical Issues in Edmund Burke’s Philosophical Enquiry’, The Review of English Studies, New Series, 56:224 (2005), 169-191 (p.169). 19) Bullard, p.171. 20) Bullard, p.170. 21) Bullard, p.188. ― 38 ― The earlier studies emphasized the ‘natural law’ tradition in Burke’s thought. The studies of Stanlis, Canavan and Wilkins are the examples of the natural law interpretation.23) In particular, Stanlis and Strauss paid attention to the similarity between Burke and Thomas Aquinas.24) However, several critics today are skeptical of the importance of natural law for Burke’s thought. For example, Lock argues that Burke’s use of the natural law ‘is closely related to his rhetorical needs’. 25) Stanlis emphasizes the intellectual connection of Burke to Aristotle, Cicero, Aquinas and Hooker, whereas for Lock, Burke shares the intellectual world-picture more with Montesquieu, Magna Carta, Lord Somers and the Bill of Rights than with Aristotle or Aquinas. 26) The common-law tradition has also been considered significant on Burke’s thought. Valuable studies in this regard are Pocock (1960) and Postema. 27) Burke himself seemed to be conscious of this tradition, 28) and drew upon Sir Edward Coke’s and Sir Matthew Hale’s defence of English common law ‘as the refined embodiment of an inarticulable collective historical experience’.29) According to Pocock, Burke’s prescriptive constitution has two features: immemorial and customary. Burke’s argument of this was used to defend the English Constitution and to oppose the reform of the representation based on the principle of natural right. 30) According to Lucas, however, we should say 22) For instance, Hampsher-Monk argues that there are six intellectual contexts for understanding Burke’s thoughts: Natural Law, Common Law, Utilitarianism, Romanticism, Old Whiggery and Political Economy.
Recommended publications
  • Rousseau Or Wollstonecraft?
    Journal of Education and Practice www.iiste.org ISSN 2222-1735 (Paper) ISSN 2222-288X (Online) Vol.7, No.6, 2016 Who Won the Debate in Women Education? Rousseau or Wollstonecraft? Clifford Owusu-Gyamfi Faculty of Theology, University of Geneva, Chemin du Riolet 8, 1012-Lausanne, Switzerland Abstract Curriculum framework in the education of children became debatable during the enlightenment. Jean-Jacque Rousseau's treatise, Emile , outlined an educational curriculum based on natural rights. Rousseau thought education should be based on espousing and exploring the natural abilities of a person. Therefore, since women have a natural responsibility of care giving, their education should be given in line with helping them to enhance these natural caring abilities. Wollstonecraft, an enlightened philosopher, took on a literary protest against Rousseau's sexual politics in her treatise, A Vindication of the Rights of Women . This paper will show why Wollstonecraft’s idea is worth considering, in that it points the way past and out of a world of discrimination to create nondiscriminatory educational concept for future generation. Since discriminatory educational ideologies perpetrates in contemporary societies in diverse fashions, this paper challenges such cultures to rethinking the imperativeness of women education. Keywords: Jean-Jacque Rousseau, Mary Wollstonecraft, Women education, Sexist politics Acknowledgement: My deepest appreciation to Abigail Gyasi of Temple University for the encouragement to write about this subject. 1. Introduction Emile is a treatise written by the French enlightened author Jean-Jacque Rousseau. In this popular work, Rousseau seeks to put across the point that education should be based on espousing and exploring the natural abilities of a person (Rousseau & Allan, 1979: 37).
    [Show full text]
  • Our Debt to Mary Wollstonecraft, Moral and Intellectual Pioneer for Women
    Our Debt to Mary Wollstonecraft, Moral and Intellectual Pioneer for Women By Susan Roberts I teach a course entitled Leadership in Writing at the United States Coast Guard Academy that includes both male and female Officer Candidates. The women in my class are strong and unafraid to accept challenges. They perform jobs often seen as men’s work, live by the Coast Guard’s Core Values of Honor, Respect and Devotion to Duty, and balance their time between being on active duty and being wife, mother, or both. In our classes, we focus on examples of leadership in the military and civilian world. To mark Women’s History Month in March, I asked each Officer Candidate (OC) to select a female who exemplifies leadership and to present a speech about her. Their choices included Hillary Rodham Clinton, Sarah Palin, Margaret Thatcher, Queen Boudicca, Cleopatra, Elizabeth I, Sally Ride, Amelia Earhart, Rosa Parks, Susan B. Anthony, Mother Teresa, and Marie Curie. I responded by noting, “I see no one has claimed Mary Wollstonecraft.” A few moments of silence were followed by a series of questions: “Who is she?” “Is she in politics?” “Is she a writer?” “Why did you expect us to know her name?” and “Did she have anything to do with the Coast Guard?” I responded, “She was an eighteenth century writer. Women today owe her a debt of gratitude for we are beneficiaries of her ideas, which were quite revolutionary for her times. She advocated moral and intellectual education for women in a world where a woman’s voice rarely counted.” One of the handful of female OCs in class was curious enough to claim Wollstonecraft as the figure for her leadership speech, and all of the students were introduced to the life of this woman, the social changes she called for over two hundred years ago, and the impact of her work on opportunities for women then and now.
    [Show full text]
  • Women's Emancipation Through Education: the Radical Agenda of Mary Wollstonecraft (1759-1797)
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 359 085 SO 022 348 AUTHOR Roberts, Leonard H.; Pollman, Mary Jo TITLE Women's Emancipation through Education: The Radical Agenda of Mary Wollstonecraft (1759-1797). PUB DATE [92] NOTE 43p. PUB TYPE Information Analyses (070) Reports Descriptive (141) EDRS PRICE MF01/PCO2 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS Educational Change; *Educational History; Educational Opportunities; Educational Philosophy; Educational Theories; Elementary Secondary Education; *Equal Education; Females; *Feminism; Sex Bias; Sex Discrimination; *Womens Education IDENTIFIERS *Wollstonecraft (Mary) ABSTRACT Two hundred years ago, Mary Wollstonecraft, the English women's rights pioneer, published her immortal work: "A Vindication of the Rights of Woman." In it she placed much ofthe blame for women's inferior political, intellectual, and socialstatus on "faulty education." In "Vindication," she offered a number of recommendations aimed at enhancing the quality of educationfor women. These included: boys and girls schooled together and sharinga curriculum rich in experiential learning, particularly in scientific studies. She advocated physical exercise and playas well as health education specifically aimed at women's needs. These andother education proposals marked her asan important progenitor of many modern and widely accepted educational innovations. Contains20 references. (Author) *********************************************************************** Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the best thatcan be made from the original document. ***********************************************************************
    [Show full text]
  • Ellen Meiksins Wood
    EMPIRE OF CAPITAL V EMPIRE OF CAPITAL ------------♦------------ ELLEN MEIKSINS WOOD V VERSO London • New York For George Comninel, with thanks for many years of conversation First published by Verso 2003 © Ellen Meiksins Wood 2003 This paperback edition first published by Verso 2005 © Ellen Meiksins Wood 2005 All rights reserved The moral rights of the author have been asserted 13579 10 8642 Verso U K: 6 Meard Street, London w i f o e g USA: 180 Varick Street, New York, n y 10014-4606 www.versobooks.com Verso is the imprint of New Left Books i s b n 1-84467-518-1 British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Wood, Ellen Meiksins Empire o f capital 1. Capitalism— History 2. Imperialism 3. Globalization 4. International relations 5. Imperialism— History I. Title 330.l'22 ISBN 1844675181 Library o f Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A Catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress Typeset by SetSystems Ltd, Saffron Walden, Essex Printed by R. R. Donnelley & Son, USA CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS vii PREFACE TO THE PAPERBACK EDITION ix PREFACE XV INTRODUCTION 1 1 THE DETACHMENT OF ECONOMIC POWER 9 2 THE EMPIRE OF PROPERTY 26 3 THE EMPIRE OF COMMERCE 44 4 A NEW KIND OF EMPIRE 73 5 THE OVERSEAS EXPANSION OF ECONOMIC IMPERATIVES 89 6 THE INTERNATIONALIZATION OF CAPITALIST IMPERATIVES l l 8 7 ‘SURPLUS IMPERIALISM’, WAR WITHOUT END 14 3 NOTES 16 9 INDEX 177 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I have been exceptionally fortunate over the years in having first-rate post-graduate students, whose own work has inspired me and whose friendship I have continued to enjoy long after they finished their studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Representations of America in the English Jacobin Novel
    SPECULATIONS fiNANCIAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL NANCY E. ] OHNSON "Seated on her Bags of Dollars": Representations of America in the English Jacobin Novel N THE 17905, THE ENGLISH jacobin novel engaged in a sus­ I tained narrative critique of comracrarianism. While it supported the foundational premises of comractarianism-for example, the concept of inalienable rights for the individual-it also exposed the restrictive requirements and specifications that proponents of the social contract were imposing on political agency. In the fiction of Roben Bage, Mary Wollstonecraft, and Charlotte Smith, among others, it becomes evident that libcrry is a function of properry.1 To establish political authority, one has to be able to claim the right of properry, which begins with self-governance and culminates in proprietorship within society2 Financial dependence means dis­ qualification, and it precludes enfranchisement or claims to politi­ cal authority in any form, thereby excluding large segments of the populations such as women. Consequently, the English jacobin ' For an extended discussion of liberty as a function of property in early contractarian thought, see C.B. Macpherson, Ibe Political 7beory of Possesst~>e IndividualiSm (London: Oxford UP, 1962). 2 In Two TreatiSes on Gwernmem, Locke establishes ownership of the self as the IU~l fundam~nlal funH uf prupric:Lun,!Jip an<J ~~~~ t:::~~lllii.tl p~tUIMJI lo JX>liltc..iJI authority. "Though the Eanh, and all inferior Creatures be common to all Man, yet every Man has a Property in his own Person. This no Body has any Right to but himself.· See Locke, Two TreatiSes of Go,•emment, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Enlightenment Thinkers and Democratic Government
    1.3 Enlightenment Thinkers and Democratic Government Standard 1.3: Enlightenment Thinkers and Democratic Government Explain the influence of Enlightenment thinkers on the American Revolution and the framework of American government. (Massachusetts Curriculum Framework for History and Social Studies) [8.T1.3] FOCUS QUESTION: How did the Enlightenment Contribute to the Growth of Democratic Principles of Government? Building Democracy for All 1 "British Museum Room 1 Enlightenment" by Mendhak is licensed under CC-BY-SA-2.0 The Enlightenment (or Age of Reason) is the term used to define the outpouring of philosophical, scientific, and political knowledge in Europe at the beginning of the 18th century. European civilization had already experienced the Renaissance (1300-1600) and the Scientific Revolution (1550-1700). The Enlightenment further transformed intellectual and political life based on the application of science to dramatically alter traditional beliefs and practices. Explore our resourcesforhistoryteachers wiki page to learn more about the Main Ideas of Enlightenment Thinkers. Enlightenment thinkers believed that rational reasoning could apply to all forms of human activity. Their writing can be "broadly understood to stand for the claim that all individuals have the right to Building Democracy for All 2 share their own ends for themselves rather than let others do it for them" (Pagden, 2013, p. x). Politically, they asked what was the proper relationship of the citizen to the monarch or the state. They held that society existed as a contract between individuals and some larger political entity. They advanced the idea of freedom and equality before the law. Enlightenment ideas about how governments should be organized and function influenced both the American and French Revolutions.
    [Show full text]
  • Mary Wollstonecraft and the French Revolution
    International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Vol. 2 No. 9; May 2012 The Roots of Modern Feminism: Mary Wollstonecraft and the French Revolution Dr. Fatih Duman Hitit University Department of Politics Turkey Abstract Mary Wollstonecraft (1759-1797), attributing a particular importance to “woman” -in the narrow sense- and to all oppressed groups -in the broad sense-, has a peculiar position in the history of political thoughts. Taking a position different from the modern male thinkers in her era, she expanded such ideas as “reason”, “natural rights”, “social contract” towards relations between genders and patriarchal authority of the family. These ideas of Wollstonecraft, who applied basic arguments of Enlightenment to the family, woman and private sphere, have constituted the foundation of modern feminism. Wollstonecraft produced classical writings that integrated political theory with gender roles and private relations. In this sense, relations that she made among freedom, equality, virtue, reason and genders and her criticism towards the societies of her era are important. The present study that has focused on Wollstonecraft’s perception about “woman” and her thoughts about the French Revolution will investigate the topic in three basic phases. The first phase will try to present her methodological point of view and her basic thoughts by moving from her book “A Vindication of the Rights of Men (1790)”. The second phase will investigate the concepts and analysis that cover basic arguments of the modern feminist thought by focusing on her book “A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792)”. The third and the final phase will discuss the results of Wollstonecraft’s basic concepts on political theory, especially in relation with the French Revolution where these concepts have been expressed.
    [Show full text]
  • The Misunderstood Philosophy of Thomas Paine
    THE MISUNDERSTOOD PHILOSOPHY OF THOMAS PAINE A Thesis Presented to The Graduate Faculty of The University of Akron In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of History Jason Kinsel December, 2015 THE MISUNDERSTOOD PHILOSOPHY OF THOMAS PAINE Jason Kinsel Thesis Approved: Accepted: ______________________________ _____________________________ Advisor Dean of the College Dr. Walter Hixson Dr. Chand Midha ______________________________ ______________________________ Faculty Reader Dean of the Graduate School Dr. Martino-Trutor Dr. Chand Midha ______________________________ ______________________________ Department Chair Date Dr. Martin Wainwright ii ABSTRACT The name Thomas Paine is often associated with his political pamphlet Common Sense. The importance of “Common Sense” in regards to the American Revolution has been researched and debated by historians, political scientists, and literary scholars. While they acknowledge that Paine’s ideas and writing style helped to popularize the idea of separation from Great Britain in 1776, a thorough analysis of the entirety of Paine’s philosophy has yet to be completed. Modern scholars have had great difficulty with categorizing works such as, The Rights of Man, Agrarian Justice, and Paine’s Dissertation on First Principles of Government. Ultimately, these scholars feel most comfortable with associating Paine with the English philosopher John Locke. This thesis will show that Paine developed a unique political philosophy that is not only different from Locke’s in style, but fundamentally opposed to the system of government designed by Locke in his Second Treatise of Government. Furthermore, I will provide evidence that Paine’s contemporary’s in the American Colonies and Great Britain vehemently denied that Paine’s ideas resembled those of Locke in any way.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Modern Women Philosophers and the History of Philosophy
    Early Modern Women Philosophers and the History of Philosophy EILEEN O’NEILL It has now been more than a dozen years since the Eastern Division of the APA invited me to give an address on what was then a rather innovative topic: the published contributions of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century women to philosophy.1 In that address, I highlighted the work of some sixty early modern women. I then said to the audience, “Why have I presented this somewhat interesting, but nonetheless exhausting . overview of seventeenth- and eigh- teenth-century women philosophers? Quite simply, to overwhelm you with the presence of women in early modern philosophy. It is only in this way that the problem of women’s virtually complete absence in contemporary histories of philosophy becomes pressing, mind-boggling, possibly scandalous.” My presen- tation had attempted to indicate the quantity and scope of women’s published philosophical writing. It had also suggested that an acknowledgment of their contributions was evidenced by the representation of their work in the scholarly journals of the period and by the numerous editions and translations of their texts that continued to appear into the nineteenth century. But what about the status of these women in the histories of philosophy? Had they ever been well represented within the histories written before the twentieth century? In the second part of my address, I noted that in the seventeenth century Gilles Menages, Jean de La Forge, and Marguerite Buffet produced doxogra- phies of women philosophers, and that one of the most widely read histories of philosophy, that by Thomas Stanley, contained a discussion of twenty-four women philosophers of the ancient world.
    [Show full text]
  • The Seneca Falls Convention
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Archivo Digital para la Docencia y la Investigación END OF DEGREE PROJECT THE ORIGINS OF WOMEN’S RIGHTS MOVEMENT IN THE UNITED STATES: THE SENECA FALLS CONVENTION Anne Ruiz Ulloa Translation & Interpreting 2018-2019 Supervisor: Jose Mª Portillo Valdés Department of Contemporary History Abstract: In the 19th century, women had very limited or almost inexistent rights. They lived in a male dominated world where they had restricted access to many fields and they were considered to be an ornament of their husband in public life, and as a domestic agent to the interior of the family, as the Spanish contemporary expression ángel del hogar denotes. In the eyes of the law, they were civilly dead. They were considered fragile and delicate, because they were dependent on a man from birth to death. Tired of being considered less than their male companions, a women’s rights movement emerged in the small town of Seneca Falls, New York, in 1848. Women gathered for the first time in history at the Wesleyan Chapel to discuss women’s rights and to find a solution to the denigration they had suffered by men and society during the years. Around 300 people gathered in Seneca Falls, both men and women. As an attempt to amend the wrongs of men, these women created the Declaration of Rights and Sentiments, a document based on the Declaration of Independence, expressing their discontent with how the society had treated them and asking for a change and equal rights, among which there was the right for suffrage.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes to Chapter 1: Gender, Class and Cultural Revolution 1. on Cultural Revolution and State Formation, See Philip Corrigan
    Notes Notes to Chapter 1: Gender, Class and Cultural Revolution 1. On cultural revolution and state formation, see Philip Corrigan and Derek Sayer, The Great Arch: English State Formation as Cultural Revol­ ution (Oxford and New York: Basil Blackwell, 1985); on revolutionary elites and state formation, see Theda Skocpol, States and Social Revol­ utions: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia, and China (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); on culture, domination, and resist­ ance, see Joan Cocks, The Oppositional Imagination : Feminism, Critique and Political Theory (London and New York: Routledge, 1989) chs 1-3. 2. Philippa Levine, Victorian Feminism , 1850-1900 (London: Hutchinson, 1987) p. 14. 3. See, for example, Anne M. Haselkom and Betty Travitsky (eds), The Renaissance Englishwoman in Print: Counterbalancing theCanon (Amherst, Mass. : University of Massachusetts Press, 1990); Elaine Hobby, Virtue of Necessity: English Women's Writing, 1649-88 (London: Virago Press, 1988); Katharine M. Rogers, Feminism in Eighteenth-Century England (Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press; Urbana, Ill.: University of Illinois Press, 1982); Alice Browne, The Eighteenth-Century Feminist Mind (De­ troit, Mich.: Wayne State University Press, 1987). 4. Mary Poovey, The Proper LAdy and theWoman Writer: Ideology as Style in the WorksofMary Wollstonecraft, Mary Shelley, andJane Austen (Chicago, Ill. and London: University of Chicago Press, 1984) ch. 1. 5. For a review of the problems of definition and a survey of accounts of class in this period, see R. J. Morris, Class and Class Consciousness in the Industrial Revolution, 1780-1850 (London : Macmillan, 1979); for a broader treatment, see R. S. Neale, Class in English History, 1680-1850 (Oxford : Basil Blackwell, 1981).
    [Show full text]
  • Rousseau As a Philosopher of Enlightenment and the Equality of Sophie and Émile Regarding Education
    The European Journal of Social and Behavioural Sciences EJSBS Volume III (e-ISSN: 2301-2218) ROUSSEAU AS A PHILOSOPHER OF ENLIGHTENMENT AND THE EQUALITY OF SOPHIE AND ÉMILE REGARDING EDUCATION Kamuran Godeleka* a Çağ University, Yaşar Bayboğan Campus,Tarsus, Yenice 33800, Mersin, Turkey Abstract J.J. Rousseau, while being an Enlightenment philosopher, is also known with his criticisms to the Enlightenment movement and basic ideas of modern philosophy. Rousseau, by rehashing the discussions brought upon by Descartes and his successors in the 18. century, pursued a social and political philosophy centered on the concepts of self and freedom. As the most controversial and paradoxical of the writers of the Enlightenment, Rousseau rejects both the Cartesian views, which reduces animals to a machine, a mere automaton with no feelings and also Ancient theses, which find the essence of humanity in the possession of reason. According to Rousseau, a human being defines oneself with both the power to squirm oneself out of the instinctual preprogramming, which means freedom, and also the power to have a history which has a priori, indefinite development. This human conception of Rousseau forms the foundation for not only for ethics but also for the politics and social life. Since, in the humanistic philosophy of Rousseau, human nature is not preprogrammed and there does not exist a single natural or social program that could compass a human being, each human being is free, who moves forward towards uncertainty and who has never been preprogrammed by the determinants related to race or gender. Rousseau argues that people who are educated according to the rules exerted by others, cannot be free; he outlines the main tenets of a freeing and perfective education in his influential work Emile with regard to the education of a boy named Emile.
    [Show full text]