Roots and Role of the Imagination in Kant: Imagination at the Core Michael Thompson University of South Florida

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Roots and Role of the Imagination in Kant: Imagination at the Core Michael Thompson University of South Florida University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 3-9-2009 Roots and Role of the Imagination in Kant: Imagination at the Core Michael Thompson University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons Scholar Commons Citation Thompson, Michael, "Roots and Role of the Imagination in Kant: Imagination at the Core" (2009). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/50 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Roots and Role of the Imagination in Kant: Imagination at the Core by Michael Thompson A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Martin Schönfeld Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Sidney Axinn, Ph.D. Charles Guignon, Ph.D. Date of Approval: March 9, 2009 Keywords: Deduction, Logic, A priori, Space, Time © Copyright 2009, Michael Thompson Table of Contents Abstract iii Introduction 1 Chapter One: Problematics 5 The Problem of the Imagination 5 The Problem of Kant Studies 15 Methodology 17 Generalist Narratives 23 Chapter Two: Imagination in Greek Philosophy 35 Promethean Imaginings 35 Plato 37 Aristotle 49 Chapter Three: Imagination in the Middle Ages and Renaissance 70 Transition from Greek to Medieval 70 St. Augustine of Hippo 76 St. Thomas Aquinas 94 Chapter Four: Imagination in Early Modern Philosophy 108 Transition from Medieval to Modern 108 The Renaissance- Pico della Mirandolla 112 Descartes 117 D. Locke and Hume 144 Chapter Five: Imagination in Kant‟s Architectonic 162 Kantian Concerns 162 Kant‟s Concern 173 Chapter Six: Imagination in the Transcendental Deduction 178 The A-deduction 178 Reactions to the Deduction 198 i Chapter Seven: An Integrative Proposal for a New Deduction 206 A New Deduction: Objective Validity 206 Schematism: Objective Reality 218 From A to B 224 Critics and Defenders 237 Chapter Eight: Is the Imagination a Faculty, One or Two? 257 Chapter Nine: Imagination and Error Production 273 Principled Error Production 273 Summary of 1st Critique 290 Chapter Ten: Implications and Integration I: Imagination in the Critique of Practical Reason 296 Chapter Eleven: Implications and integration II: Imagination in the Critique of Judgment 320 Conclusion 343 Works Cited 346 About the Author ` End Page ii Roots and Role of the Imagination in Kant: Imagination at the Core Michael Thompson ABSTRACT Kant‟s critical philosophy promises to overturn both Empiricism and Rationalism by arguing for the necessity of a passive faculty, sensibility, and an active faculty, understanding, in order for cognition to obtain. Kant argues in favor of sense impression found in standard empirical philosophies while advocating conceptual necessities like those found in rational philosophies. It is only in the synthesis of these two elements that cognition and knowledge claims are possible. However, by affirming such a dualism, Kant has created yet another problem familiar to the history of philosophy, one of faculty interaction. By affirming two separate and exclusive capacities necessary for cognition, Kant has bridged the gap between the two philosophical traditions, but created a gap that must be overcome in order to affirm his positive programmatic. Kant himself realizes the difficulty his new philosophy faces when he claims the two sources of knowledge must have a “common, but unknown root.” To complete Kant‟s program one must ask: “What bridges the gap between sensible intuition and conceptual understanding?” In my dissertation, I turn to Kant‟s philosophy and find the answer to this question in the productive imagination. In order to evaluate the viability of this answer, I iii problematize the imagination as it has been found in the history of Western philosophy. By tracing the historical use of the imagination in archetypal figures from both empiricist and rationalist traditions, one finds a development of imagination that culminates in the fundamental formulation found in Kant‟s Critique of Pure Reason. In his critical philosophy, Kant synthesizes the imagination (Einbildungskraft) and the use of imagination found in both traditions, thus demonstrating its role in both sensation and understanding. By employing the imagination at both sensorial and conceptual levels, Kant has found, I argue, the liaison that overcomes the dualism established by his requirements for knowledge, as well as the common root for both. iv Introduction Due to technical vocabulary, complexity of thought and overall intricacy of Kant‟s philosophical position, isolating any one element of his cognitive apparatus in order to make clear its function, status, role and employment in cognition presents an interpreter with a number of challenges. For example, isolating sensibility from the rest of the cognitive structures e.g. the understanding and reason, and determining its constituent role in knowledge production appears to be nearly impossible if not entirely so. How can one understand this element without reference to its counterpart, and, furthermore, how can one clearly determine its role in cognition without the contraposing faculty with which it combines in knowledge production? By focusing on one element in Kant‟s philosophy, one runs the risk of failing to illustrate said element‟s proper place in Kant‟s critical philosophy. And yet, one cannot understand Kant‟s philosophy without providing an analytic of the elements by which one can isolate constitutive parts and determine them in their interactions. For this essay, I would like to propose that an isolation of one element is not only possible, but also necessary in an interpretation, defense and emendation of Kant‟s critical works. By focusing on the imagination, one will be able, I argue, to interpret and defend Kant‟s critical evaluation of scientific, metaphysical, practical and aesthetic knowledge. Knowledge is, according to Kant, a synthesis of two 1 separate and heterogeneous faculties, sensibility and understanding. With such a formulation, Kant must present an explanation for how two such disparate faculties can be synthesized. The imagination, I contend, is just such a liaison between sensibility and understanding. My intent here is to focus on the imagination in order to gain greater insight on this “blind but indispensible function” as well as to defend Kant‟s description and prescription for knowledge claims. Moreover, by focusing on the imagination one is able to further illustrate central doctrines of Kant‟s critical philosophy. Describing the functions of other faculties as well as the origin and development of their products is one such chief concern. By defining knowledge as a synthesis of the products of sensibility and the understanding, intuitions and concepts respectively, Kant presents himself and the reader with a considerable dualism. Sensibility has its own processes and products separate from understanding. So too does the understanding have its own processes and products removed from the influence of sensibility. By bifurcating knowledge production between two separate faculties, Kant resurrects and defends a doctrine that will reconcile the passivity of empirical sensation with the activity, spontaneity, of intellectual processes involved in understanding. But such a dualism presents Kant with a number of problems: What are the origins of the products of both capacities, that is, what is the source for the elemental factors involved in the separate faculties, what do they have in common, and what ensures the correct applicability of concepts to intuitions, in short, their objective validity? If they are mutually exclusive faculties and their products are radically different, how can such a synthesis come about, and 2 what applicability do we find in human experience, in short, their objective reality? Kant must address not only the sources and the correctness of the products of the faculties, but he must also demonstrate that they are connected in application and use in knowledge claims. By turning to the imagination, I hope to present a coherent interpretation and defense of this central doctrine of Kant‟s critical works, but also to gain insight into this overlooked and often marginalized, but necessary, capacity of human cognition. Rather than approaching this topic through the regular means—by examining the arguments found in the Transcendental Deduction of the 1st Critique, an approach most Anglo-American Kant scholars pursue—I prefer to examine the imagination in several of Kant‟s works. The Anglo-American debate has combined to present a standard interpretation, one which posits Kant‟s pure concepts, categories, as having no explanation other than his assumption and emendation of Aristotle‟s categories in conjunction with a table of logical judgments. To combat this interpretation, I would like to center the focus of this protracted debate around the use Kant makes of the imagination. The mediating capacity of the imagination, between sensibility and understanding, is a provocative suggestion Kant himself makes, one to which non- Anglo-American philosophers only occasionally attend and Anglo-American interpreters
Recommended publications
  • JTE-2010-Netzer
    Journal of Transformative Education http://jtd.sagepub.com/ Inquiry into Creative and Innovative Processes: An Experiential, Whole-Person Approach to Teaching Creativity Dorit Netzer and Nancy Mangano Rowe Journal of Transformative Education 2010 8: 124 DOI: 10.1177/1541344611406905 The online version of this article can be found at: http://jtd.sagepub.com/content/8/2/124 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com Additional services and information for Journal of Transformative Education can be found at: Email Alerts: http://jtd.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://jtd.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations: http://jtd.sagepub.com/content/8/2/124.refs.html Downloaded from jtd.sagepub.com at INST OF TRANSPERSONAL PSYCH on June 30, 2011 Journal of Transformative Education 8(2) 124-145 ª The Author(s) 2010 Inquiry into Reprints and permission: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1541344611406905 Creative and http://jted.sagepub.com Innovative Processes: An Experiential, Whole-Person Approach to Teaching Creativity Dorit Netzer1 and Nancy Mangano Rowe1 Abstract This article highlights the transformative nature of an online master’s level course titled, Inquiry into Creative and Innovative Processes. The authors emphasize the importance of whole-person, imaginative, and intuitive experiences in adult stu- dents’ unique, scholarly development. They describe their process of adapting intuitive inquiry,atranspersonalresearchmethod,as a supportive structure for this online course on creativity. A creative and innovative approach to teaching in itself, the course facilitated a flexible learningcontainer,wherestudentswereguided toward integrating their academic learning and personal discovery in embodied and deeply conscious ways.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Investigation of Principlism and the Implications Raised by the Treatment of the Mentally Ill
    Aporia vol. 24 no. 1—2014 A Philosophical Investigation of Principlism and the Implications Raised by the Treatment of the Mentally Ill BENJAMIN FOSTER Introduction he objective of this investigation is to identify reasonable and relevant problems and issues posed for Principlism by the mentally T ill. Two concepts of Principlism will be presented: a normative con- ceptualization of the bioethical theory and a descriptive conceptualization. In reference to both, two philosophical questions will be asked: can we know the natures of other minds and, if so, how? These two questions have theoretical and practical implications for the treatment of the mentally ill. And, in so far as the questions have implications for the treatment of the mentally ill, they have implications for the bioethical theory of Principlism. There is a lack of concurrence on the meaning, nature, and function of mental phenomena, producing conceptual difficulties concerning the common morality that provides Principlism its normative authority. Similarly, a contradiction appears to arise when one considers the imaginative leap of predicting another’s desires, feelings, and thoughts, a maneuver that professionals participating in the treatment of the mentally ill must perform. There is also significant ambiguity surrounding the concept of mental illness, which produces pragmatic problems when professionals attempt to diagnose and treat an individual in conjunction Benjamin Foster graduated with a degree in philosophy and a minor in biology from the University of Alaska Fairbanks. While there he served as president of the univer- sity’s philosophy club, The Socratic Society. His primary philosophical interests include ethics and epistemology. He currently plans to attend medical school.
    [Show full text]
  • Barriers to Creativity in Engineering Education: a Study of Instructors and Students Perceptions
    See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/245366675 Barriers to Creativity in Engineering Education: A Study of Instructors and Students Perceptions Article in Journal of Mechanical Design · July 2007 DOI: 10.1115/1.2739569 CITATIONS READS 158 2,294 2 authors, including: Kazem Kazerounian University of Connecticut 69 PUBLICATIONS 938 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: Systematic Design and Analysis of Artificial Molecular Machines View project All content following this page was uploaded by Kazem Kazerounian on 21 September 2015. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. Barriers to Creativity in Engineering Education: A Study of Instructors and Students Kazem Kazerounian Professor Fellow ASME Perceptions Stephany Foley This paper studies “creativity” in engineering education, by examining the perception of NSF Graduate Fellow instructors and students. We aim to identify factors that impede a creative environment (creativity blockers). The study entails a review of established research in the fields of Department of Mechanical Engineering, psychology and educational psychology to identify factors which create an educational University of Connecticut, environment conducive to creativity. These factors are formalized in the Ten Maxims of Storrs, CT 06269-3139 Creativity in Education, a set of criteria that constitute an educational environment conducive to fostering creativity in students. These maxims form the basis for our work in examining the contemporary engineering education. Extensive surveys are designed, cre- ated, distributed, and statistically quantified to study the perceptions of engineering edu- cators and students, in comparison to nonengineering educators and students.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Objects After Deleuze
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School March 2021 Hume's Objects After Deleuze Michael P. Harter Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Harter, Michael P., "Hume's Objects After Deleuze" (2021). LSU Master's Theses. 5305. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/5305 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUME’S OBJECTS AFTER DELEUZE A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Michael Patrick Harter B.A., California State University, Fresno, 2018 May 2021 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Human beings are wholly dependent creatures. In our becoming, we are affected by an incredible number of beings who aid and foster our growth. It would be impossible to devise a list of all such individuals. However, those who played imperative roles in the creation of this work deserve their due recognition. First, I would like to thank my partner, Leena, and our pets Merleau and the late Kiki. Throughout the ebbs and flows of my academic career, you have remained sources of love, joy, encouragement, and calm.
    [Show full text]
  • Dance Into the Unknown. a Heuristic Inquiry
    Dance into the unknown. A heuristic inquiry. Jane Christophers A dissertation submitted to Auckland University of Technology in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Psychotherapy Department of Psychotherapy Auckland University of Technology Supervisor: Dr Margot Solomon 2019 i Table of Contents Table of Contents ............................................................................................................... i List of Figures .................................................................................................................. iii Attestation of authorship .................................................................................................. iv Acknowledgements ........................................................................................................... v Abstract ............................................................................................................................ vi Chapter One: Introduction................................................................................................. 1 Dancing in the bush .................................................................................................................. 1 Salire – To leap ......................................................................................................................... 2 Dance and movement ................................................................................................................ 2 5Rhythms dance – Inviting spirit .............................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Holism and Compositionality
    Holism and Compositionality Francis Jeffry Pelletier 1 Introduction A brief acquaintance with the web shows that the terms ‘holism’1 and ‘compositionality’ are used in many different fields, both academic and non-academic. And given any two academic fields, it is usually not obvious that the terms mean the same to the practitioners. Even just within philosophy and linguistics it seems that rather different conceptions are in play when we read any two different authors. We start, therefore, with a brief survey of some of the senses in which these terms are used. A little later we will make some more careful remarks about the notions. 1.1 Two Kinds of Compositionality A recent interdisciplinary conference revealed that there are (at least) two different things that are thought of when the issue of compositionality is considered. One concerns a (generalized) notion of “what is a complex item (of my theory) made of?” Here are a few places where this notion arose: Prototypes: Current prototype theory says that a prototype is a structure that has a number of attribute-value pairs. A question of interest in this area is: Given that prototype-1 has a structure [A: value-a; B: value-b; . ] and that prototype-2 has the structure [C: value-c; D: value-d . ], is the prototype of the “combined prototypes” (that is, the conceptual combination of the two proto- types) made up only from the material in the two component prototypes, that is, from the attribute-value pairs that are in one or the other of the prototypes? 1 ‘Whole’, and presumably also ’hole’, is derived from the Greek .
    [Show full text]
  • Creativity in the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead
    CREATIVITY IN WIDTEHEAD'S l\1ETAPHYSICS CREATIVITY IN THE METAPHYSICS OF ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD By JEFFREY A. MCPHERSON, B.A.(Hons.) A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts © Copyright by Jeffrey A. McPherson, SEPTEMBER, 1996 MASTER OF ARTS (1996) McMaster University (Religious Studies) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Creativity in the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead. AUTHOR: Jeffrey A. McPherson, B.A.(Hons.) (York University) SUPERVISOR: Dr. J.C. Robertson, Jr. NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 127 ii ABSTRACT This is a study of the role that creativity plays in the metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead ( 1861-1947). As the title generally indicates, there are two parts to this project. The first part develops an understanding of Whitehead's metaphysics through the careful analysis of two key texts, namely Religion in the Making ( 1926), and Process and Reality (1929). The second part examines and carefully analyses the role that creativity plays within this metaphysic. The second part focuses on two questions. The first question considers the ontological status which creativity requires to perform the role which it is given within the metaphysical system. The second question discusses implications of this status for creativity's relationship to God. This second section further discusses the implications of such an understanding of "process theology" for Christian theology in general. Specifically it comments on the various responses of theology to creatio ex nihilo and the problem of evil. This thesis concludes that creativity functions as an ultimate explanatory principle in Whitehead's metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • COGS 101B Slides Outline History Descartes
    COGS 101B Slides • Web Page • PDF version of Powerpoint slides available – http://www.cogsci.ucsd.edu/~coulson/101b/ on the course website • Instructor http://www.cogsci.ucsd.edu/~coulson/101b/ – Dr. Coulson – Email: coulson “at” cogsci.ucsd.edu – CSB 161 – Thursday: 12-2pm •TAs – Alan Robinson – Nate Harrison – Zack Weinberg Outline History •History • Philosophical Origins • Methods • Structuralism • Paradigms • Functionalism • Gestalt Psychology • Genetic Epistemology • Behaviorism • Cognitive Revolution Descartes • Epistemology • Radical Skepticism • Evil Demon • “Cogito ergo sum.” • Leap of Faith 1 Premises & Problems Rationalism vs. Empiricism Kant Locke, Hume • Knowledge begins • All knowledge originates Physical Neural Mental w/experience but is in experience Energy Activity Experience constructed by mind • Mind is a blank slate • Experience mediated by mental categories or qualia – “raw feels”, raises problem of how to relate physical schemata facts to mental facts Structuralism • Philosophical Motivation – Belief in reductionism – Consciousness can be broken down into basic elements • Goal – Discover basic structures of mental life • Methodology – Introspection Wundt Titchener • Founded first • Took introspection to new experimental psychology level laboratory • “Tell me your sensations • Not just sensations but of this rock” thoughts • BUT: Also did lots of • Tell me your reactions to psychophysics “green things” • Most introspection was people saying “yes” or • Unfortunately, “no” to targeted questions inconsistencies about
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Model of Causality: Causal Powers, Laws, and Kant's Reply to Hume
    KANT’ S MODEL OF CAUSALITY 449 Kant’s Model of Causality: Causal Powers, Laws, and Kant’s Reply to Hume ERIC WATKINS* KANT’S VIEWS ON CAUSALITY have received an extraordinary amount of scholarly at- tention, especially in comparison with Hume’s position. For Hume presents pow- erful skeptical arguments concerning causality, yet Kant claims to have an ad- equate response to them. Since it turns out to be far from obvious what even the main lines of Kant’s response are, scholars have felt the need to clarify his posi- tion. Unfortunately, however, no consensus has been reached about how best to understand Kant’s views. To gauge the current state of the debate, consider briefly Hume’s two-fold skeptical attack on causality in his Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding and what strategy Kant is often thought to be pursuing in response in the Critique of Pure Reason.1 1 Hume’s fuller views on causality are naturally more complex than the brief summary provided below indicates. For more comprehensive discussions, see, e.g., Barry Stroud, Hume (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), John Wright, The Sceptical Realism of David Hume (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983), Richard Fogelin, Hume’s Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985), Galen Strawson, The Secret Connexion: Causation, Realism, and David Hume (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), Ken Winkler, “The New Hume,” Philosophical Review 100 (1991): 541–79, and Don Garrett “The Representation of Causation and Hume’s Two Defini- tions of ‘Cause’,” Nous 27 (1993): 167–90.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to the Special Topic Section on Arts and Consciousness Dorit Netzer Hofstra University
    International Journal of Transpersonal Studies Volume 34 Article 8 Iss. 1-2 (2015) 1-1-2015 Introduction to the Special Topic Section on Arts and Consciousness Dorit Netzer Hofstra University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.ciis.edu/ijts-transpersonalstudies Part of the Art Practice Commons, Philosophy Commons, Psychology Commons, and the Religion Commons Recommended Citation Netzer, D. (2015). Netzer, D. (2015). Introduction to the special topic section on arts and consciousness. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 34(1-2), 65–69.. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 34 (1). http://dx.doi.org/10.24972/ ijts.2015.34.1-2.65 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. This Special Topic Introduction is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals and Newsletters at Digital Commons @ CIIS. It has been accepted for inclusion in International Journal of Transpersonal Studies by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ CIIS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Introduction to the Special Topic Section on Arts and Consciousness Dorit Netzer Hofstra University Hempstead, NY he arts have traditionally served a wide range of Culture and International Development (2015) is cogently social functions, from the utilitarian, political, reviewed by Judy Schavrien (p. 214), eloquently said: and entertaining, to the sacred, ritualistic, and The imaginary is not simply fantasy, although Treligious. As such, the arts have always been an integral fantasy plays a very important part in our emotional vehicle of transpersonal development, by uncovering and psychic lives as attested by many cultural forms the unconscious and raising consciousness, preserving from fairy tales and myths or utopias and science cultures, and propelling global transformation.
    [Show full text]
  • HTT Introduction
    1 The Transcendental Turn Sebastian Gardner Kant's influence on the history of philosophy is vast and protean. The transcendental turn denotes one of its most important forms, defined by the notion that Kant's deepest insight should not be identified with any specific epistemological or metaphysical doctrine, but rather concerns the fundamental standpoint and terms of reference of philosophical enquiry. To take the transcendental turn is not to endorse any of Kant's specific teachings, but to accept that the Copernican revolution announced in the Preface of the Critique of Pure Reason sets philosophy on a new footing and constitutes the proper starting point of philosophical reflection. The question of what precisely defines the transcendental standpoint has both historical and systematic aspects. It can be asked, on the one hand, what different construals have been put on Kant's Copernican revolution and what different historical forms the transcendental project has assumed, and on the other, how transcendental philosophy, in abstraction from its historical instances, should be defined and practised. Though separable, the two questions are best taken together. In so far as historical interest has a critical dimension, it will constantly broach systematic issues, just as any convincing account of the nature of transcendental philosophy will need to take account of the historical development. The present volume examines the history of the transcendental turn with the dual aim of elucidating the thought of individual philosophers, and of bringing into clearer view the existence of a transcendental tradition, intertwined with but distinguishable from other, more configurations in late modern philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant – Transcendental Idealism
    Kant – Transcendental Idealism In the wake of Hume, it seemed that philosophy was over (“commit it to the flames”) and science was ultimately unjustified (there is no rational justification for believing that facts about observed spaces and times entails anything about unobserved spaces/times). Further, it seems that Reid missed the point of Hume’s arguments. OF COURSE we have to ASSUME that there ARE external objects, and that there IS regularity in the world, etc., before we may proceed with our inquiries. Hume’s point was only that these starting assumptions (these “first principles” of “common sense”) are ultimately unjustified. But, “common sense must be shown practically, by well-considered and reasonable thoughts and words, not by appealing to it as an oracle, when no rational justification can be advanced.” (Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics) Kant is going to try to rescue both philosophy and science. 1. Step One: Synthetic A Priori Knowledge: Consider two distinctions: (a) A priori knowledge – Knowledge gained independent of sensory experience; or “from the armchair”, so to speak, based on “pure reason”. (b) Empirical (a posteriori) knowledge – knowledge gained by sensory experience. (i) Analytic truths – Truths where the predicate is contained in the subject; i.e., truths that are true by definition. (ii) Synthetic truths – Truths that are NOT true by definition. (The predicate adds something NEW to the subject.) Hume mistakenly believed that (a)/(i) and (b)/(ii) were really just the same categories: analytic/a priori. You can know that an analytic truth such as <All triangles have three sides> is true without needing to go out into the world and verify by checking every triangle to make sure that it is three-sided.
    [Show full text]