LYSANDER and the a THEN IAN CIVIL WAR (HELLEN/CA II.Iii.11-11.Iv)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

LYSANDER and the a THEN IAN CIVIL WAR (HELLEN/CA II.Iii.11-11.Iv) CHAPTER FIVE LYSANDER AND THE A THEN IAN CIVIL WAR (HELLEN/CA II.iii.11-11.iv) Whereas the event narrated in Hellenica 11.ii.23 appeared to conclude the war of the Peloponnesians and the Athenians according to the express designation of Thucydides (V.26), Xenophon seems to suggest that the ominous return of Lysander to Sparta is the truer conclusion of that war; for his account of that homecoming is followed by an annalistic ending according to the style of Thucydides (Hell. Il.iii.9-10). Even if this passage be rejected on suspicion of its being an interpolation by a later hand, the event itself, the return home of the last of the warring troops and the victorious commander, seems to common sense to put the final period to the narrative of the war. But this expectation, too, is belied when Xenophon proceeds straightway, again without editorial comment, with words implying that there can be no separating the events by which Thucydides defined the end of a distinct "motion" in human affairs from the events caused by those events: "Now the Thirty were chosen as soon as ( l1tti 'tlXXL<na) the Long Walls and those around the Peiraeus had been torn down .... " (iii.11; cf. again Thuc. V.26.1.) Thus the Athenian sequel begins just where the concluding events of the war began (iii.2-3). Xenophon perhaps indicates in this way that one can understand the war apart from its consequences as little as Thucydides could have begun his own writing at the beginning of Book II (and we might add: as little as one could justly end an account of the Second World War at the sur­ render of Germany and Japan). While the concluding narrative of the war had to do mainly with Lysander's activities before leaving Athens, in Samos, and returning to Sparta (iii.1-10), the sequel focuses on the rise and fall of the Thirty oligarchs1 in Athens (iii.ll-iv.43). But we soon find that Lysander has an important part in the latter, too, not only in having effected their appointment as legislators but also in supporting their tyrannic ambitions and in nearly providing for their victory over the people. Apart from whatever other purpose Xenophon's narration of the oligarchy and civil war in Athens might have (perhaps as part of a general treatment of Athenian politics together with I. iv .8-20, v .16-17, vii.1-35 and other 1 They are usually called the Thirty tyrants, but I have tried to reflect Xenophon's implicit suggestion that their rule at first was more aristocratic and then degenerated into tyranny. "Oligarchy" is a neutral term (see e.g., II.iii.47-48). LYSANDER AND THE ATHENIAN CIVIL WAR 81 Athenian passages in the first two books), it may also exemplify both the behavior and the difficult position of Lysander vis-a-vis the Spartan authorities in his support of the oligarchies he helped to establish in many other of the Greek cities besides Samos ( cf. III. iv. 2, v. 13). 2 Lysander assists the oligarchs on two occasions. The first is not long after their appointment, just at their turning from the popularly accepted murder of the sycophants toward more tyrannic designs (Il.iii.12-13). At this time they still conceal their design even from Lysander, telling him that they need a garrison ''just, of course (81i), until they should put the scoundrels out of the way and establish the regime . " (iii.13). Lysander uses his influence ( exactly how, we are not told) to obtain this garrison and in addition, although it was apparently not requested, a Spartan harmost over Athens ( iii .14). The oligarchs immediately begin to put this force to nefarious uses: ... they arrested whom they wished, no longer those who were scoundrels and of little worth but already those who they thought least tolerated being brushed aside and who, making any attempt to act in opposition, would obtain the most associates. (iii.14) They soon learn, however, that this is only increasing the numbers and organization of their enemies, and so begin to apply their principles more consistently by employing the Spartan garrison along with their trusted accomplices to disarm all but their newly appointed body of Three Thou­ sand "partners" (iii.17-20). Some of the worst excesses that follow are occasioned by their need for money to give to the garrison (iii. 21- merely for its "support" or "victualing," per iii.13?). When the last remaining barrier to those domestic excesses, Theramenes, has been eliminated (iii.22-56) and the tyrants have exiled large numbers from the city, the Laconian garrison is sent out with some of the Athenian cavalry to guard against plundering raids by the exiles who hold the fortress of Phyle; caught in a surprise attack by Thrasybulus, more than 120 of the hoplites are slain (II. iv .1-7). The Thirty thereupon employ a ruse to seize and bind the Eleusinians one by one in order to have that town as a refuge if necessary. To secure the complicity of the Three Thousand in the murder of these Eleusinians, i.e. to insure their loyalty through fear of common punishment, the tyrants frighten the reluctant into voting for 2 Gaston Colin compares Xenophon's narrative in these chapters with the accounts of Aristotle (in the Constitution of the Athenians), Diodorus, and others, and finds Xenophon sadly wanting in plausibility as a meticulous chronicler: Xenophon historien d'apres le livre II des Helleniques (hiver 406-405 d 401-0) (Paris, 1933). But once again we ask, Did Xenophon intend to be a chronicler? Colin makes some useful observations about the structure of Xenophon's narrative (e.g., p. 43) but passes many judgments against his factual reliability without analyzing that structure in depth. .
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • The Trial of Socrates 399 BCE
    The Trial of Socrates 399 BCE 2 WHY? The trial and execution of Socrates in Athens in 399 B.C.E. puzzles historians What did Socrates say or do that prompted a jury to send a seventy- year-old philosopher to his death? Finding an answer is complicated by the two surviving accounts of the defense They were written by Socrates disciples, Plato and Xenophon Their accounts probably were trying to show their master in a favorable light They failed to present the most damning evidence against Socrates 3 The decisions to prosecute and ultimately convict Socrates had a lot to do with the turbulent history of Athens in the several years preceding his trial An examination of that history may not provide final answers, but it does provide important clues 4 As a young man, Socrates saw the rise to power of Pericles He brought on the dawning of the "Golden Age of Greece." Pericles--perhaps history's first liberal politician-- acted on his belief that the masses deserved liberty Pericles used the public treasury to promote the arts He pushed a building program designed to demonstrate the glory that was Greece It also ensured full employment and opportunities for the lower classes Pericles rebuilt the Acropolis and constructed the Parthenon 5 Parthenon 6 SOCRATES’ BELIEFS Meanwhile, Socrates developed a set of values and beliefs that would put him at odds with most Athenians 7 Socrates was not a democrat To him, the people should not be self-governing They were like a herd of sheep that needed a wise shepherd He denied that citizens had basic virtue
    [Show full text]
  • Today We Examine the Contribupons of Classical, Ancient Greece To
    Today we examine the contribu3ons of classical, ancient Greece to government, both in the championing of democracy and in the development of philosophy to address ques3ons of ethics and jus3ce. Plato, the Greek philosopher who studied under Socrates and who himself taught Aristotle, was one of the first ancient thinkers to ask: what is jus3ce? What is a just society? What is the proper func3on of government and which form of government is the best? 1 During the mid sixth century BCE, the Persian Empire expanded into Asia Minor, eventually conquering Ionia itself and installing tyrants to rule the Ionian city-states on their behalf. One of these tyrants aempted to conquer the island of Naxos in the Aegean and various Greek city-states, including Athens, helped repulse this invasion. This coali3on of city-states soon began to aid and encourage the Ionians to revolt against their Persian rulers. The revolt was defeated but the Persian ruler decided that Athens and the other Greek city-states must be punished for their role in suppor3ng the revolt. This first Persian invasion was defeated and turned back at the Bale of Marathon (490 BCE). Ten years later, the Persian king Xerxes returned with one of the largest armies ever assembled to complete the subjugaon of the Greeks. Despite early successes and despite vastly outnumbering the Greeks, the Persians under Xerxes were defeated at Salamis and Plataea and control of the Aegean Sea, the Greek Islands and parts of Asia Minor passed to this coali3on of Greek city-states led by Athens and Sparta.
    [Show full text]
  • Stone, Socrates
    I. F. Stone Breaks the Socrates Story An old muckraker sheds fresh light on the 2,500-year-old mystery and reveals some Athenian political realities that Plato did his best to hide. [This interview was originally published in The New and the gymnasiums where they spent much of their leisure. York Times Magazine, April 8, 1979, pp. 22 ff.] Free speech – what the Greeks called parrhasia – was as much On his 70th birthday, in an interview with himself for this taken for granted as breathing. Magazine, retired journalist I. F. Stone spoke of his new- found joy in Greek studies and his hope of finding in them But then I was stopped, or stumped, by this contradictory and “one last scoop” that would help clear up some of the traumatic spectacle of what they did to Socrates. These people mystery which still surrounds the trial of Socrates, that and this city, to which I look back for inspiration – how could cause célèbre which has tantalized scholars and histori- they have condemned this philosopher to death? How could so ans for centuries. Now, he believes he has found new evi- dence that sheds light not only on the trial itself but on the blatant a violation of free speech occur in a city that prided complex politics of fifth-century Athens. Here – again in itself on freedom of inquiry and expression? a self-interview – Mr. Stone sets forth his discovery and, at the same time, takes us on an adventure in learning and But why should we care at this late date? an armchair tour of the ancient world.
    [Show full text]
  • The Pennsylvania State University the Graduate School College of The
    The Pennsylvania State University The Graduate School College of the Liberal Arts ARISTOTELIAN TOPICS FOR PLURALIST DEMOCRACY A Thesis in Communication Arts and Sciences by Adam Cody © 2016 A. W. Cody Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts December 2016 ii The thesis of Adam Cody was reviewed and approved* by the following: Rosa A. Eberly Associate Professor of Communication Arts and Sciences and English Thesis Adviser Stephen H. Browne Professor of Communication Arts and Sciences Michele Kennerly Assistant Professor of Communication Arts and Sciences Denise Haunani Solomon Liberal Arts Research Professor of Communication Arts and Sciences Head of Communication Arts and Sciences *Signatures are on file in the Graduate School. iii ABSTRACT Rhetorical scholars distrust topos theory, fearing that attention to argumentative “spaces” will produce an overly formalized image of rhetoric. This anxiety can be attributed to Aristotle, whose Rhetoric claims that common topoi are preferable to specific topoi as premises for rhetorical argument. By reading Aristotle in conversation with the Athenian civil war (415-403 BCE), rhetorical scholars can recognize this preference as a prescriptive response to Athens’ political history. Three rhetorical texts from the period of civil war display the rhetorical capacity to build toward a position of commonality from one of particularity. The three texts attribute the discord of civil war to this particular-to-common rhetorical mode. Aristotle, attempting to correct the perception that rhetoric necessarily produces civic strife, privileges arguments premised on already existing commonality. Decoupling Aristotle’s preference for common premises from topos theory opens space for rhetorical scholars to address some twenty-first century CE problems in argumentation theory and pluralist democracy.
    [Show full text]
  • UCLA Historical Journal
    UCLA UCLA Historical Journal Title Reasons for the Coup of the Four Hundred Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3mc6m50g Journal UCLA Historical Journal, 6(0) ISSN 0276-864X Author Ellis, Walter Publication Date 1985 eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California 5 NOTES AND DOCUMENTS Reasons for the Coup of the Four Hundred Walter Ellis Introduction The Peloponnesian War (431-404 B.C.) between Athens and Sparta came to a temporary halt during the period between 42 1 and 413. In 4 1 the Athenians, under the influence of Alcibiades, inaugurated an ambitious invasion of the island of Sicily that by 413 had turned into a disaster for the invaders. The Athenians lost thousands of men, most of their navy, and their two leading statesmen, the generals Nicias and Alcibiades. Nicias died in Sicily and Alcibiades defected to the Spartans. Also, in 413 the Spartans formally reopened the war by occupying on a permanent basis the fortress at Decelea which was on the Athenian frontier. Bereft of effective leadership and the greater part of its navy, Athens was on the verge of losing its empire as more and more of its subject allies began to rebel. The foundation upon which Athens' strength was built seemed to be on the verge of collapse. This crisis led directly to a coup in Athens in the year 411; the democracy was overthrown by a group of oligarchs known as the Four Hundred. The Four Hundred held power in Athens for about four months through mid-September before they were replaced by a more moderate oHgarchy known as the Five Thousand.
    [Show full text]
  • F. As Executions and Exiles Accelerate; Theramenes Moves to Set up the 3000, 1
    I. THIRTY TYRANTS (404-403) A. After Aegospotami, Lysander est. Decarchies throughout Aegean; oligarchic puppet states of Sparta; Athens would need a larger governing board => The Thirty, a group of pro-Spartan oligarchs B. Initial Actions of the Thirty 1. abolish organs of dem. govt. under guise of returning to “ancestral constitution”; a) Participation in legal functions — which had previously been open to all Athenians — was restricted to a select group of 500 persons (Boule antidemocrats). b) The Assembly was abolished; c) pay for service abolished; d) suspended Heliaea. 2. request Spartan garrison of 700 + commander; surrounded by 300 whip-bearers; 3. est. informers to watch Piraeus = hotbed of democratic activism C. Leaders = Theramenes and Critias, pupil of Socrates (uncle of Plato) Critias = brilliant intellectual, atheist, passionate antidemocrat; brutal; amoral; banished member of the 400 D. At outset, seemed an enlightened move: Plato was joyful; Aristotle” in Ath. Pol 35.3-4 “At the outset, therefore, they were engaged in ... removing the blackmailers and the persons who consorted undesirably with the people to curry favor and were evil-doers and scoundrels; and the state was delighted at these measures, thinking they were acting with the best intentions... when they got a firmer hold on the state, they kept their hands off none of the citizens, but put to death those of outstanding wealth or birth or reputation... desiring to plunder their estates, and by the end of a brief interval of time they had made away with not less than fifteen hundred.” = at least 2-3% of population. E. The Thirty began a purge of citizens who had collaborated with the Athenians during the Peloponnesian War.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Plato's Apology of Socrates 1. Background A. the Setting
    Sean Hannan The Examined Life Fall 2015 Notes on Plato’s Apology of Socrates 1. Background a. The Setting: Ancient Athens i. ὅτι μὲν ὑμεῖς, ὦ ἄνδρες Ἀθηναῖοι, πεπόνθατε ὑπὸ τῶν ἐμῶν κατηγόρων, οὐκ οἶδα: ἐγὼ δ᾽ οὖν καὶ αὐτὸς ὑπ᾽ αὐτῶν ὀλίγου ἐμαυτοῦ ἐ πελαθόμην, οὕτω πιθανῶς ἔλεγον. ii. Those are the opening words of Plato’s Apology of Socrates, at least in the version of it we have now. For most of us, I’d presume, these words don’t sound terribly familiar. Our ears are not attuned to the Attic dialect spoken by most ancient Athenians. But how ancient was this Athens of Socrates? How far away from us was it, chronologically speaking? And how does that chronological distance relate to the conceptual distance between us and Socrates? In other words: does the length of time between us make it harder for us to get a grip on what these ancient Greek figures were arguing about? iii. Perhaps a brief timeline can help us begin to fathom the number of years we’re talking about here. We’ll work backwards. 1. 2015 CE—Today 2. 1997 CE—Average Freshman’s Birth Year 3. 1969 CE—First Internet Prototype (ARPANet) Goes Online 4. 1939 CE—World War II Breaks Out 5. 1914 CE—World War I Breaks Out 6. 1865 CE—End of the American Civil War 7. 1776 CE—America’s Declaration of Independence 8. 1492 CE—Columbus Crosses the Atlantic 9. 1440 CE—Invention of Printing Press 10. 1000 CE—Leif Erikson Crosses the Atlantic 11.
    [Show full text]
  • Late Classical Period 404 to 338 B.C
    LATE CLASSICAL PERIOD 404 TO 338 B.C. THIRTY TYRANTS IN ATHENS TO BATTLE OF CHAERONEA ERA SUMMARY – LATE CLASSICAL After the defeat of Athens at the end of the Peloponnesian War, Sparta became the undisputed first power among the Greek city-states. The walls of Athens were pulled down and the Spartan general Lysander appointed thirty men who were loyal to Sparta to run the city. The leaders were called the "thirty tyrants" and they put many of their political opponents, including Socrates to death. Plato was a student of Socrates and witnessed these oppressions and they greatly influenced his later writings. The period immediately after the Peloponnesian war is called the "Spartan Hegemony" because, although Sparta did not collect tribute, it allowed only governments which were friendly to Sparta to exist throughout Greece. The major figure of this period was Agesilaus, a brave and noble Spartan king who came very near to freeing all of the Greek Colonies in Asia Minor before he was recalled to deal with a political crisis at home. While Agesilaus was off fighting Persians in the east, the Spartan government had fallen into a great deal of trouble. The spoils from the successful wars had done much to corrupt Sparta; there was intrigue and infighting and wars with Corinth and Thebes. These problems combined with a significantly reduced population led to the disaster the Battle of Leuctra in 371 BC. Only 33 years after they prevailed in the Peloponnesian War, the Spartans suffered a humiliating defeat against Thebes, the first major land battle that the Spartans had lost to another Greek city-state in 500 years.
    [Show full text]
  • Tyrants As Impious Leaders in Xenophon's Hellenica
    Histos Supplement ( ) – TYRANTS AS IMPIOUS LEADERS IN XENOPHON’S HELLENICA * Frances Pownall Abstract : Recent scholarship has drawn attention to the consistent focus throughout Xenophon’s large and disparate body of work upon articulating a very specific set of virtues that define a good leader. I examine the reverse side of this trend in scholarship by identifying the characteristics that Xenophon employs to define bad leaders. I argue that Xenophon deliberately shaped his narrative in the Hellenica to portray egregiously bad leaders as tyrants, focusing in particular upon their impiety, which he presents as the crucial explanatory factor in their downfalls. Appropriating the figure of the evil tyrant from Athenian democratic ideology, he bequeaths to the later Greek historiographical tradition the topos of the impious tyrant. Keywords : Xenophon, tyranny, impiety, the Thirty, Jason of Pherae, Euphron of Sicyon. ecent scholarship has drawn attention to the consistent focus throughout Xenophon’s large and Rdisparate body of work upon identifying and articulating a very specific set of virtues that define a good leader. 1 I intend to examine the reverse side of this recent * I have benefitted from the generous comments and advice of audiences at the > APA meeting in Chicago, at the Department of Classics and Religion at the University of Calgary, and at Philipps Universität in Marburg, as well as from the anonymous reviewers for Histos and the editor. 1 While Xenophon’s theory of leadership has been a topic of interest for scholars since the middle of the twentieth century, beginning with the seminal work of Breitenbach (C ) and Wood (C>), and much of it focusing upon how his own military experience influenced his conception of the ideal leader (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyrighted Material
    04_55977X c01.qxd 5/12/04 11:46 PM Page 1 1Plato’s Life “I am that gadfly which God has given the state and all day long and in all places am always fastening upon you, arousing and per- suading and reproaching you.” —Socrates, Apology Plato has been called, with no exaggeration, the Father of Western Philosophy. Though he hadn’t aspired to such a role, he probably would not have shied away from it. (He was not known for his humility.) Like many other great figures in his- tory, Plato came to play the role he did as much because of circumstance and chance as because of his own decisions. What we know about Plato today, nearly 2,400 years after his death, stems mostly from his numerous writings (some 650,000 words have been attributed to his hand, according to Plato historian Christopher Planeaux). Through what he mentions in his work, and through biographies of Plato written by his contemporaries, we have produced a fairly good picture of what Plato’s life was like. But this picture, like most old images, has been blurred by time. Some of what we know of Plato stems from writings that tried to make him seem legendary in stature, so it is important to try to weed out some of the more grandiose descrip- tions of his background. Other information comes from his letters, the only writ- ten work from Plato where he actually mentions events in his life. Unfortunately, there is some COPYRIGHTEDdispute as to whether all the letters attributed MATERIAL to Plato were even writ- ten by him, placing their accuracy in question.
    [Show full text]
  • The Failure of Athenian Democracy and the Reign of the Thirty Tyrants Lucas D
    Eastern Washington University EWU Digital Commons EWU Masters Thesis Collection Student Research and Creative Works 2013 Tyranny and terror: the failure of Athenian democracy and the reign of the Thirty Tyrants Lucas D. LeCaire Eastern Washington University Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.ewu.edu/theses Part of the Anthropology Commons Recommended Citation LeCaire, Lucas D., "Tyranny and terror: the failure of Athenian democracy and the reign of the Thirty Tyrants" (2013). EWU Masters Thesis Collection. 179. http://dc.ewu.edu/theses/179 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Research and Creative Works at EWU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in EWU Masters Thesis Collection by an authorized administrator of EWU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TYRANNY AND TERROR: THE FAILURE OF ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY AND THE REIGN OF THE THIRTY TYRANTS A Thesis Presented to Eastern Washington University Cheney, WA In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts By Lucas D. LeCaire Spring 2013 THESIS OF LUCAS D. LECAIRE APPROVED BY _________________________________________________ Date_____ Carol Thomas, GRADUATE STUDY COMMITTEE __________________________________________________ Date_____ Julia Smith, GRADUATE STUDY COMMITTEE MASTER’S THESIS In presenting this thesis in partial fulfillment of the requirements for a master’s degree at Eastern Washington University, I agree that the JFK Library shall make copies freely available for inspection. I further agree that copying of this project in whole or in part is allowable only for scholarly purposes. It is understood, however, that any copying or publication of this thesis for commercial purposes, or for financial gain, shall not be allowed without my written permission.
    [Show full text]